SlideShare una empresa de Scribd logo
1 de 29
Descargar para leer sin conexión
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to
Evaluating Business Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett, Esquire
Author Note
Adjunct Professor for Masters Business Administration Program, Graduate and Professional
Studies, Averett University, Danville, VA (MCB Quantico Campus).
Correspondence regarding this manuscript should be addressed to Craig D. Barrett. Email:
cbarrett@averett.edu or regular mail at 15660 William Bayliss Court, Woodbridge VA 22191.
The author can also be reached on cell phone at 703-409-6808.
CONTENTS
Introduction: The Purpose of Ethics…………….………….……….…………………………………..p. 3
The Difficulty with Business Ethics…………………………………………….………...............….…p. 4
Introduction of the Procedural and Substantive Challenge…………………….…………..….p. 4
Procedural Problem with the Application of Kantian Ethics……………………...…...….…….…...…p. 6
Organizational Ethics vs. Individual Ethical Theory………………………....…………....…..p. 6
The Challenge of Directly Applying Kant’s Ethics…….………………….……..............….…p. 6
Overcoming the Challenge…………………………………………….……….………..……..p. 8
The Substantive Problem: Applicability of Categorical Imperative……………………………..…….p. 10
Categorical Imperative: Act Only on Maxims that can be Willed as a Universal Law……….p. 11
Categorical Imperative: Treat Humanity as Ends……………………………….……………p. 15
Stakeholder Theory: Response to the Substantive Challenge…..……………………….…….…….…p. 16
What Stakeholder Theory Must Accomplish……………………………………….………….p. 16
Distributive Justice and Social Contract Theory: Broader Theoretical Considerations to Provide
A Normative Basis to Stakeholder Theory………………...…………………………………..p. 17
Concluding Thoughts: A Moral Conception of Business Decisions……………..…..………………..p. 22
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
2
Abstract
When we speak of ethics, we think of a set of rules or principles that guide our
actions. Our basic understanding leads us to believe that ethical principles ought to be
followed by everyone under similar circumstances. Said rules or principles would lose
their utility as a guide if it were the case they apply only to certain individuals while others
are unreasonably exempt from the duty to act (or to refrain from acting) in a particular
way. Equally problematic is when given two identical circumstances—all things being
equal—the obligation holds only in one situation and not the other. The issue at hand is
whether we can hold corporations to the same ethical standards to which we hold
individual persons, employing the same ethical analysis to determine the blameworthiness
of business entities. Such a determination serves as the basis for Business Ethics.
However, business entities are dissimilar from persons in very fundamental ways which
calls into question our method of morally judging business entities and thus the notion of
Business Ethics. These fundamental differences cannot be ignored and warrants further
analysis if we are to do justice to any discussion that attempts to determine what in fact
business ethics is and whether such a notion is even coherent. The following paper will
identify and explore the paradoxical tension between the notion of “business” and “ethics”
when viewed through a Kantian lens and will aim to reconcile that tension by appealing to a
version of stakeholder theory. Thus, we can make sense of a normative ethical theory that
serves to guide business practice.
Keywords: Stakeholder theory, Ethics, Kant, Kantian, Business Ethics, categorical
imperative.
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
3
1. Introduction: The Purpose of Ethics
Before beginning an analysis on the coherency of “business ethics”, it is important to
understand the general purpose of ethics. Such an understanding requires a firm grasp of the
assumptions that are at work in our ethical considerations. First, we assume there are actors,
organized socially, whose actions have an effect on others (in that social setting) either for better
or for worse. These actors realize that it is advantageous for them to organize into groups
because there is a higher probability of success for them to operate through mutual cooperation
than it would were one to attempt to succeed at life on their own. Thus these actors operate
within a social setting marked by a set of complicated relationships, connecting one person to
another.1
It is in one’s best interest—one might reason—to operate within this social setting or
well-organized society than it is to go at it alone. As a result, it is in one’s best interest to work
in such a way that would contribute to the sustainability of this well organized society of mutual
cooperation. This leads to the second assumption: these actors have a tendency to act in
accordance with their self-interest.2
This motivation by self-interest has as its direct object some
“good” that is —for some reason or another—relatively difficult to come by or is characterized
by relative scarcity. Because these actors are rational and motivated by their self-interest, they
naturally desire more of a “good” than less for themselves; and, securing more of this “good”,
which is the object of their interest, will invariably breed conflict with others seeking to secure
the same good for themselves due to its relative scarcity. As Rawls explains, “there is conflict of
1
Borrowing from Rawls, central to this discussion of ethics is the role of social institutions and individuals’ position in society. That is, moral
considerations independent of society and social institutions however basic or complex may not be possible, for human existence outside society
does not exist. As Rawls explains, “the major social institutions define men’s rights and duties and influences their life prospects, what they can
expect to be and how well they can hope to do.” (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 7) Thus a coherent discussion of ethics must assume the complex
relationship we have in a social setting.
2
This is not to discount the occurrence of altruistic behavior or to suggest that it is somehow irrational when one acts altruistically. On the
contrary, one might sacrifice one’s self or prioritize the interest of someone else over their own in an attempt to materialize a much more
important overarching interest: a parent might sacrifice herself for the protection of a child in an attempt to perpetuate the species, or an activist
might sacrifice themselves in the name of a greater political cause for example. These instances of altruism do not gainsay the claim that rational
beings are beings that act in a manner that is consistent with of preserving their self-interests (however defined) but are consistent with self
interested pursuits.
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
4
interests since persons are not indifferent as to how the greater benefits produced by their
collaboration are distributed, for in order to pursue their ends they each prefer a larger to a lesser
share.” (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 4.) Thus there becomes a need for ethical principles that
can regulate the interaction between members of society with regards to the fair distribution of
the goods available, recognizing and protecting the respective rights of citizens. Such ethical
principles support the notion of justice and fairness, which are central in the preservation of a
well-ordered society. The question that remains: where does an artificially formed entity such as
a corporation fit into all of this? And how do we define its obligations and duties in ethical
terms? The difficulty of this inquiry, however, should not be underestimated. Nevertheless it is
a challenge I will undertake in the discussion that follows. In an attempt to get a grasp on the
notion of “business ethics”, I will examine stakeholder theory through a Kantian lens with a
reliance on the social contract theory.
2. The Difficulty with Business Ethics
There is generally some consensus as to what constitutes ethical behavior as it relates to
individual rational beings, i.e., people. For example, we basically agree that lying, breaking
promises because keeping said promise no longer benefits us, or using people for our own
personal gain are all morally frowned upon. However, such consensus often fails to carry over
when we attempt to define the ethical behavior of a corporation or define what constitutes
business ethics. In business, creative advertising may be called “lying”; an economic efficient
breach of a contract might be called “breaking of a promise”; and, the purpose of business, which
is to generate profit, might in effect treat people as a means toward that end. Nevertheless, the
aforementioned are acceptable business practices. The difficulty of defining the sort of behavior
that ought to be undertaken by a corporation—beyond mere compliance with established laws—
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
5
is one often taken for granted and often ignored when we engage in a discussion regarding
“business ethics.” For if “ethics” suggests a normative theory that guides action, what exactly
are we saying a business “ought” to do under certain circumstances when it involves the interests
of others? Whose interests is a corporation responsible for protecting, and why? Concepts such
as duty, moral agency, and categorical imperative are all familiar terms in a discussion about the
moral ethics of individual rational beings. However, without rigorous examination of the
appropriate application of those terms, within the context of “business ethics”, such concepts
may lose their coherency in our attempt to determine the acceptable behavior of business entities.
2.1. Introduction of the Procedural and Substantive Challenge
There are two fundamental questions we must consider. First, can (or must) we consider
a business as a moral agent in order for it to have moral obligations or duties in the first place? If
moral obligations are dependent upon the presence of moral agency, we must then answer the
question of what constitutes a moral agent and whether a business in fact possesses the
characteristics required to constitute it as a moral agent as such. Arguably, if we fail to
constitute the corporation as a moral agent, then any notion of moral obligation assumed by a
non-moral agent becomes nonsense—and, equally perplexing would be this notion of “business
ethics.” For how could there be a field of ethics for entities that are non-moral agents? Second,
even if we can assume a corporation has ethical obligations, how can we define the duty of a
corporation, and can we effectively apply Kant’s categorical imperative in this instance? These
two questions, respectively, imply a procedural and substantive challenge that must be
considered when determining the duty of a corporation. The procedural question pertains to
whether a business is one to which the categorical imperative is appropriately assigned in the
first place—i.e., is it proper to treat a corporation as a moral agent; and, the substantive question
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
6
examines whether the categorical imperative can serve as an effective guide for normal business
practices.
Kant “believed that reason provided the basis for the categorical imperative, thus the
categorical imperatives of morality were requirements of reason.” (Bowie, “A Kantian
Approach,” p. 2.) The categorical imperative, although it captures the key feature of individual
morality, does not apply as neatly to a corporation. A corporation’s inability to “reason”
presents some difficulty in supporting the position that a corporation is subject to the categorical
imperative in the first place. I will take on this procedural question in the next section. Second, I
will then address the more substantive challenges of the categorical imperative as it applies to
corporate responsibility. Finally, I will appeal to stakeholder theory from a social contract
perspective to make sense of a Kantian approach to business ethics. The purpose of this paper is
to bridge the gap between (1) business ethics as we may think it applies to corporations and (2)
our normal understanding of Kantian ethics as it applies to the individual morality of persons.
Because corporations are made up of people, our first instincts are to hold businesses
accountable for moral actions using similar reasons we use to hold people accountable.
However, as I will explain later, this reasoning is flawed and thus will not do. It is my intention
to make sense of business ethics, grounded in Kantian ethics, in such a way that is consistent
with our intuitions. Thus we might properly evaluate the actions of a corporation as it operates
under real life market conditions.
3. Procedural Problem with the Application of Kantian Ethics: Moral Agency and the
Assignment of Moral Obligation
3.1. Organizational Ethics vs. Individual Moral Theory
There is a distinction that ought to be recognized between organizational ethics and
individual moral theory. Too often in our discussion of business ethics the two obvious distinct
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
7
fields are confounded, leading to strange and often counter-intuitive claims as to what a business
organization ought to do when acting in its capacity as a corporate entity and considering its
place in society. Despite the recognition of the corporation as a legal “person’, an ethical theory
centered around the actions of business entities cannot be modeled perfectly after a Kantian
theory of ethics, as that theory was intended to apply specifically to rational beings, i.e., humans.
Although there are some parallels between what we perceive to be the responsibilities of
corporations and the moral responsibilities of humans—i.e., ideas such as fairness, justice, duty,
frequently appear in discussions of both theories—the concept of “humans” as a subject of ethics
is not interchangeable with the concept of “business entities.” Thus we cannot expect to
establish a singular ethical theory for these two distinct concepts that can provide univocal
guidance for both. Humans and corporation are simply not the same type of being. Rather, a
custom ethical theory for corporations must be constructed from the bottom up rather than
simply adding it as an addendum to the moral theory we hold sound for human beings.
Stakeholder theory is one such theory as will be discussed. Although, some Kantian concepts
may reappear in the context of business ethics, its implications are vastly different than those
considered in the context of (Kantian) moral theory regarding individual persons. Such
differences cannot simply be ignored; and, although a Kantian approach is possible when
understanding the obligations of corporations, some issues arise when directly applying Kant’s
ethics to corporations outside the stakeholder theory framework.
3.2. The Challenge of Directly Applying of Kant’s Ethics
For Kant, autonomy and rationality are necessary for moral agency. Furthermore, in order
for there to be a moral obligation, there must be a moral agent (i.e., a rational being) to whom the
obligation attaches. To elucidate this point, consider for example animal rights activists who
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
8
argue that humans have a duty not to mistreat animals based on our status as rational beings.
Thus, we have a duty to refrain from actions that might be considered cruel to animals; however,
no such duty exists for animals. We do not, for example, hold a lion morally accountable for
mauling its trainer or for injuring other animals. Because animals lack rationality, they are not
considered moral agents to which we could assign blamed. Christine Korsgaard in her article
“Personhood, Animals, and the Law” explains that the basis of rationality is defined by
“normative self-governance.” This is the capacity to be governed by thoughts about what you
ought to do or believe. (Korsgaard, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law,” p. 26) In the
empiricist tradition of Hume and Locke it was common to attribute to human beings alone the
capacity to form what is called second-ordered attitudes, which is the basis for normative self-
governance. (Korsgaard, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law,” p. 26) These are attitudes
towards our own desires and serve as the basis for regulating our actions in accordance with our
understanding of what is “right”, thus not giving in to hedonistic desires without regard to moral
consequences: “Though one may desire to do something, I may disapprove of that desire and
reject its influence over me.” (Korsgaard, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law,” p. 26.) Second-
tier attitudes, Korsgaard explains, are what make humans subject to the “ought.” If this is the
case, a corporation—like an animal—can never be subjected to the “ought” since the
corporation—properly speaking—does not have desires and cannot engage in the act of
“normative self-governance.” Thus, the question of moral obligation, which is the subject of
ethics, entails the question of what constitutes moral agency. It therefore seems if we cannot
constitute a “being” as a moral agent, a discussion of ethics that might govern the actions of said
being would be incoherent. This is the procedural problem.
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
9
Though it is true the corporation as a whole has as its constitutive parts “real”
autonomous rational beings—i.e., people—that alone cannot not support the position that a
corporation is a moral agent, subject to the same categorical imperatives like promise-keeping
for example. This would be an appeal to an informal fallacy, which is the fallacy of
composition. This fallacious inference improperly attributes characteristic of the parts of a whole
to the collective whole. This simple logical point makes it difficult to move from a Kantian
argument we hold sound for individuals to an ethical argument regarding corporations grounded
in a similar Kantian theory. For example, just because all of the parts of a machine are made in
Germany does not necessarily mean the machine comprised of those parts is made in Germany
as well. For it could be the case the parts were shipped to the United States and the machine was
assembled there. Thus, a corporation made of moral agents does not make the corporation, as
such, a moral agent as well. However, it does not seem correct to end the story there, for we do
say “a company ought to do such and such”, or “this company is responsible for thus and so
harm.” And we feel justified in doing so. Unless we are willing to concede that such “moral-
language” as it relates to corporations is no more than a misnomer—that is to say, it is no more
than an improper application of language to corporate behavior—we will need to do more work
here. This incongruence between the corporate collective and the individual moral agent is not
the undoing of business ethics. However some work must be done to overcome this challenge.
3.3. Overcoming the Challenge
The question then is whether a corporation is the sort of entity that can be the subject of
moral duty. This then leads us to the following question: is moral agency a necessary
precondition for a corporation in order for it to have moral responsibilities thus making sense of
the notion of business ethics? As stated, if moral agency is based on rationality, moral
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
10
responsibility is not possible. However, we may still be able to make a case for Business
Ethics. In Margaret Gilbert's article “Who's to blame? Collective Moral Responsibility and Its
Implications for Group Members,” she explores the question of blameworthiness as it pertains to
individuals and the collective group to which the individuals are said to belong. Since the
corporate entity only exists as an entity made up of people, the actions of the corporate entity
necessarily are actions carried out by people. Gilbert explores the asymmetry between the flow
of blameworthiness to individuals (from the group) as compared to the flow of blame to the
collective (from individuals) as it pertains to the same act. The example she provides is one
where we as humans assume responsibility for environmental pollution even though I as an
individual may not have specifically engaged in any activities causally connected to the pollution
of the environment. In such a case, the collective (not the individual) serves as a distinct subject
to our moral judgment. (Gilbert, “Who's to Blame,” p. 102) Here, although what is true for the
whole is not necessarily true of its constitutive parts, blame still attaches to both entities. In the
business context, although Enron as a company may have been blameworthy for a variety of
corporate malfeasance deserving of sanctions, the manager of research and development of
Enron may not be held personally responsible or viewed with the same approbation. However,
to the extent that the manager’s efforts are in support of the success of a corrupt company and is
identifiable with the company, she shoulders blame in that regard. Conversely, the bad acts of an
