SlideShare una empresa de Scribd logo
1 de 12
university of cape coast 
SCHOOL OF BUSINESS 
DEPARTMENT OF MANAGEMENT STUDIES 
LECTURER: DR.ABORAMPA AMOAH MENSAH 
ASSIGNMENT: BUS 207 
Question: Ghanaians revere the affluent 
without questioning the sources of their 
wealth. Garrett proportionality framework is 
therefore of no relevance to them. Discuss. 
INDEX NUMBER :SB/BMS/13/0045 
11/12/2014
Introduction 
Our Ghanaian societies are structured in a way that respect is given to someone 
according to the measure of his or her riches. Everything in our societies is controlled by 
the affluent (rich men) who are citizens in that society. Before a child begins to attend 
school, there is the ambition of wealth creation in his or her mind. 
Wealth has been the only instrument that commands respect in Ghana. This is 
because success is measured according to materiality. If someone want to tease his or 
her enemy, the best way is to expensive clothing or prepare a delicious meal if only they 
stay in the same house or even do something that shows riches. As a result of the 
ambition for wealth by most Ghanaians, our able youths are travelling oversees for 
greener pastures. Most of these youths travel by illegal means (stoway), others to by 
stealing family properties or other fraudulent means in order to fetch him or her some 
money to live by. Our family system is structured in a way that the poor is regarded as a 
failure, as a result, his or her (the poor) contribution in the family meeting is not adhered 
to. It does not matter the wisdom in what they (the poor) say, all that drives Ghanaians 
is riches but not advice. If a member of a family arrives from oversees, he or she wi ll be 
regarded as an important figure in the family, and whatever he or she says is final. It 
does not matter whether what he or she is saying contains senses all because such a 
person has money on herself or himself. These people have refused to ask the sources 
of their family member’s riches. Children are refusing to ask their parent the sources of 
their wealth, parent are also not asking the sources of their children riches. The only 
question that comes into their mind is “what kind of job do you do?” whatever reply 
given them is final. Instead of the children and the parent to find out whether what was 
told is true or not , they rather hail their parent or children for their good works. 
Ghanaians have generated the attitude of measuring success with goodness. Thus, the 
more good you are the more success (deontological theory) which has been a historical 
issue. This issue has driven people who engage in fraudulent means for wealth to rather 
do good in their society in order for them to be seen as good citizens. Most corrupt 
individuals are engaging in charity and orphanage foundations just to hide their 
intensions. 
Our churches have been made in such a way that the rich men (affluent) are given 
Eldership positions without questioning then source of their wealth. Such people have 
used the church to cover their evil means of creating wealth. During appeal for funds, 
harvest or even fund raising, they (the affluent in church) will be quoting the highest bid 
for a clap from the congregation. The desperation for money by modern pastors has 
created way for corrupt citizens to be in the church with no fear of God. This attitude has 
defiled our churches, because the congregation too has refused to question the source 
of the affluent wealth. 
The ambition for wealth creation has made doctors to use fraud and also have lost their 
integrity in serving the nation. Today doctors are building their own private hospitals and 
no one has ever asked them the sources of their wealth.
Small thief in society is regarded as a menace to the society and is even imprisoned but 
the great thief for example, the business man Alfred Agbesi Woyome is now regarded a 
hero although he has used fraud to take GHC52.1 million from the government. His 
name has been in dailies reports and the television but not regarded as a thief. Even his 
thievery has given political parties opportunity to make unnecessary propaganda. 
Therefore, Ghanaians regard the most corrupt as a hero without thinking the 
consequence of their (the corrupt) actions to the nation. After all, they have been a 
blessing to others lives. 
. Affluent: this refers to having an abundance of wealth, property, or other material 
goods; prosperous; rich: an affluent person.(encyclopedia) 
Garrett’s proportionality framework (1966) 
Garrett provides what is termed a ‘proportionality’ framework and is usefully compared 
with Ross’s prima facie duties framework. 
His framework combines the utilitarian concern with outcomes (consequences) with the 
Kantian preoccupation with process (intentions and means). 
For Garrett, ethical decisions comprise three components: intention, means and end. 
The sequence in the decision-making model then becomes: 
· Intention or that which is willed. What is the motivation behind a person’s actions? Are 
the intentions ethical? 
· Means. What methods or processes are used to bring about certain ends? Are they 
ethical? An unforeseen harm, resulting from risk, is permissible because it is not willed 
(intended). A foreseen harm, however, is only permissible if there is a proportionate 
reason for taking the risk of the harm. For instance, it is permissible when the outcomes 
will be clearly of great good and the risks are minimal (the notion of restricted risk). 
· End. Garrett’s view is that ends should be measured in terms of the intrinsic value 
(nature) foreseen of the acts rather than by the consequences produced by these acts. 
In other words, the end should not justify the means. Also, his notion of restricted 
responsibility should not be applied in the sense that anything is permissible if the ends 
justify the means. 
The Garrett proportionality framework combines the deontological theory with the 
utilitarian theory. These theories are explained below. 
Deontological ethics 
The word deontology comes from the Greek roots deon, which means duty, and logos, 
which means science. Thus, deontology is the "science of duty." Key questions which 
deontological ethical systems ask include: What is my moral duty?
What are my moral obligations? 
How do I weigh one moral duty against another? 
Deontological ethics, in philosophy, ethical theories that place special emphasis on 
the relationship between duty and the morality of human actions. Deontology (Greek 
Deon, “duty,” and logos, “science”) consequently focuses on logic and ethics. No 
attempt is made in such theories to explicate specific moral obligations. 
In deontological ethics an action is considered morally good because of some 
characteristic of the action itself, not because the product of the action is good. 
Deontological ethics holds that at least some acts are morally obligatory regardless of 
their consequences for human welfare. Descriptive of such ethics are such expressions 
as “Duty for duty’s sake,” “Virtue is its own reward,” and “Let justice be done though the 
heavens fall.” 
By contrast, teleological ethics holds that the basic standard of morality is precisely the 
value of what an action brings into being. Deontological theories have been termed 
formalistic because their central principle lies in the conformity of an action to some rule 
or law. 
The first great philosopher to define deontological principles was Immanuel Kant, the 
18th-century German founder of critical philosophy, whose ethics were much influenced 
by Christianity as well as by the Rationalism of the Enlightenment. Kant held that 
nothing is good without qualification except a good will, which is one that wills to act in 
accord with the moral law and out of respect for that law, rather than out of natural 
inclinations. He saw the moral law as a categorical imperative—i.e., an unconditional 
command—and believed that its content could be established by human reason alone. 
Reason begins with the principle “Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the 
same time will that it should become a universal law.” Kant’s critics, however, have 
questioned his view that all duties can be derived from this purely formal principle and 
have argued that, in his preoccupation with rational consistency; he neglected the 
concrete content of moral obligation. 
This objection was faced in the 20th century by the British philosopher W.D. Ross, who 
held that numerous “prima facie duties,” rather than a single formal principle for deriving 
them, are themselves immediately self-evident. Ross distinguished these prima facie 
duties (such as promise keeping, reparation, gratitude, and justice) from actual duties, 
for “any possible act has many sides to it which are relevant to its rightness or 
wrongness”; and these facets have to be weighed before “forming a judgment on the 
totality of its nature” as an actual obligation in the given circumstances. 
Types of Deontological Ethics 
Some examples of deontological ethical theories: 
Divine Command: the most common forms of deontological moral theories are those 
which derive their set of moral obligations from a god. According to many