individual, whether CEO or line-worker, might be imputed to the organization. Thus, the
corporate collective is worthy of blame and deserving of punishment even if there was no
unanimous corporate endorsement of the bad act by the members of the collective group. This
pattern of the assignment of blame in the latter case is also present in our legal system of Agency
and Tort Law. The theory of Respondent Superior (“imputed liability”) in law endorses the
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
11
rendering of liability to the corporation (the principal) for the specific actions of the individual
employee (acting as agents of the corporation) in instances when the company stands to benefit
from the wrong committed or if the wrong committed was within the scope of their employment
in support of the collective objective. “Under the doctrine of respondent superior…the principal
may be held liable for an agent’s tort even though the principal was blameless.” (Posner,
Economic Analysis of Law, p. 114) Thus blame is assigned to the collective (or corporation)
even though the collective did not formally endorse the “bad act” in question.
Even though the status of moral agency does not go from individual member to corporate
collective—because of the requirement of rationality—does not prevent one from passing
judgment on the corporate entity under a theory of imputed liability. It is uncontroverted that a
corporation is made up of individual autonomous beings. It cannot exist otherwise. However,
although we may not be able to claim the corporate collective is a moral agent as such, if an act
is wrong and causes harm as a result, said act is wrong whether attributed to an individual
member of the collective or attributable to the entire organization. Said act may be attributed to
the corporation because the individual actor was acting at the behest of the corporate entity or
because the corporate entity benefitted from the commission of the “bad act.” In this way, the
corporate collective “owns” the actions and may therefore be judged accordingly—though not in
exactly the same way we morally judge individual actors. Thus by focusing on the act itself, and
not necessarily on the constitution of the “actor” (as moral agent) we can make coherent moral
judgments about business practices. Granted, because of the absence of rationality, this is not a
perfect “Kantian” judgment of business practices so to speak. However, even if Kant’s theory
does not perfectly apply to corporate practices, “he still has a lot to offer the business ethicist”.
(Bowie “A Kantian Approach,” p. 12) For as stated earlier, we do—as common practice—pass
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
12
moral judgment on corporate activity. However, the fact that we engage in a particular act
cannot serve as a normative basis or as justification for that act. Description of a practice alone
is not sufficient to serve as justification of this practice, as you cannot obtain an “ought” from an
“is”. This is in philosophy a well-known error in reasoning called the naturalistic fallacy.
However, so long as the corporate entity is considered the “but-for” cause of the complained-of
act in question, even if the actions are executed by the employees for corporation’s benefit, we
are justified under the Tort Law theory of respondent superior (see, supra p. 8) in ascribing
blame to that corporation. If we accept the proposition that a corporation can be blameworthy as
argued above, then we can argue they possess duties: For the assignment of blame properly
occurs when one fails to carryout one’s duties as assigned. However, how might we define the
duties of corporate entities? This brings us to the substantive issue and is one that will be
addressed in a discussion of stakeholder theory. These are taken up in greater detail in the
sections that follows, first examining the substantive issue in greater detail.
4. The Substantive Problem: Applicability of Categorical Imperative To Corporations
A summary of Kant’s categorical imperative might be summarized as follows:
1. Act only on maxims which you can will to be universal laws of nature;
2. Always treat the humanity in a person as an end and never as a means only;
3. So act as if you were a member of an ideal kingdom of ends in which you were both
subject and sovereign at the same time
In his article “The Kantian Approach to Business Ethics,” Bowie explains, “Kant’s ethics
is an ethics of duty rather than an ethics of consequences.” The ethical person, he continues, “is
the person who acts from the right intentions.” (Bowie, “A Kantian Approach to Business
Ethics,” p. 2) Such intentions must not be concerned with the consequences of a particular act
but must instead focus on the duty (or obligation) that give rise to the act in the first place. Thus,
Kant’s ethics has as its fundamental principle the “categorical imperative”, which provides the
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
13
outline for ethical duty. “The categorical imperative,” Bowie continues, “is not irrelevant in the
world of business. If a maxim for an action when universalized is self-defeating, then the
contemplated action is not ethical. That is Kant’s conceptual point.” (Bowie, The Kantian
Approach, p. 5)
4.1 Categorical Imperative: Act Only on Maxims that can be Willed as a Universal Law
However despite Bowie’s claim of the categorical imperative’s applicability in the world
of business, there are some challenges in a applying the categorical imperative to business
organizations. Consider the applicability of (1) “act only on maxims which you can will to be
universal laws of nature.” On Kantian grounds, Bowie argues, a corporation must act only on
maxims it can will to be universal business law without yielding a contradiction in its practice or
yield a “self-defeating” end. From an individual perspective it is easy to see how this might play
out: consider one who engages in the act of stealing in order to secure more resources for herself.
She could not universalize this act of stealing as a universal law without endorsing the act of
stealing in general, to include the stealing of resources from herself; and, for her to endorse the
act of “being stolen from” contradicts (or defeats) her original purpose to secure more resources
for herself—which was the motivation for her to steal in the first place. Thus the act of stealing
in this case cannot be morally endorsed according to the categorical imperative. In this way
Bowie argues, “when enough people behave immorally…certain business practices…become
impossible.” (Bowie, “A The Kantian Approach,” p.5.)
What is problematic about Bowie’s assessment here is (1) corporations are not—strictly
speaking—individual persons (an issue addressed in the previous section); and, (2) although the
act of going back on promises, for example, may be an act that cannot be universalized as
universal law for persons, the efficient breach or renegotiation of a contract is a common
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
14
acceptable business practice. A contract represents a legally enforceable promise; however,
when its terms are no longer advantageous to a party of the contract, it is not uncommon for a
business to renegotiate or refuse to honor those terms. Bowie acknowledges this point in his
article explaining, “[executives] point out that, in the real world, contracts are often
‘renegotiated’ and yet business people still engage in contract making.” To this, Bowie simply
replies: “These executives raise an interesting point.” (Bowie, “A Kant Approach,” p. 4) Bowie
then cites to some other “real world” business examples that support Kant’s point but never
directly addresses the issue of “broken-promises” in business contracts. I contend this is more
than just “an interesting point” and represents a substantive issue that merits further examination,
for it calls into question the applicability of the categorical imperative to very common business
practices.
Consistent with the law (and supported by one legal economic theory) it is a common
practice for companies to engage in what is called an efficient breach. According to Black’s
Law Dictionary, efficient breach theory is a modern contract theory that endorses the breaching
of a contract and payment of damages to the non-breaching party if doing so would be more
“economically efficient [than performing under the contract]...[And this] occurs when the
breaching party will still profit after compensating the other for its ‘expectation interest.’”
(Black’s Law Dictionary, Abridged Sixth Edition.) It should be noted, however, “this theory is
not well accepted.” (Id.) However, the point here is not to argue the merits of the “efficient
breach theory”; rather, the point is to demonstrate how the categorical imperative of “promise
keeping” may not be “self-defeating” if violated in the context of normal business practices. As
Richard Posner explains,
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
15
In some cases a party is tempted to break his contract simply because his profit from
breach would exceed his profit from completion of the contract. If it would also exceed
the expected profit to the other party from completion of the contract, and if damages are
limited to the loss of that profit, there will be an incentive to commit a breach.” (Posner,
Economic Analysis of Law, p. 120.)
To elucidate this point, consider the following example (inspired by a well-known illustration by
Judge Posner): assume Company A contracts to deliver 100 widgets to Company B for $1 per
widget. Company B will in turn use these 100 widgets to create 25 machine gadgets it plans to
sell in the market place for $10 per gadget (10 x $25= $250 in gross sales) thus realizing a profit
of $150 before assembly cost, shipping, warehousing etc. (i.e., $250 cash after sales -$100 the
cost of the widgets = $150 before-cost earnings). Assuming said costs to Company B are $2.50
per gadget (2.50 x 25=$62.50), Company B expects to yield a net profit of $87.50 ($150-
62.50=$87.50) if Company A performs per the contract. Assume further that instead of selling
the 100 widgets to Company B as contracted, Company A sells the widgets to Company C who
finds itself in desperate need of the widgets in question and is willing to pay double the market
value at $2 per widget ($2 x 100=$200). Company A, not wanting to pass up on an arbitrage
opportunity, decides to breach the contract it has with Company B, paying Company B damages
in the amount of $88 dollars—in effect purchasing the “right” to keep the widgets. The dollar
amount in damages Company B receives is $0.50 more than Company B would have realized
had the contract been honored. Additionally, Company A as a result of the breach realizes a gain
of $112.00 (after damages paid to Company B), $12 more than the gains Company A would have
realized had it honored the contract in the first place. In such an example, all players in the
market, Company A, B, and C fair better than they would had the parties performed in
accordance with the original contract. Thus, breaching the contract is Pareto Superior to
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
16
honoring the contract. Here market efficiency, dictates what is in the best interest of all parties
involved and is thus the action that ought to be taken.
This idea was never more clearly expressed than in Ronald Coase’s “The Problem of
Social Cost.” The Coase Theorem is concerned with resolving the conflict between competing
activities. The conflict arises when the pursuit for profits for one activity threatens the gains of a
competing activity. Here the parties enjoy legal entitlements with regards to their respective
activities for which a market valuation is attached. The point of conflict is as yet unresolved;
and, the market is capable of determining the practical outcome of the dispute based on the
market value of each activity no matter what legal resolution is proposed at the point of conflict.
The basic thesis of Coase is that efficient market theory can better resolve the disputes between
two parties where “rights” and “obligations” are in question. Rather than appealing to legal
institutions to adjudicate what is “right”, “fair”, or “just”, the wider normative application of the
Coase Theorem asserts that legal liability ought to be determined based upon economic
efficiency. And rather than imposing punishment upon the “wrong-doing” company, that
company might simply be required to pay “rents” to the suffering party in an amount dictated by
the market. In such a case, the (complained-of) act must generate more value through its activity
than the value created if the company were to refrain from that activity. Here this value creates a
larger “pie” to be shared by all interested parties who each in effect will enjoy a larger share.
Because the administration of justice comes with associated transaction costs, the size of the
“pie” is substantially reduced when justice is sought through the court system.3
This “transaction
3
In the section on administrative cost, Kaplow and Shavell’s explanation illustrates, in my view, how transaction cost associated with the legal
system lead to market inefficiency. They explain, “The administrative costs of the liability system are the legal and other costs (notably the time
of litigants) involved in bringing suit and resolving it through settlement or trial. These costs are substantial; a number of estimates suggest that,
on average, administrative costs of a dollar or more are incurred for every dollar that a victim receives through the liability system. In contrast,
the administrative cost of receiving a dollar through the insurance system is often below fifteen cents.” (Kaplow and Shavell, Economic Analysis
of Law, p. 1673)
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
17
cost” reduces the value available for all parties to share—or so a proponent of the Coase
Theorem might argue.4
Thus the more valuable harm-causing activity—absent transaction cost
however defined—might be able to buyout and induce the less valuable activity to forgo its legal
rights. The more valuable harm-causing activity is now free to pursue its activity so long as the
value it generates is sufficient to conduct the buyout and still retain a gain. Thus, the Coase
Theorem posits that the determination of legal liability (and perhaps also moral responsibility)
becomes moot where efficient markets are concerned. In pursuit of establishing economic
efficiency, “[l]aw and economics derive the guiding principle that the courts should mimic the
markets: the courts should determine issues of liability on the basis of what the market in ideal
conditions would determine as the efficient outcome of the dispute between parties.” (Halpin,
Disproving The Coase Theorem? p. 322.) Thus an efficient breach of a promise—from a
business perspective—if adopted as a universal law does not “defeat” the activity of contract-
making but may fall under the vast array of business practices supported by market efficiency.
Such practices do not defeat contracting between businesses, but facilitates its negotiation in a
free market.
4.2. Second Categorical Imperative: Treat Humanity as Ends
The second representation of the categorical imperative requires that we treat humanity as an
end and never as a means. Such an idea of the categorical imperative may be difficult to apply
in that a corporation is an artificially created entity formed for the sole purpose of generating a
profit.5
If we accept profit seeking as the function of a business, how can a corporation ever
4
It should be noted that in my paper to which I cite, supra at p.13, I argue against this position. In that discussion, I contend that we cannot
ignore the value that society places in the act of formally assigning blame to the harm-causing party. This assignment of blame can only be
acquired through the institution of laws, which necessarily comes with an associated transactional cost. Thus, our desire to hold wrong-doers
accountable for their actions cannot always be replaced with cash compensation—however, oftentimes it can.
5
Obviously to the extent that such a pursuit runs afoul established laws, such actions ought to be avoid; however, this—arguably—is because
purposefully violating the law threatens the corporation’s profits and because violation of the law might lead to costly fines or substantial
diminution of market value that could lead to the corporation’s ultimate undoing.
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
18
avoid treating beings—whether employees, customers, investors or suppliers—other than as a
means to that end? This then violates Kant’s categorical imperative if we accept Bowie’s
position that “it is a central tenant of Kant’s moral philosophy that an action is only truly moral if
it is morally motivated.” (Bowie, Kantian Approach, p.11). Thus a theory on business ethics
must do more than speak to the instrumental function of managerial decisions. That is, it must
establish something more than “a framework for examining the connections…between the
[ethical] practice of…management and the achievement of various corporate performance
goals.” (Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 67. Here defining “instrumental
function” of morality.) This would be no more than engaging in a moral act because it is
instrumental or a means in achieving various ends or performance goals. Consider, for example,
a company that produces defective cars that might cause the death of others. A decision by
management to recall these cars may only be because in the short-run it restores the confidence
of the consumer in the company’s brand. Thus in the long-run, the corrective action preserves
the company’s market share amongst those customers—promising the company’s continued
success—serving as an instrumental basis for a manager’s decision. Although the decision
considers the customer and perhaps the community writ large, there is still a component of that
decision that seems to casts a lascivious eye toward profit preservation. However, this is not a
desirable start for an ethical theory. On Kantian grounds, “it is the intention behind an action
rather than its consequences that make an action good…For Kant if a merchant is honest so as to
earn a good reputation, these acts of being honest are not genuinely moral.” (Bowie, A Kantian
Approach to Business Ethics, p. 1) In such a case—a decision made on purely instrumental
grounds cannot be said to be “ethical” because people are not treated as ends in themselves but
merely as means to a more self-serving corporate objective. However, it seems odd that we
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
19
should expect an artificially created entity formed for the purpose of creating profit to have an
obligation to materialize some end that does not preserve profit. Thus claiming there exists a
branch of ethics that imposes such an obligation on businesses may seem equally odd.
Donaldson and Preston explain that although descriptive and instrumental justifications “are
significant aspects of the of stakeholder theory, its fundamental basis is normative.” (Donaldson
and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 67) In this way, Donaldson and Preston concede there is a
need for the theory to have some “normative bite” if it is to have any ethical significance. As
such, it is imperative (no pun intended) that our justifications of corporate activity go beyond
profit generation (which is an instrumental justification) if we are to establish a normative basis
in support of our moral judgments in the context of business ethics.
5. Stakeholder Theory: Response to the Substantive Challenge
5.1. What Stakeholder Theory Must Accomplish
In their article “The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation: Concepts, Evidence, and
Implication,” Thomas Donaldson and Lee Preston argue that managers can apply stakeholder
theory to guide their decisions. They “believe that the ultimate justification for the stakeholder
theory is to be found in its normative base.” Donaldson and Lee conclude that the alternative to
stakeholder theory, which is a style of management centered on shareowner interests, is
untenable. (Donaldson and Preston p. 88.) “Stakeholders are persons or groups with legitimate
interests in procedural and/or substantive aspects of corporate activity and are identified by their
interest in the corporation, whether the corporation has any corresponding functional interest in
them.” (Donaldson and Preston, p. 67 emphasis in the original.) However, even if we concede
that developing a normative theory around the interest of shareowners is in fact “untenable,” how
do we justify imposing an “ought” on business organizations that requires it to take into
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
20
consideration the interests of these “other” persons? Consider for example the following: the
adoption of certain technology may increase efficiency in the production of the product the
company sells, however, this technology results in the elimination of hundreds of jobs and the
termination of hundreds of employees; or the outsourcing of jobs increases a company’s profit
margin but also devastates the economy of the adjacent community as a result of the decreased
economic activity in that area; or finally, the carbon emissions of a corporation’s industrial plant
is central to its production and profit but reduces the quality of air for future generations. Why
should a company, in any of these instances, forgo immediate profit to preserve jobs for
employees, or help to maintain the economic stability of the adjacent community, or preserve the
environment for future generations? Consequently we must reveal what Donaldson and Preston
allude to as the “normative base” of the stakeholder theory. It is this ”normative base” that is
doing most of the theoretical heavy lifting here. Second, who qualifies as a “legitimate”
stakeholder in the first place, and how must we consider and adjudicate their varied and
sometimes conflicting interests? To the latter question, the solution starts with how we must
define “interest.” If it is the case that the type of “interest” determines whether one has a
legitimate stake, which is at the root of stakeholder theory, it becomes necessary to delineate
with some clarity what and how interests are considered legitimate. To accomplish this, we must
appeal to a theory of property rights. Here we argue that stakeholders have entitlements and
rights in the value created by the corporation because of the relationship corporations have with
them and society writ large. Then it must be determined how that value can be fairly distributed
amongst those with these legitimate claims.
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
21
5.2. Distributive Justice and Social Contract Theory: Broader Theoretical Considerations to
Provide A Normative Basis to Stakeholder Theory
“Even the most enlightened corporations are almost always justified in part on the
grounds that such actions are profitable, it appears [then] that even the best actions of the best
corporations are not truly moral.” (Bowie Kantian Theory p. 12.) Enhancing profit, arguably,
represents the “self interest” of the company and is the purpose of the corporation’s existence,
for the corporation was formed for that purpose. Although other interests may be considered, the
self-interest of the corporation (i.e., profit) may seem to subordinate all other interests (not
leading to profit.) Milton Friedman argues “the whole justification for permitting the corporate
executive to be selected by stockholders is that the executive is an agent serving the interest of
the principal. This justification disappears when the corporate executive imposes taxes and
spends the proceeds for social purposes.” (Friedman, The Social Responsibility of Business, p.
4, emphasis added.) Here Friedman is incorrect: the justification for a manager’s decision does
not necessarily “disappear” simply because it serves the interest of other interested parties and
results in some social good. Friedman’s point fails to consider the duty a manager may have as
agent of multiple principals, i.e., the various stakeholders. Consider stakeholder theory as
outlined above which suggests a business, specifically managers, should consider the interests of
not only shareowners—whose primary interest is profit—but also to others who too have a
“stake” in the success of the firm or who are somehow otherwise impacted by the activities of
the firm. Under stakeholder theory, the decisions made by management are not always “profit-
driven” and must consider the respect for and dignity of other stakeholders, treating them as ends
in themselves and not merely as means. This represents the notion of “the what” with regards to
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
22
the actions managers should take, but we must determine “how” these interests ought to be
managed. Stakeholder theory thus requires support in order to succeed as a normative theory.
Although stakeholder theory advocates argue that mangers ought to shift their focus from
a shareowner centric style of management to a stakeholder style of management, this theory must
still consider the interest of shareowners, though not as a primary focus. The theory expands the
category of persons whose interests ought to be protected by managerial decisions. Notably, in
order for a theory to fail to qualify as a stakeholder theory, such a theory would “have to
specifically instruct managers to ignore the interests, values, and rights of one or more category
of persons…” (Hasnas p. 50); thus stakeholder theory requires a manager to consider the interest
of (all) those who might have a stake in the company’s success and not just the interest of the
shareowner. However, the theory is vulnerable to criticism of it failing to be a normative theory.
According to one such criticism, Hasnas explains, “the injunction that business ‘pay attention’ to
stakeholders does not mark out any definite normative theory.” (Id. p. 50.) Any managerial
decision would be justifiable since every act would be in the interest of some stakeholder; and, if
everyone is a legitimate stakeholder, stakeholder theory would endorse any act on the basis that
it furthers the interest of someone. There is no “definite normative theory” here; and, no
guidance, then, will be available under this theory. Thus there must be an appeal to another
theory that might guide us in prioritizing the interests of the various stakeholders we are now
considering.
To start, the “interests of all stakeholders are of intrinsic value. That is, each group of
stakeholders merit consideration for its own sake and not merely because of its ability to further
the interest of some other group, such as shareowners.” (Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder
Theory, p. 67) The for-profit corporation is an artificially created entity formed for the purpose
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
23
of creating value. Thus the appropriate question becomes simply: who has rights in the value
generated by the corporation? Thus persons acting in their capacity as managers are merely
agents of those whom might be identified as having legitimate property claims to that value. In
this way, the stakeholder theory is based on a much broader philosophical theory, supported by a
notion of distributive justice. More precisely, how ought the primary goods, i.e., profit,
generated by the corporation be distributed amongst existing parties who may have a legitimate
claim to the value created by the corporation? Stakeholder theory recognizes a right to the value
created by the company amongst those other than the shareowner. Such a notion can be
normatively based on the evolving theory of property rights. (Donaldson and Preston,
Stakeholder Theory, p. 83.) The irony in this view, as Donaldson and Preston point out, is that
“property rights” have most commonly been associated with shareowner’s interests. (See id. at
p. 83.) However, as Donaldson and Preston explains, the most persuasive view of property
rights is as a bundle of many rights and not the unlimited rights of one party. The rights and
entitlements of owners are merely part of the story here: because the adjudication of rights,
privileges, and obligations are done amongst human actors, we must also consider the plethora of
human rights and obligations based on our coexistence qua humans, a relationship which is far
more complicated than mere “property ownership” would suggest. There is a mutual
dependency we have on one another. As such, we must consider society—independent of the
individual property owner—even in the context of the ownership of specific property, for
without society and the preservation of its well-being, the “thing” which is the subject of
ownership and enjoyed by its owner would not exist in the first place. Thus not even a privately
owned track of land purchased with the hard-earned dollars of the owner should be used to
dispose of toxic nuclear waste. Or in the less extreme case, all property is subject to taxes
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
24
revenue, which is used for the public good. Here there is a feature of stakeholder theory that
provides a normative approach to business ethics: shareholders or owners or investors are not
the only ones entitled to the value created from trade, sales, production etc. Rather, an account
can be defended where other stakeholders are entitled to the residual gain on a notion of
distributive justice and a version of social contract theory.
From a social contract perspective, each stakeholder is not only essential to the
corporation’s ability to generate profit, but is also essential to the corporation’s very existence.
The corporation reaps the benefits from the mutual cooperation of those who work in society for
the mutual advantage of all members within that society; and, as a beneficiary of the advantage
created, the basic theory of social contract requires the corporation also to treat those participants
as ends rather than means to more self-serving ends. For without society’s participants, the self-
serving ends could not be realized in the first place. The notion of social contract theory coupled
with a theory of Kantian ethics and distributed justice is doing the philosophical “work” here,
grounding stakeholder theory as a normative one. Thus Donaldson and Preston are correct in
saying, “more formal normative justifications of stakeholder theory might be based on broad
theories of philosophical ethics, such as utilitarianism, or narrower “middle-level” theories
derived from the notion that a social contract exists between corporation and society.”
(Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 83.)
From a Kantian perspective it is not acceptable to give priority to some stakeholders’
interest simply because they out number other stakeholders as advocated by utilitarianism. A
corporation, then, may decide not to enhance corporate profit or shareowner gain if so doing fails
to treat stakeholders (other than shareowners) with dignity and respect. These other stakeholders
by virtue of their position in society, relationship to the corporation, and contribution to its
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
25
continued existence, arguably, possess a property interest in the corporate created value. Thus
those with a legitimate claim to the value created by the corporation must be treated with the
respect and dignity that would require the manager to consider their interest, treating them as
ends insofar as their existence is the necessary precondition upon which the existence of the
corporation rest. Thus when considering the “just” distribution of corporate-created value, every
stakeholder is entitled to their fair share for reasons that can be justified on Kantian grounds and
considering the special relationship developed between corporations and other entities in the
context of the social contract tradition. As a result, a fair distribution of corporate value may
appropriately reduce the value or profit for shareowners.
Thus the Stakeholder theory suggests that matters are more complicated: stakeholder
relationships are involved, and human beings are more complex than standard accounts assume.
All stakeholders must be treated as ends in themselves because each stakeholder is sine quo non
to the formation and continued existence of the corporate entity. In this way, we can evaluate the
behavior of the corporate entity in its treatment of the many stakeholders who have a property
stake in the value that a corporation creates because, in a sense, neither the corporation nor the
value it creates would exist but-for the existence of these stakeholders. Thus there is nothing
incoherent about a corporation—from an ethical standpoint—taking into consideration the stake
of say, employees, suppliers, or the adjacent community, eliminating profit generating behavior
that might adversely impact on those stakeholders. From a social contract theorist perspective,
without these stakeholders and—to be sure—without society writ large, the corporation itself
would not exist. From one perspective, it is not necessarily the case the corporation is forgoing
greater profit in the interest of, say, preserving a living wage for employees; rather, a portion of
the value generated by the corporation is returned to the population of persons, i.e., employees,
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
26
who make it possible for the company to generate value in the first place. Their role then must
be considered on moral grounds, as their contribution creates an entitlement and a right to the
value generated by the corporation. How that value is distributed might be determined on
Kantian grounds of justice and fairness, perhaps set in the Rawlsian tradition of Justice as
Fairness for example.6
6. Concluding Thoughts: A Moral Conception of Business Decisions
An action undertaken by a corporation that results in its inability to turn a profit may lead
to its inability to meet pay roll, cover invoices from suppliers, or pay overhead which enables the
corporation to bring their product or services to market. These inabilities may result in the
company’s failure and ultimate dissolution. A corporation’s failure can adversely affect its
employees who are now faced with unemployment, other businesses that rely on that
corporation’s economic role in society, and adversely impact customers who now no longer
receive products and services from the failed company. Conversely, decisions that may increase
profit can lead to the damage of the environment when shortcuts are taken, the exploitation of
low wageworkers, and the damaging of the economy through unfair business practices. When
corporations understand that they do not function independent of society, it becomes natural to
adopt a stakeholder approach; for like individuals, business entities can only realize their
objectives within the framework of the social cooperation for mutual advantage that
characterizes a well ordered society. Thus every decision made by a corporation should take into
account the interests of those who not only have a equity interest in the company, but also, those
whose existence makes it possible for the corporation to do business in the first place.
6
See John Rawls discussion of justice as fairness in his book A Theory of Justice.
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
27
One clear example of this is when Goldman Sachs used Credit Default Swaps to reduce
the risks inherent in the mortgage-backed securities it sold in the market place. The default
swaps were basically an “insurance policy” taken against the mortgage backed security in the
event the borrower failed to repay the underlying mortgage from which the mortgage security
derived.7
Goldman Sachs collected fees by packaging the mortgaged backed securities they sold
to investors which in turn created greater liquidity for the banks to originate loans for home
purchasing. Greater liquidity led to more available loans, which led to greater demand for
homes because more people now had access to mortgages. This greater demand for homes
artificial increased home value, which is a simple matter of supply and demand. In addition,
more loans led to more origination fees for (saving and loan) banks and led to more security
products such as mortgage securities for investors to purchase; and, thus this led to more fees for
investment banks such as Goldman Sachs. The moral issue is this: while Goldman sold these
securities to (and collected fees from) their clients, they also purchased these Debt Swaps
(insurance policies) against the very products they sold to their clients. Thus Goldman stood to
make money should borrowers fail to repay these mortgages; however, if and when these same
borrowers defaulted, Goldman’s clients who held these mortgage securities would lose money as
a result. Thus in essence, Goldman stood to make money on the failure of a product they sold to
their clients who would in the end lose millions.
On a phone conference, one top Goldman executive stated—and I am paraphrasing
here—“there is nothing wrong with conflicts of interests in business; rather, it is how you
manage these conflicts that is important to good business practices.” Here we have a case where
7
Technically, although credit default swaps function as an insurance policy, it is treated as a financial instrument rather than an insurance policy
subject to a variety of regulations. Arguably, the intention behind calling these products financial instruments titling them “credit default swaps”
or “credit default obligations” rather than “credit default insurance policies” was with the intentions of side-stepping the regulations imposed
upon insurance products: One such regulation requires that the entity ensuring the policy (in this case AIG) actually has the liquid cash to cover
the losses the policy is intended to protect the policy holder against.
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
28
Goldman engaged in actions that affected a variety of stakeholders all of whom were owed a
duty. They are as follows: (1) clients who were sold risky financial product; (2) shareholders,
who are entitled to —when legally possible—the minimization of risks of their capital invested
which prompted the purchase of the Default Swaps in this case; and, (3) society and the financial
system which was devastated due to the oversaturation of subprime-lending in the market,
facilitated by mortgage-backed securities sold by Goldman. Though there was nothing overtly
illegal about Goldman’s purchase of $2 billion in Default Swaps or their standing to gain from
their clients’ losses, an evaluation as to whether their actions were “right” can be effectively
determined by applying stakeholder theory as presented in the discussion above. One might
argue that in this case, sufficient consideration was not given to clients and the financial impact
on society writ large with an over emphasis on the interest of shareowners and profit. This
becomes increasingly more apparent when we consider the $183 billion of taxpayer dollars used
for the corporate bailout of insurance company giant AIG who owed Goldman approximately
$13 billion dollars. Thus in the end, Goldman was paid $13 billion from AIG who was bailed-
out by the collective earnings of members of the same society devastated by Goldman’s actions
that spawned the housing bubble in the first place.
This interdependency between corporation and society requires the corporate entity to
treat all these stakeholders as ends in themselves and not simply a means to leverage greater
profit (for the benefit of one of many stakeholders). Moreover, the claims to the value created by
the corporation are not the exclusive property interest of shareowners. Thus managers should
not limit their consideration to what is in the interest of shareowners and investors alone when
making decisions. A broader understanding of property rights includes a consideration of the
many and complex relationships between society’s participants to include its citizens as well as
Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business
Ethics.
Craig D. Barrett
29
corporate entities. This broader understanding of property rights requires one to consider the
claims and rights of other stakeholders and the obligation the corporation may have to them.
Thus decisions based on stakeholder theory, coupled with Kantian and social contract
consideration, provides a more comprehensive approach of what a corporation ought to do,
considering its place in society and the overall implications and impact of its actions. And
although such decisions may at times appear also to maximize profit, managers must have some
justification for those decisions beyond mere profit maximization.
References
1. Bowie, “A Kantian Approach to Business Ethics”, Ethical Issues in Business: a
philosophical approach. 7th
ed. New Jersey: Prentice Hall pp. 61-71
2. Bowie, “A Kantian Theory of Meaningful Work”
3. Coase, Ronald H., The Problem of Social Cost, (1960). The Journal of Law &
Economics, volume III, pp1-44.
4. Donaldson and Preston, “Stake holder Theory of the Corporations Concepts, Evidence,
and Implication,” The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Jan., 1995), pp.
65-91
5. Friedman, Milton, “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase Its Profits,”
(1970) The New York Times Magazine, September 13, 1970
6. Haplin, Andrew, “Disproving The Coase Theorem?” (2007) Economics and Philosophy,
23, pp321-341
7. Hasnus, John, “Whither Stake Holder Theory? A Guide for the Perplexed Revisited,”
(2012) Springer Science Business Media B.V.
8. Kosgaard Christine, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law”, Think Philosophy for
Everyone, Summer 2013, 25-32
9. Margeret Gilbert, “Who's to Blame? Collective Moral Responsibility and Its Implications
for Group Members” (2006) Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Blackwell Publishing, Inc.
10. Posner, Richard Economic Analysis of Law, Sixth Ed., Aspen Publishers (2007)
11. Rawls, John, Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press (1971)

Más contenido relacionado

La actualidad más candente

Towards a social action analysis of organizations
Towards a social action analysis of organizationsTowards a social action analysis of organizations
Towards a social action analysis of organizationsAmir Ghazinoori
 
personal and organizational values
personal and organizational valuespersonal and organizational values
personal and organizational valuesLolit Orlanda
 
Foundations of ethics
Foundations of ethicsFoundations of ethics
Foundations of ethicsAmr Sherif
 
Business ethics assignment
Business ethics assignmentBusiness ethics assignment
Business ethics assignmentRohan Naik
 
Moral Framework for Ethics
Moral Framework for EthicsMoral Framework for Ethics
Moral Framework for EthicsSinbad Konick
 
Ethical decision making in business
Ethical decision making in business Ethical decision making in business
Ethical decision making in business Souman Guha
 
Changing paradigms of corporate social responsibility
Changing paradigms of corporate social responsibilityChanging paradigms of corporate social responsibility
Changing paradigms of corporate social responsibilitySorab Sadri
 
Chapt 3 evaluating business ethics
Chapt 3   evaluating business ethicsChapt 3   evaluating business ethics
Chapt 3 evaluating business ethicsLùn Tê Giác
 
Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...
Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...
Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...Wonderjunior
 
BUsiness Ethics and Corporate Governance
BUsiness Ethics and Corporate GovernanceBUsiness Ethics and Corporate Governance
BUsiness Ethics and Corporate GovernanceDrVaidehi Shukla
 
Fairness and ethics in decision making
Fairness and ethics in decision makingFairness and ethics in decision making
Fairness and ethics in decision makingAmr Sherif
 
Mod 1 notes
Mod 1 notesMod 1 notes
Mod 1 notesmverm1
 
Business ethics definition
Business ethics definitionBusiness ethics definition
Business ethics definitionLenny Rosadiawan
 
Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3
Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3
Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3Loren Schwappach
 

La actualidad más candente (20)

Chapter # 5
Chapter # 5Chapter # 5
Chapter # 5
 
Business ethics an introduction
Business ethics   an introductionBusiness ethics   an introduction
Business ethics an introduction
 
Towards a social action analysis of organizations
Towards a social action analysis of organizationsTowards a social action analysis of organizations
Towards a social action analysis of organizations
 
personal and organizational values
personal and organizational valuespersonal and organizational values
personal and organizational values
 
Foundations of ethics
Foundations of ethicsFoundations of ethics
Foundations of ethics
 
Business ethics assignment
Business ethics assignmentBusiness ethics assignment
Business ethics assignment
 
Moral Framework for Ethics
Moral Framework for EthicsMoral Framework for Ethics
Moral Framework for Ethics
 
Ethical decision making in business
Ethical decision making in business Ethical decision making in business
Ethical decision making in business
 
Chapter # 6
Chapter # 6Chapter # 6
Chapter # 6
 
Changing paradigms of corporate social responsibility
Changing paradigms of corporate social responsibilityChanging paradigms of corporate social responsibility
Changing paradigms of corporate social responsibility
 
Chapt 3 evaluating business ethics
Chapt 3   evaluating business ethicsChapt 3   evaluating business ethics
Chapt 3 evaluating business ethics
 
20140929 ethics-foundations
20140929 ethics-foundations20140929 ethics-foundations
20140929 ethics-foundations
 
Business ethics
Business ethicsBusiness ethics
Business ethics
 
Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...
Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...
Why a Code of Conduct is Important for the Entrepeneur (Dingman Center of Ent...
 
BUsiness Ethics and Corporate Governance
BUsiness Ethics and Corporate GovernanceBUsiness Ethics and Corporate Governance
BUsiness Ethics and Corporate Governance
 
Fairness and ethics in decision making
Fairness and ethics in decision makingFairness and ethics in decision making
Fairness and ethics in decision making
 
Corporate Karma
Corporate KarmaCorporate Karma
Corporate Karma
 
Mod 1 notes
Mod 1 notesMod 1 notes
Mod 1 notes
 
Business ethics definition
Business ethics definitionBusiness ethics definition
Business ethics definition
 
Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3
Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3
Intd670 1103 a-10-schwappach-loren-p1-t3
 

Destacado

Business Ethics Theories Teachback Presentation
Business Ethics Theories Teachback PresentationBusiness Ethics Theories Teachback Presentation
Business Ethics Theories Teachback Presentationdunham16
 
El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?
El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?
El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?vivilissette
 
Cso Credentials
Cso CredentialsCso Credentials
Cso CredentialsReu Santos
 
Business ethics
Business ethicsBusiness ethics
Business ethicstappoo
 
ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...
ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...
ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...Semyon Mikhailenko
 
Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN
Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN
Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN DanielCardona04
 
Prelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for Individuals
Prelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for IndividualsPrelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for Individuals
Prelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for IndividualsVasiti Ratusau
 
Business ethics ppt
Business ethics pptBusiness ethics ppt
Business ethics pptAli Zeeshan
 

Destacado (18)

Business Ethics Theories Teachback Presentation
Business Ethics Theories Teachback PresentationBusiness Ethics Theories Teachback Presentation
Business Ethics Theories Teachback Presentation
 
El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?
El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?
El poder y sus conflictos o ¿Quién puede más?
 
Cso Credentials
Cso CredentialsCso Credentials
Cso Credentials
 
El patinaje
El patinajeEl patinaje
El patinaje
 
Business ethics
Business ethicsBusiness ethics
Business ethics
 
Osilator
OsilatorOsilator
Osilator
 
Normative theories of business ethics..
Normative theories of business ethics..Normative theories of business ethics..
Normative theories of business ethics..
 
Prueba corta 2 ricardo
Prueba corta 2 ricardoPrueba corta 2 ricardo
Prueba corta 2 ricardo
 
ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...
ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...
ИРИДИС Групп. Мы ближе чем кажется...
 
Seguridad ciudadana
Seguridad ciudadanaSeguridad ciudadana
Seguridad ciudadana
 
Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN
Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN
Wikis/QUE SON Y PARA QUE SIRVEN
 
Ceramicos
CeramicosCeramicos
Ceramicos
 
Prelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for Individuals
Prelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for IndividualsPrelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for Individuals
Prelim PDHPE-Core 1: Better Health for Individuals
 
Ethical theories
Ethical theoriesEthical theories
Ethical theories
 
Unidad educativa riobamba
Unidad educativa riobambaUnidad educativa riobamba
Unidad educativa riobamba
 
Ethics IIIrd sem MBA
Ethics IIIrd sem MBA Ethics IIIrd sem MBA
Ethics IIIrd sem MBA
 
Business ethics ppt
Business ethics pptBusiness ethics ppt
Business ethics ppt
 
CV_EN_DTL_2015
CV_EN_DTL_2015CV_EN_DTL_2015
CV_EN_DTL_2015
 

Similar a BARRETT_MANUSCRIPT_Evaluating Business Ethics.2016

BUSINESS IN ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n A n t .docx
BUSINESS  IN  ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n  A n t .docxBUSINESS  IN  ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n  A n t .docx
BUSINESS IN ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n A n t .docxfelicidaddinwoodie
 
Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1Andy Lopez
 
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docxTHE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docxoreo10
 
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docxTHE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docxssusera34210
 
Business ethic & values
Business ethic & valuesBusiness ethic & values
Business ethic & valuespavidhillon
 
Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docx
 Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docx Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docx
Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docxgertrudebellgrove
 
Intro To BUSINESS ETHICS
Intro To BUSINESS ETHICSIntro To BUSINESS ETHICS
Intro To BUSINESS ETHICSsimply_coool
 
Business ethics and spirituality
Business ethics and spiritualityBusiness ethics and spirituality
Business ethics and spiritualitysanekha
 
10 myths about business ethics
10 myths about business ethics10 myths about business ethics
10 myths about business ethicsMateen Yousuf
 
American MNEs In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRD
American MNEs  In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRDAmerican MNEs  In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRD
American MNEs In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRDAudrey Britton
 
chapter one ethics.pptx
chapter one ethics.pptxchapter one ethics.pptx
chapter one ethics.pptxAhmedDahir27
 
EmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docx
EmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docxEmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docx
EmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docxYASHU40
 
RUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview .docx
RUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview                                 .docxRUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview                                 .docx
RUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview .docxsusanschei
 
Chapter 2
Chapter 2Chapter 2
Chapter 2gbrand
 

Similar a BARRETT_MANUSCRIPT_Evaluating Business Ethics.2016 (20)

BUSINESS IN ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n A n t .docx
BUSINESS  IN  ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n  A n t .docxBUSINESS  IN  ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n  A n t .docx
BUSINESS IN ETHICAL FOCUSndedition2A n A n t .docx
 
Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1
 
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docxTHE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
 
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docxTHE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
THE QUEST FOR A CODE OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AN INTELLECTUAL AND M.docx
 
businessethics
businessethicsbusinessethics
businessethics
 
Business ethic & values
Business ethic & valuesBusiness ethic & values
Business ethic & values
 
66.pdf67.pdf.docx
66.pdf67.pdf.docx66.pdf67.pdf.docx
66.pdf67.pdf.docx
 
Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docx
 Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docx Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docx
Review Conflicts of Interest and Self-Dealing in the Pro.docx
 
Intro To BUSINESS ETHICS
Intro To BUSINESS ETHICSIntro To BUSINESS ETHICS
Intro To BUSINESS ETHICS
 
Business ethics and spirituality
Business ethics and spiritualityBusiness ethics and spirituality
Business ethics and spirituality
 
10 myths about business ethics
10 myths about business ethics10 myths about business ethics
10 myths about business ethics
 
American MNEs In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRD
American MNEs  In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRDAmerican MNEs  In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRD
American MNEs In Search Of Legitimacy When You Re WEIRD
 
chapter one ethics.pptx
chapter one ethics.pptxchapter one ethics.pptx
chapter one ethics.pptx
 
CV OF Coudhry Babar
CV OF Coudhry BabarCV OF Coudhry Babar
CV OF Coudhry Babar
 
Ethics1
Ethics1Ethics1
Ethics1
 
EmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docx
EmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docxEmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docx
EmployeesLearning ObjectivesAfter completing this chap.docx
 
Values
ValuesValues
Values
 
RUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview .docx
RUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview                                 .docxRUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview                                 .docx
RUNNING HEAD Christian Worldview .docx
 
Chapter 2
Chapter 2Chapter 2
Chapter 2
 
Business Ethics
Business EthicsBusiness Ethics
Business Ethics
 

BARRETT_MANUSCRIPT_Evaluating Business Ethics.2016

  • 1. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett, Esquire Author Note Adjunct Professor for Masters Business Administration Program, Graduate and Professional Studies, Averett University, Danville, VA (MCB Quantico Campus). Correspondence regarding this manuscript should be addressed to Craig D. Barrett. Email: cbarrett@averett.edu or regular mail at 15660 William Bayliss Court, Woodbridge VA 22191. The author can also be reached on cell phone at 703-409-6808. CONTENTS Introduction: The Purpose of Ethics…………….………….……….…………………………………..p. 3 The Difficulty with Business Ethics…………………………………………….………...............….…p. 4 Introduction of the Procedural and Substantive Challenge…………………….…………..….p. 4 Procedural Problem with the Application of Kantian Ethics……………………...…...….…….…...…p. 6 Organizational Ethics vs. Individual Ethical Theory………………………....…………....…..p. 6 The Challenge of Directly Applying Kant’s Ethics…….………………….……..............….…p. 6 Overcoming the Challenge…………………………………………….……….………..……..p. 8 The Substantive Problem: Applicability of Categorical Imperative……………………………..…….p. 10 Categorical Imperative: Act Only on Maxims that can be Willed as a Universal Law……….p. 11 Categorical Imperative: Treat Humanity as Ends……………………………….……………p. 15 Stakeholder Theory: Response to the Substantive Challenge…..……………………….…….…….…p. 16 What Stakeholder Theory Must Accomplish……………………………………….………….p. 16 Distributive Justice and Social Contract Theory: Broader Theoretical Considerations to Provide A Normative Basis to Stakeholder Theory………………...…………………………………..p. 17 Concluding Thoughts: A Moral Conception of Business Decisions……………..…..………………..p. 22
  • 2. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 2 Abstract When we speak of ethics, we think of a set of rules or principles that guide our actions. Our basic understanding leads us to believe that ethical principles ought to be followed by everyone under similar circumstances. Said rules or principles would lose their utility as a guide if it were the case they apply only to certain individuals while others are unreasonably exempt from the duty to act (or to refrain from acting) in a particular way. Equally problematic is when given two identical circumstances—all things being equal—the obligation holds only in one situation and not the other. The issue at hand is whether we can hold corporations to the same ethical standards to which we hold individual persons, employing the same ethical analysis to determine the blameworthiness of business entities. Such a determination serves as the basis for Business Ethics. However, business entities are dissimilar from persons in very fundamental ways which calls into question our method of morally judging business entities and thus the notion of Business Ethics. These fundamental differences cannot be ignored and warrants further analysis if we are to do justice to any discussion that attempts to determine what in fact business ethics is and whether such a notion is even coherent. The following paper will identify and explore the paradoxical tension between the notion of “business” and “ethics” when viewed through a Kantian lens and will aim to reconcile that tension by appealing to a version of stakeholder theory. Thus, we can make sense of a normative ethical theory that serves to guide business practice. Keywords: Stakeholder theory, Ethics, Kant, Kantian, Business Ethics, categorical imperative.
  • 3. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 3 1. Introduction: The Purpose of Ethics Before beginning an analysis on the coherency of “business ethics”, it is important to understand the general purpose of ethics. Such an understanding requires a firm grasp of the assumptions that are at work in our ethical considerations. First, we assume there are actors, organized socially, whose actions have an effect on others (in that social setting) either for better or for worse. These actors realize that it is advantageous for them to organize into groups because there is a higher probability of success for them to operate through mutual cooperation than it would were one to attempt to succeed at life on their own. Thus these actors operate within a social setting marked by a set of complicated relationships, connecting one person to another.1 It is in one’s best interest—one might reason—to operate within this social setting or well-organized society than it is to go at it alone. As a result, it is in one’s best interest to work in such a way that would contribute to the sustainability of this well organized society of mutual cooperation. This leads to the second assumption: these actors have a tendency to act in accordance with their self-interest.2 This motivation by self-interest has as its direct object some “good” that is —for some reason or another—relatively difficult to come by or is characterized by relative scarcity. Because these actors are rational and motivated by their self-interest, they naturally desire more of a “good” than less for themselves; and, securing more of this “good”, which is the object of their interest, will invariably breed conflict with others seeking to secure the same good for themselves due to its relative scarcity. As Rawls explains, “there is conflict of 1 Borrowing from Rawls, central to this discussion of ethics is the role of social institutions and individuals’ position in society. That is, moral considerations independent of society and social institutions however basic or complex may not be possible, for human existence outside society does not exist. As Rawls explains, “the major social institutions define men’s rights and duties and influences their life prospects, what they can expect to be and how well they can hope to do.” (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 7) Thus a coherent discussion of ethics must assume the complex relationship we have in a social setting. 2 This is not to discount the occurrence of altruistic behavior or to suggest that it is somehow irrational when one acts altruistically. On the contrary, one might sacrifice one’s self or prioritize the interest of someone else over their own in an attempt to materialize a much more important overarching interest: a parent might sacrifice herself for the protection of a child in an attempt to perpetuate the species, or an activist might sacrifice themselves in the name of a greater political cause for example. These instances of altruism do not gainsay the claim that rational beings are beings that act in a manner that is consistent with of preserving their self-interests (however defined) but are consistent with self interested pursuits.
  • 4. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 4 interests since persons are not indifferent as to how the greater benefits produced by their collaboration are distributed, for in order to pursue their ends they each prefer a larger to a lesser share.” (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 4.) Thus there becomes a need for ethical principles that can regulate the interaction between members of society with regards to the fair distribution of the goods available, recognizing and protecting the respective rights of citizens. Such ethical principles support the notion of justice and fairness, which are central in the preservation of a well-ordered society. The question that remains: where does an artificially formed entity such as a corporation fit into all of this? And how do we define its obligations and duties in ethical terms? The difficulty of this inquiry, however, should not be underestimated. Nevertheless it is a challenge I will undertake in the discussion that follows. In an attempt to get a grasp on the notion of “business ethics”, I will examine stakeholder theory through a Kantian lens with a reliance on the social contract theory. 2. The Difficulty with Business Ethics There is generally some consensus as to what constitutes ethical behavior as it relates to individual rational beings, i.e., people. For example, we basically agree that lying, breaking promises because keeping said promise no longer benefits us, or using people for our own personal gain are all morally frowned upon. However, such consensus often fails to carry over when we attempt to define the ethical behavior of a corporation or define what constitutes business ethics. In business, creative advertising may be called “lying”; an economic efficient breach of a contract might be called “breaking of a promise”; and, the purpose of business, which is to generate profit, might in effect treat people as a means toward that end. Nevertheless, the aforementioned are acceptable business practices. The difficulty of defining the sort of behavior that ought to be undertaken by a corporation—beyond mere compliance with established laws—
  • 5. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 5 is one often taken for granted and often ignored when we engage in a discussion regarding “business ethics.” For if “ethics” suggests a normative theory that guides action, what exactly are we saying a business “ought” to do under certain circumstances when it involves the interests of others? Whose interests is a corporation responsible for protecting, and why? Concepts such as duty, moral agency, and categorical imperative are all familiar terms in a discussion about the moral ethics of individual rational beings. However, without rigorous examination of the appropriate application of those terms, within the context of “business ethics”, such concepts may lose their coherency in our attempt to determine the acceptable behavior of business entities. 2.1. Introduction of the Procedural and Substantive Challenge There are two fundamental questions we must consider. First, can (or must) we consider a business as a moral agent in order for it to have moral obligations or duties in the first place? If moral obligations are dependent upon the presence of moral agency, we must then answer the question of what constitutes a moral agent and whether a business in fact possesses the characteristics required to constitute it as a moral agent as such. Arguably, if we fail to constitute the corporation as a moral agent, then any notion of moral obligation assumed by a non-moral agent becomes nonsense—and, equally perplexing would be this notion of “business ethics.” For how could there be a field of ethics for entities that are non-moral agents? Second, even if we can assume a corporation has ethical obligations, how can we define the duty of a corporation, and can we effectively apply Kant’s categorical imperative in this instance? These two questions, respectively, imply a procedural and substantive challenge that must be considered when determining the duty of a corporation. The procedural question pertains to whether a business is one to which the categorical imperative is appropriately assigned in the first place—i.e., is it proper to treat a corporation as a moral agent; and, the substantive question
  • 6. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 6 examines whether the categorical imperative can serve as an effective guide for normal business practices. Kant “believed that reason provided the basis for the categorical imperative, thus the categorical imperatives of morality were requirements of reason.” (Bowie, “A Kantian Approach,” p. 2.) The categorical imperative, although it captures the key feature of individual morality, does not apply as neatly to a corporation. A corporation’s inability to “reason” presents some difficulty in supporting the position that a corporation is subject to the categorical imperative in the first place. I will take on this procedural question in the next section. Second, I will then address the more substantive challenges of the categorical imperative as it applies to corporate responsibility. Finally, I will appeal to stakeholder theory from a social contract perspective to make sense of a Kantian approach to business ethics. The purpose of this paper is to bridge the gap between (1) business ethics as we may think it applies to corporations and (2) our normal understanding of Kantian ethics as it applies to the individual morality of persons. Because corporations are made up of people, our first instincts are to hold businesses accountable for moral actions using similar reasons we use to hold people accountable. However, as I will explain later, this reasoning is flawed and thus will not do. It is my intention to make sense of business ethics, grounded in Kantian ethics, in such a way that is consistent with our intuitions. Thus we might properly evaluate the actions of a corporation as it operates under real life market conditions. 3. Procedural Problem with the Application of Kantian Ethics: Moral Agency and the Assignment of Moral Obligation 3.1. Organizational Ethics vs. Individual Moral Theory There is a distinction that ought to be recognized between organizational ethics and individual moral theory. Too often in our discussion of business ethics the two obvious distinct
  • 7. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 7 fields are confounded, leading to strange and often counter-intuitive claims as to what a business organization ought to do when acting in its capacity as a corporate entity and considering its place in society. Despite the recognition of the corporation as a legal “person’, an ethical theory centered around the actions of business entities cannot be modeled perfectly after a Kantian theory of ethics, as that theory was intended to apply specifically to rational beings, i.e., humans. Although there are some parallels between what we perceive to be the responsibilities of corporations and the moral responsibilities of humans—i.e., ideas such as fairness, justice, duty, frequently appear in discussions of both theories—the concept of “humans” as a subject of ethics is not interchangeable with the concept of “business entities.” Thus we cannot expect to establish a singular ethical theory for these two distinct concepts that can provide univocal guidance for both. Humans and corporation are simply not the same type of being. Rather, a custom ethical theory for corporations must be constructed from the bottom up rather than simply adding it as an addendum to the moral theory we hold sound for human beings. Stakeholder theory is one such theory as will be discussed. Although, some Kantian concepts may reappear in the context of business ethics, its implications are vastly different than those considered in the context of (Kantian) moral theory regarding individual persons. Such differences cannot simply be ignored; and, although a Kantian approach is possible when understanding the obligations of corporations, some issues arise when directly applying Kant’s ethics to corporations outside the stakeholder theory framework. 3.2. The Challenge of Directly Applying of Kant’s Ethics For Kant, autonomy and rationality are necessary for moral agency. Furthermore, in order for there to be a moral obligation, there must be a moral agent (i.e., a rational being) to whom the obligation attaches. To elucidate this point, consider for example animal rights activists who
  • 8. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 8 argue that humans have a duty not to mistreat animals based on our status as rational beings. Thus, we have a duty to refrain from actions that might be considered cruel to animals; however, no such duty exists for animals. We do not, for example, hold a lion morally accountable for mauling its trainer or for injuring other animals. Because animals lack rationality, they are not considered moral agents to which we could assign blamed. Christine Korsgaard in her article “Personhood, Animals, and the Law” explains that the basis of rationality is defined by “normative self-governance.” This is the capacity to be governed by thoughts about what you ought to do or believe. (Korsgaard, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law,” p. 26) In the empiricist tradition of Hume and Locke it was common to attribute to human beings alone the capacity to form what is called second-ordered attitudes, which is the basis for normative self- governance. (Korsgaard, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law,” p. 26) These are attitudes towards our own desires and serve as the basis for regulating our actions in accordance with our understanding of what is “right”, thus not giving in to hedonistic desires without regard to moral consequences: “Though one may desire to do something, I may disapprove of that desire and reject its influence over me.” (Korsgaard, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law,” p. 26.) Second- tier attitudes, Korsgaard explains, are what make humans subject to the “ought.” If this is the case, a corporation—like an animal—can never be subjected to the “ought” since the corporation—properly speaking—does not have desires and cannot engage in the act of “normative self-governance.” Thus, the question of moral obligation, which is the subject of ethics, entails the question of what constitutes moral agency. It therefore seems if we cannot constitute a “being” as a moral agent, a discussion of ethics that might govern the actions of said being would be incoherent. This is the procedural problem.
  • 9. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 9 Though it is true the corporation as a whole has as its constitutive parts “real” autonomous rational beings—i.e., people—that alone cannot not support the position that a corporation is a moral agent, subject to the same categorical imperatives like promise-keeping for example. This would be an appeal to an informal fallacy, which is the fallacy of composition. This fallacious inference improperly attributes characteristic of the parts of a whole to the collective whole. This simple logical point makes it difficult to move from a Kantian argument we hold sound for individuals to an ethical argument regarding corporations grounded in a similar Kantian theory. For example, just because all of the parts of a machine are made in Germany does not necessarily mean the machine comprised of those parts is made in Germany as well. For it could be the case the parts were shipped to the United States and the machine was assembled there. Thus, a corporation made of moral agents does not make the corporation, as such, a moral agent as well. However, it does not seem correct to end the story there, for we do say “a company ought to do such and such”, or “this company is responsible for thus and so harm.” And we feel justified in doing so. Unless we are willing to concede that such “moral- language” as it relates to corporations is no more than a misnomer—that is to say, it is no more than an improper application of language to corporate behavior—we will need to do more work here. This incongruence between the corporate collective and the individual moral agent is not the undoing of business ethics. However some work must be done to overcome this challenge. 3.3. Overcoming the Challenge The question then is whether a corporation is the sort of entity that can be the subject of moral duty. This then leads us to the following question: is moral agency a necessary precondition for a corporation in order for it to have moral responsibilities thus making sense of the notion of business ethics? As stated, if moral agency is based on rationality, moral
  • 10. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 10 responsibility is not possible. However, we may still be able to make a case for Business Ethics. In Margaret Gilbert's article “Who's to blame? Collective Moral Responsibility and Its Implications for Group Members,” she explores the question of blameworthiness as it pertains to individuals and the collective group to which the individuals are said to belong. Since the corporate entity only exists as an entity made up of people, the actions of the corporate entity necessarily are actions carried out by people. Gilbert explores the asymmetry between the flow of blameworthiness to individuals (from the group) as compared to the flow of blame to the collective (from individuals) as it pertains to the same act. The example she provides is one where we as humans assume responsibility for environmental pollution even though I as an individual may not have specifically engaged in any activities causally connected to the pollution of the environment. In such a case, the collective (not the individual) serves as a distinct subject to our moral judgment. (Gilbert, “Who's to Blame,” p. 102) Here, although what is true for the whole is not necessarily true of its constitutive parts, blame still attaches to both entities. In the business context, although Enron as a company may have been blameworthy for a variety of corporate malfeasance deserving of sanctions, the manager of research and development of Enron may not be held personally responsible or viewed with the same approbation. However, to the extent that the manager’s efforts are in support of the success of a corrupt company and is identifiable with the company, she shoulders blame in that regard. Conversely, the bad acts of an individual, whether CEO or line-worker, might be imputed to the organization. Thus, the corporate collective is worthy of blame and deserving of punishment even if there was no unanimous corporate endorsement of the bad act by the members of the collective group. This pattern of the assignment of blame in the latter case is also present in our legal system of Agency and Tort Law. The theory of Respondent Superior (“imputed liability”) in law endorses the
  • 11. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 11 rendering of liability to the corporation (the principal) for the specific actions of the individual employee (acting as agents of the corporation) in instances when the company stands to benefit from the wrong committed or if the wrong committed was within the scope of their employment in support of the collective objective. “Under the doctrine of respondent superior…the principal may be held liable for an agent’s tort even though the principal was blameless.” (Posner, Economic Analysis of Law, p. 114) Thus blame is assigned to the collective (or corporation) even though the collective did not formally endorse the “bad act” in question. Even though the status of moral agency does not go from individual member to corporate collective—because of the requirement of rationality—does not prevent one from passing judgment on the corporate entity under a theory of imputed liability. It is uncontroverted that a corporation is made up of individual autonomous beings. It cannot exist otherwise. However, although we may not be able to claim the corporate collective is a moral agent as such, if an act is wrong and causes harm as a result, said act is wrong whether attributed to an individual member of the collective or attributable to the entire organization. Said act may be attributed to the corporation because the individual actor was acting at the behest of the corporate entity or because the corporate entity benefitted from the commission of the “bad act.” In this way, the corporate collective “owns” the actions and may therefore be judged accordingly—though not in exactly the same way we morally judge individual actors. Thus by focusing on the act itself, and not necessarily on the constitution of the “actor” (as moral agent) we can make coherent moral judgments about business practices. Granted, because of the absence of rationality, this is not a perfect “Kantian” judgment of business practices so to speak. However, even if Kant’s theory does not perfectly apply to corporate practices, “he still has a lot to offer the business ethicist”. (Bowie “A Kantian Approach,” p. 12) For as stated earlier, we do—as common practice—pass
  • 12. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 12 moral judgment on corporate activity. However, the fact that we engage in a particular act cannot serve as a normative basis or as justification for that act. Description of a practice alone is not sufficient to serve as justification of this practice, as you cannot obtain an “ought” from an “is”. This is in philosophy a well-known error in reasoning called the naturalistic fallacy. However, so long as the corporate entity is considered the “but-for” cause of the complained-of act in question, even if the actions are executed by the employees for corporation’s benefit, we are justified under the Tort Law theory of respondent superior (see, supra p. 8) in ascribing blame to that corporation. If we accept the proposition that a corporation can be blameworthy as argued above, then we can argue they possess duties: For the assignment of blame properly occurs when one fails to carryout one’s duties as assigned. However, how might we define the duties of corporate entities? This brings us to the substantive issue and is one that will be addressed in a discussion of stakeholder theory. These are taken up in greater detail in the sections that follows, first examining the substantive issue in greater detail. 4. The Substantive Problem: Applicability of Categorical Imperative To Corporations A summary of Kant’s categorical imperative might be summarized as follows: 1. Act only on maxims which you can will to be universal laws of nature; 2. Always treat the humanity in a person as an end and never as a means only; 3. So act as if you were a member of an ideal kingdom of ends in which you were both subject and sovereign at the same time In his article “The Kantian Approach to Business Ethics,” Bowie explains, “Kant’s ethics is an ethics of duty rather than an ethics of consequences.” The ethical person, he continues, “is the person who acts from the right intentions.” (Bowie, “A Kantian Approach to Business Ethics,” p. 2) Such intentions must not be concerned with the consequences of a particular act but must instead focus on the duty (or obligation) that give rise to the act in the first place. Thus, Kant’s ethics has as its fundamental principle the “categorical imperative”, which provides the
  • 13. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 13 outline for ethical duty. “The categorical imperative,” Bowie continues, “is not irrelevant in the world of business. If a maxim for an action when universalized is self-defeating, then the contemplated action is not ethical. That is Kant’s conceptual point.” (Bowie, The Kantian Approach, p. 5) 4.1 Categorical Imperative: Act Only on Maxims that can be Willed as a Universal Law However despite Bowie’s claim of the categorical imperative’s applicability in the world of business, there are some challenges in a applying the categorical imperative to business organizations. Consider the applicability of (1) “act only on maxims which you can will to be universal laws of nature.” On Kantian grounds, Bowie argues, a corporation must act only on maxims it can will to be universal business law without yielding a contradiction in its practice or yield a “self-defeating” end. From an individual perspective it is easy to see how this might play out: consider one who engages in the act of stealing in order to secure more resources for herself. She could not universalize this act of stealing as a universal law without endorsing the act of stealing in general, to include the stealing of resources from herself; and, for her to endorse the act of “being stolen from” contradicts (or defeats) her original purpose to secure more resources for herself—which was the motivation for her to steal in the first place. Thus the act of stealing in this case cannot be morally endorsed according to the categorical imperative. In this way Bowie argues, “when enough people behave immorally…certain business practices…become impossible.” (Bowie, “A The Kantian Approach,” p.5.) What is problematic about Bowie’s assessment here is (1) corporations are not—strictly speaking—individual persons (an issue addressed in the previous section); and, (2) although the act of going back on promises, for example, may be an act that cannot be universalized as universal law for persons, the efficient breach or renegotiation of a contract is a common
  • 14. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 14 acceptable business practice. A contract represents a legally enforceable promise; however, when its terms are no longer advantageous to a party of the contract, it is not uncommon for a business to renegotiate or refuse to honor those terms. Bowie acknowledges this point in his article explaining, “[executives] point out that, in the real world, contracts are often ‘renegotiated’ and yet business people still engage in contract making.” To this, Bowie simply replies: “These executives raise an interesting point.” (Bowie, “A Kant Approach,” p. 4) Bowie then cites to some other “real world” business examples that support Kant’s point but never directly addresses the issue of “broken-promises” in business contracts. I contend this is more than just “an interesting point” and represents a substantive issue that merits further examination, for it calls into question the applicability of the categorical imperative to very common business practices. Consistent with the law (and supported by one legal economic theory) it is a common practice for companies to engage in what is called an efficient breach. According to Black’s Law Dictionary, efficient breach theory is a modern contract theory that endorses the breaching of a contract and payment of damages to the non-breaching party if doing so would be more “economically efficient [than performing under the contract]...[And this] occurs when the breaching party will still profit after compensating the other for its ‘expectation interest.’” (Black’s Law Dictionary, Abridged Sixth Edition.) It should be noted, however, “this theory is not well accepted.” (Id.) However, the point here is not to argue the merits of the “efficient breach theory”; rather, the point is to demonstrate how the categorical imperative of “promise keeping” may not be “self-defeating” if violated in the context of normal business practices. As Richard Posner explains,
  • 15. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 15 In some cases a party is tempted to break his contract simply because his profit from breach would exceed his profit from completion of the contract. If it would also exceed the expected profit to the other party from completion of the contract, and if damages are limited to the loss of that profit, there will be an incentive to commit a breach.” (Posner, Economic Analysis of Law, p. 120.) To elucidate this point, consider the following example (inspired by a well-known illustration by Judge Posner): assume Company A contracts to deliver 100 widgets to Company B for $1 per widget. Company B will in turn use these 100 widgets to create 25 machine gadgets it plans to sell in the market place for $10 per gadget (10 x $25= $250 in gross sales) thus realizing a profit of $150 before assembly cost, shipping, warehousing etc. (i.e., $250 cash after sales -$100 the cost of the widgets = $150 before-cost earnings). Assuming said costs to Company B are $2.50 per gadget (2.50 x 25=$62.50), Company B expects to yield a net profit of $87.50 ($150- 62.50=$87.50) if Company A performs per the contract. Assume further that instead of selling the 100 widgets to Company B as contracted, Company A sells the widgets to Company C who finds itself in desperate need of the widgets in question and is willing to pay double the market value at $2 per widget ($2 x 100=$200). Company A, not wanting to pass up on an arbitrage opportunity, decides to breach the contract it has with Company B, paying Company B damages in the amount of $88 dollars—in effect purchasing the “right” to keep the widgets. The dollar amount in damages Company B receives is $0.50 more than Company B would have realized had the contract been honored. Additionally, Company A as a result of the breach realizes a gain of $112.00 (after damages paid to Company B), $12 more than the gains Company A would have realized had it honored the contract in the first place. In such an example, all players in the market, Company A, B, and C fair better than they would had the parties performed in accordance with the original contract. Thus, breaching the contract is Pareto Superior to
  • 16. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 16 honoring the contract. Here market efficiency, dictates what is in the best interest of all parties involved and is thus the action that ought to be taken. This idea was never more clearly expressed than in Ronald Coase’s “The Problem of Social Cost.” The Coase Theorem is concerned with resolving the conflict between competing activities. The conflict arises when the pursuit for profits for one activity threatens the gains of a competing activity. Here the parties enjoy legal entitlements with regards to their respective activities for which a market valuation is attached. The point of conflict is as yet unresolved; and, the market is capable of determining the practical outcome of the dispute based on the market value of each activity no matter what legal resolution is proposed at the point of conflict. The basic thesis of Coase is that efficient market theory can better resolve the disputes between two parties where “rights” and “obligations” are in question. Rather than appealing to legal institutions to adjudicate what is “right”, “fair”, or “just”, the wider normative application of the Coase Theorem asserts that legal liability ought to be determined based upon economic efficiency. And rather than imposing punishment upon the “wrong-doing” company, that company might simply be required to pay “rents” to the suffering party in an amount dictated by the market. In such a case, the (complained-of) act must generate more value through its activity than the value created if the company were to refrain from that activity. Here this value creates a larger “pie” to be shared by all interested parties who each in effect will enjoy a larger share. Because the administration of justice comes with associated transaction costs, the size of the “pie” is substantially reduced when justice is sought through the court system.3 This “transaction 3 In the section on administrative cost, Kaplow and Shavell’s explanation illustrates, in my view, how transaction cost associated with the legal system lead to market inefficiency. They explain, “The administrative costs of the liability system are the legal and other costs (notably the time of litigants) involved in bringing suit and resolving it through settlement or trial. These costs are substantial; a number of estimates suggest that, on average, administrative costs of a dollar or more are incurred for every dollar that a victim receives through the liability system. In contrast, the administrative cost of receiving a dollar through the insurance system is often below fifteen cents.” (Kaplow and Shavell, Economic Analysis of Law, p. 1673)
  • 17. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 17 cost” reduces the value available for all parties to share—or so a proponent of the Coase Theorem might argue.4 Thus the more valuable harm-causing activity—absent transaction cost however defined—might be able to buyout and induce the less valuable activity to forgo its legal rights. The more valuable harm-causing activity is now free to pursue its activity so long as the value it generates is sufficient to conduct the buyout and still retain a gain. Thus, the Coase Theorem posits that the determination of legal liability (and perhaps also moral responsibility) becomes moot where efficient markets are concerned. In pursuit of establishing economic efficiency, “[l]aw and economics derive the guiding principle that the courts should mimic the markets: the courts should determine issues of liability on the basis of what the market in ideal conditions would determine as the efficient outcome of the dispute between parties.” (Halpin, Disproving The Coase Theorem? p. 322.) Thus an efficient breach of a promise—from a business perspective—if adopted as a universal law does not “defeat” the activity of contract- making but may fall under the vast array of business practices supported by market efficiency. Such practices do not defeat contracting between businesses, but facilitates its negotiation in a free market. 4.2. Second Categorical Imperative: Treat Humanity as Ends The second representation of the categorical imperative requires that we treat humanity as an end and never as a means. Such an idea of the categorical imperative may be difficult to apply in that a corporation is an artificially created entity formed for the sole purpose of generating a profit.5 If we accept profit seeking as the function of a business, how can a corporation ever 4 It should be noted that in my paper to which I cite, supra at p.13, I argue against this position. In that discussion, I contend that we cannot ignore the value that society places in the act of formally assigning blame to the harm-causing party. This assignment of blame can only be acquired through the institution of laws, which necessarily comes with an associated transactional cost. Thus, our desire to hold wrong-doers accountable for their actions cannot always be replaced with cash compensation—however, oftentimes it can. 5 Obviously to the extent that such a pursuit runs afoul established laws, such actions ought to be avoid; however, this—arguably—is because purposefully violating the law threatens the corporation’s profits and because violation of the law might lead to costly fines or substantial diminution of market value that could lead to the corporation’s ultimate undoing.
  • 18. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 18 avoid treating beings—whether employees, customers, investors or suppliers—other than as a means to that end? This then violates Kant’s categorical imperative if we accept Bowie’s position that “it is a central tenant of Kant’s moral philosophy that an action is only truly moral if it is morally motivated.” (Bowie, Kantian Approach, p.11). Thus a theory on business ethics must do more than speak to the instrumental function of managerial decisions. That is, it must establish something more than “a framework for examining the connections…between the [ethical] practice of…management and the achievement of various corporate performance goals.” (Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 67. Here defining “instrumental function” of morality.) This would be no more than engaging in a moral act because it is instrumental or a means in achieving various ends or performance goals. Consider, for example, a company that produces defective cars that might cause the death of others. A decision by management to recall these cars may only be because in the short-run it restores the confidence of the consumer in the company’s brand. Thus in the long-run, the corrective action preserves the company’s market share amongst those customers—promising the company’s continued success—serving as an instrumental basis for a manager’s decision. Although the decision considers the customer and perhaps the community writ large, there is still a component of that decision that seems to casts a lascivious eye toward profit preservation. However, this is not a desirable start for an ethical theory. On Kantian grounds, “it is the intention behind an action rather than its consequences that make an action good…For Kant if a merchant is honest so as to earn a good reputation, these acts of being honest are not genuinely moral.” (Bowie, A Kantian Approach to Business Ethics, p. 1) In such a case—a decision made on purely instrumental grounds cannot be said to be “ethical” because people are not treated as ends in themselves but merely as means to a more self-serving corporate objective. However, it seems odd that we
  • 19. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 19 should expect an artificially created entity formed for the purpose of creating profit to have an obligation to materialize some end that does not preserve profit. Thus claiming there exists a branch of ethics that imposes such an obligation on businesses may seem equally odd. Donaldson and Preston explain that although descriptive and instrumental justifications “are significant aspects of the of stakeholder theory, its fundamental basis is normative.” (Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 67) In this way, Donaldson and Preston concede there is a need for the theory to have some “normative bite” if it is to have any ethical significance. As such, it is imperative (no pun intended) that our justifications of corporate activity go beyond profit generation (which is an instrumental justification) if we are to establish a normative basis in support of our moral judgments in the context of business ethics. 5. Stakeholder Theory: Response to the Substantive Challenge 5.1. What Stakeholder Theory Must Accomplish In their article “The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation: Concepts, Evidence, and Implication,” Thomas Donaldson and Lee Preston argue that managers can apply stakeholder theory to guide their decisions. They “believe that the ultimate justification for the stakeholder theory is to be found in its normative base.” Donaldson and Lee conclude that the alternative to stakeholder theory, which is a style of management centered on shareowner interests, is untenable. (Donaldson and Preston p. 88.) “Stakeholders are persons or groups with legitimate interests in procedural and/or substantive aspects of corporate activity and are identified by their interest in the corporation, whether the corporation has any corresponding functional interest in them.” (Donaldson and Preston, p. 67 emphasis in the original.) However, even if we concede that developing a normative theory around the interest of shareowners is in fact “untenable,” how do we justify imposing an “ought” on business organizations that requires it to take into
  • 20. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 20 consideration the interests of these “other” persons? Consider for example the following: the adoption of certain technology may increase efficiency in the production of the product the company sells, however, this technology results in the elimination of hundreds of jobs and the termination of hundreds of employees; or the outsourcing of jobs increases a company’s profit margin but also devastates the economy of the adjacent community as a result of the decreased economic activity in that area; or finally, the carbon emissions of a corporation’s industrial plant is central to its production and profit but reduces the quality of air for future generations. Why should a company, in any of these instances, forgo immediate profit to preserve jobs for employees, or help to maintain the economic stability of the adjacent community, or preserve the environment for future generations? Consequently we must reveal what Donaldson and Preston allude to as the “normative base” of the stakeholder theory. It is this ”normative base” that is doing most of the theoretical heavy lifting here. Second, who qualifies as a “legitimate” stakeholder in the first place, and how must we consider and adjudicate their varied and sometimes conflicting interests? To the latter question, the solution starts with how we must define “interest.” If it is the case that the type of “interest” determines whether one has a legitimate stake, which is at the root of stakeholder theory, it becomes necessary to delineate with some clarity what and how interests are considered legitimate. To accomplish this, we must appeal to a theory of property rights. Here we argue that stakeholders have entitlements and rights in the value created by the corporation because of the relationship corporations have with them and society writ large. Then it must be determined how that value can be fairly distributed amongst those with these legitimate claims.
  • 21. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 21 5.2. Distributive Justice and Social Contract Theory: Broader Theoretical Considerations to Provide A Normative Basis to Stakeholder Theory “Even the most enlightened corporations are almost always justified in part on the grounds that such actions are profitable, it appears [then] that even the best actions of the best corporations are not truly moral.” (Bowie Kantian Theory p. 12.) Enhancing profit, arguably, represents the “self interest” of the company and is the purpose of the corporation’s existence, for the corporation was formed for that purpose. Although other interests may be considered, the self-interest of the corporation (i.e., profit) may seem to subordinate all other interests (not leading to profit.) Milton Friedman argues “the whole justification for permitting the corporate executive to be selected by stockholders is that the executive is an agent serving the interest of the principal. This justification disappears when the corporate executive imposes taxes and spends the proceeds for social purposes.” (Friedman, The Social Responsibility of Business, p. 4, emphasis added.) Here Friedman is incorrect: the justification for a manager’s decision does not necessarily “disappear” simply because it serves the interest of other interested parties and results in some social good. Friedman’s point fails to consider the duty a manager may have as agent of multiple principals, i.e., the various stakeholders. Consider stakeholder theory as outlined above which suggests a business, specifically managers, should consider the interests of not only shareowners—whose primary interest is profit—but also to others who too have a “stake” in the success of the firm or who are somehow otherwise impacted by the activities of the firm. Under stakeholder theory, the decisions made by management are not always “profit- driven” and must consider the respect for and dignity of other stakeholders, treating them as ends in themselves and not merely as means. This represents the notion of “the what” with regards to
  • 22. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 22 the actions managers should take, but we must determine “how” these interests ought to be managed. Stakeholder theory thus requires support in order to succeed as a normative theory. Although stakeholder theory advocates argue that mangers ought to shift their focus from a shareowner centric style of management to a stakeholder style of management, this theory must still consider the interest of shareowners, though not as a primary focus. The theory expands the category of persons whose interests ought to be protected by managerial decisions. Notably, in order for a theory to fail to qualify as a stakeholder theory, such a theory would “have to specifically instruct managers to ignore the interests, values, and rights of one or more category of persons…” (Hasnas p. 50); thus stakeholder theory requires a manager to consider the interest of (all) those who might have a stake in the company’s success and not just the interest of the shareowner. However, the theory is vulnerable to criticism of it failing to be a normative theory. According to one such criticism, Hasnas explains, “the injunction that business ‘pay attention’ to stakeholders does not mark out any definite normative theory.” (Id. p. 50.) Any managerial decision would be justifiable since every act would be in the interest of some stakeholder; and, if everyone is a legitimate stakeholder, stakeholder theory would endorse any act on the basis that it furthers the interest of someone. There is no “definite normative theory” here; and, no guidance, then, will be available under this theory. Thus there must be an appeal to another theory that might guide us in prioritizing the interests of the various stakeholders we are now considering. To start, the “interests of all stakeholders are of intrinsic value. That is, each group of stakeholders merit consideration for its own sake and not merely because of its ability to further the interest of some other group, such as shareowners.” (Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 67) The for-profit corporation is an artificially created entity formed for the purpose
  • 23. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 23 of creating value. Thus the appropriate question becomes simply: who has rights in the value generated by the corporation? Thus persons acting in their capacity as managers are merely agents of those whom might be identified as having legitimate property claims to that value. In this way, the stakeholder theory is based on a much broader philosophical theory, supported by a notion of distributive justice. More precisely, how ought the primary goods, i.e., profit, generated by the corporation be distributed amongst existing parties who may have a legitimate claim to the value created by the corporation? Stakeholder theory recognizes a right to the value created by the company amongst those other than the shareowner. Such a notion can be normatively based on the evolving theory of property rights. (Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 83.) The irony in this view, as Donaldson and Preston point out, is that “property rights” have most commonly been associated with shareowner’s interests. (See id. at p. 83.) However, as Donaldson and Preston explains, the most persuasive view of property rights is as a bundle of many rights and not the unlimited rights of one party. The rights and entitlements of owners are merely part of the story here: because the adjudication of rights, privileges, and obligations are done amongst human actors, we must also consider the plethora of human rights and obligations based on our coexistence qua humans, a relationship which is far more complicated than mere “property ownership” would suggest. There is a mutual dependency we have on one another. As such, we must consider society—independent of the individual property owner—even in the context of the ownership of specific property, for without society and the preservation of its well-being, the “thing” which is the subject of ownership and enjoyed by its owner would not exist in the first place. Thus not even a privately owned track of land purchased with the hard-earned dollars of the owner should be used to dispose of toxic nuclear waste. Or in the less extreme case, all property is subject to taxes
  • 24. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 24 revenue, which is used for the public good. Here there is a feature of stakeholder theory that provides a normative approach to business ethics: shareholders or owners or investors are not the only ones entitled to the value created from trade, sales, production etc. Rather, an account can be defended where other stakeholders are entitled to the residual gain on a notion of distributive justice and a version of social contract theory. From a social contract perspective, each stakeholder is not only essential to the corporation’s ability to generate profit, but is also essential to the corporation’s very existence. The corporation reaps the benefits from the mutual cooperation of those who work in society for the mutual advantage of all members within that society; and, as a beneficiary of the advantage created, the basic theory of social contract requires the corporation also to treat those participants as ends rather than means to more self-serving ends. For without society’s participants, the self- serving ends could not be realized in the first place. The notion of social contract theory coupled with a theory of Kantian ethics and distributed justice is doing the philosophical “work” here, grounding stakeholder theory as a normative one. Thus Donaldson and Preston are correct in saying, “more formal normative justifications of stakeholder theory might be based on broad theories of philosophical ethics, such as utilitarianism, or narrower “middle-level” theories derived from the notion that a social contract exists between corporation and society.” (Donaldson and Preston, Stakeholder Theory, p. 83.) From a Kantian perspective it is not acceptable to give priority to some stakeholders’ interest simply because they out number other stakeholders as advocated by utilitarianism. A corporation, then, may decide not to enhance corporate profit or shareowner gain if so doing fails to treat stakeholders (other than shareowners) with dignity and respect. These other stakeholders by virtue of their position in society, relationship to the corporation, and contribution to its
  • 25. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 25 continued existence, arguably, possess a property interest in the corporate created value. Thus those with a legitimate claim to the value created by the corporation must be treated with the respect and dignity that would require the manager to consider their interest, treating them as ends insofar as their existence is the necessary precondition upon which the existence of the corporation rest. Thus when considering the “just” distribution of corporate-created value, every stakeholder is entitled to their fair share for reasons that can be justified on Kantian grounds and considering the special relationship developed between corporations and other entities in the context of the social contract tradition. As a result, a fair distribution of corporate value may appropriately reduce the value or profit for shareowners. Thus the Stakeholder theory suggests that matters are more complicated: stakeholder relationships are involved, and human beings are more complex than standard accounts assume. All stakeholders must be treated as ends in themselves because each stakeholder is sine quo non to the formation and continued existence of the corporate entity. In this way, we can evaluate the behavior of the corporate entity in its treatment of the many stakeholders who have a property stake in the value that a corporation creates because, in a sense, neither the corporation nor the value it creates would exist but-for the existence of these stakeholders. Thus there is nothing incoherent about a corporation—from an ethical standpoint—taking into consideration the stake of say, employees, suppliers, or the adjacent community, eliminating profit generating behavior that might adversely impact on those stakeholders. From a social contract theorist perspective, without these stakeholders and—to be sure—without society writ large, the corporation itself would not exist. From one perspective, it is not necessarily the case the corporation is forgoing greater profit in the interest of, say, preserving a living wage for employees; rather, a portion of the value generated by the corporation is returned to the population of persons, i.e., employees,
  • 26. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 26 who make it possible for the company to generate value in the first place. Their role then must be considered on moral grounds, as their contribution creates an entitlement and a right to the value generated by the corporation. How that value is distributed might be determined on Kantian grounds of justice and fairness, perhaps set in the Rawlsian tradition of Justice as Fairness for example.6 6. Concluding Thoughts: A Moral Conception of Business Decisions An action undertaken by a corporation that results in its inability to turn a profit may lead to its inability to meet pay roll, cover invoices from suppliers, or pay overhead which enables the corporation to bring their product or services to market. These inabilities may result in the company’s failure and ultimate dissolution. A corporation’s failure can adversely affect its employees who are now faced with unemployment, other businesses that rely on that corporation’s economic role in society, and adversely impact customers who now no longer receive products and services from the failed company. Conversely, decisions that may increase profit can lead to the damage of the environment when shortcuts are taken, the exploitation of low wageworkers, and the damaging of the economy through unfair business practices. When corporations understand that they do not function independent of society, it becomes natural to adopt a stakeholder approach; for like individuals, business entities can only realize their objectives within the framework of the social cooperation for mutual advantage that characterizes a well ordered society. Thus every decision made by a corporation should take into account the interests of those who not only have a equity interest in the company, but also, those whose existence makes it possible for the corporation to do business in the first place. 6 See John Rawls discussion of justice as fairness in his book A Theory of Justice.
  • 27. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 27 One clear example of this is when Goldman Sachs used Credit Default Swaps to reduce the risks inherent in the mortgage-backed securities it sold in the market place. The default swaps were basically an “insurance policy” taken against the mortgage backed security in the event the borrower failed to repay the underlying mortgage from which the mortgage security derived.7 Goldman Sachs collected fees by packaging the mortgaged backed securities they sold to investors which in turn created greater liquidity for the banks to originate loans for home purchasing. Greater liquidity led to more available loans, which led to greater demand for homes because more people now had access to mortgages. This greater demand for homes artificial increased home value, which is a simple matter of supply and demand. In addition, more loans led to more origination fees for (saving and loan) banks and led to more security products such as mortgage securities for investors to purchase; and, thus this led to more fees for investment banks such as Goldman Sachs. The moral issue is this: while Goldman sold these securities to (and collected fees from) their clients, they also purchased these Debt Swaps (insurance policies) against the very products they sold to their clients. Thus Goldman stood to make money should borrowers fail to repay these mortgages; however, if and when these same borrowers defaulted, Goldman’s clients who held these mortgage securities would lose money as a result. Thus in essence, Goldman stood to make money on the failure of a product they sold to their clients who would in the end lose millions. On a phone conference, one top Goldman executive stated—and I am paraphrasing here—“there is nothing wrong with conflicts of interests in business; rather, it is how you manage these conflicts that is important to good business practices.” Here we have a case where 7 Technically, although credit default swaps function as an insurance policy, it is treated as a financial instrument rather than an insurance policy subject to a variety of regulations. Arguably, the intention behind calling these products financial instruments titling them “credit default swaps” or “credit default obligations” rather than “credit default insurance policies” was with the intentions of side-stepping the regulations imposed upon insurance products: One such regulation requires that the entity ensuring the policy (in this case AIG) actually has the liquid cash to cover the losses the policy is intended to protect the policy holder against.
  • 28. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 28 Goldman engaged in actions that affected a variety of stakeholders all of whom were owed a duty. They are as follows: (1) clients who were sold risky financial product; (2) shareholders, who are entitled to —when legally possible—the minimization of risks of their capital invested which prompted the purchase of the Default Swaps in this case; and, (3) society and the financial system which was devastated due to the oversaturation of subprime-lending in the market, facilitated by mortgage-backed securities sold by Goldman. Though there was nothing overtly illegal about Goldman’s purchase of $2 billion in Default Swaps or their standing to gain from their clients’ losses, an evaluation as to whether their actions were “right” can be effectively determined by applying stakeholder theory as presented in the discussion above. One might argue that in this case, sufficient consideration was not given to clients and the financial impact on society writ large with an over emphasis on the interest of shareowners and profit. This becomes increasingly more apparent when we consider the $183 billion of taxpayer dollars used for the corporate bailout of insurance company giant AIG who owed Goldman approximately $13 billion dollars. Thus in the end, Goldman was paid $13 billion from AIG who was bailed- out by the collective earnings of members of the same society devastated by Goldman’s actions that spawned the housing bubble in the first place. This interdependency between corporation and society requires the corporate entity to treat all these stakeholders as ends in themselves and not simply a means to leverage greater profit (for the benefit of one of many stakeholders). Moreover, the claims to the value created by the corporation are not the exclusive property interest of shareowners. Thus managers should not limit their consideration to what is in the interest of shareowners and investors alone when making decisions. A broader understanding of property rights includes a consideration of the many and complex relationships between society’s participants to include its citizens as well as
  • 29. Is Business Ethics An Oxymoron? A Kantian and Stakeholder Theory Approach to Evaluating Business Ethics. Craig D. Barrett 29 corporate entities. This broader understanding of property rights requires one to consider the claims and rights of other stakeholders and the obligation the corporation may have to them. Thus decisions based on stakeholder theory, coupled with Kantian and social contract consideration, provides a more comprehensive approach of what a corporation ought to do, considering its place in society and the overall implications and impact of its actions. And although such decisions may at times appear also to maximize profit, managers must have some justification for those decisions beyond mere profit maximization. References 1. Bowie, “A Kantian Approach to Business Ethics”, Ethical Issues in Business: a philosophical approach. 7th ed. New Jersey: Prentice Hall pp. 61-71 2. Bowie, “A Kantian Theory of Meaningful Work” 3. Coase, Ronald H., The Problem of Social Cost, (1960). The Journal of Law & Economics, volume III, pp1-44. 4. Donaldson and Preston, “Stake holder Theory of the Corporations Concepts, Evidence, and Implication,” The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Jan., 1995), pp. 65-91 5. Friedman, Milton, “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase Its Profits,” (1970) The New York Times Magazine, September 13, 1970 6. Haplin, Andrew, “Disproving The Coase Theorem?” (2007) Economics and Philosophy, 23, pp321-341 7. Hasnus, John, “Whither Stake Holder Theory? A Guide for the Perplexed Revisited,” (2012) Springer Science Business Media B.V. 8. Kosgaard Christine, “Personhood, Animals, and the Law”, Think Philosophy for Everyone, Summer 2013, 25-32 9. Margeret Gilbert, “Who's to Blame? Collective Moral Responsibility and Its Implications for Group Members” (2006) Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Blackwell Publishing, Inc. 10. Posner, Richard Economic Analysis of Law, Sixth Ed., Aspen Publishers (2007) 11. Rawls, John, Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press (1971)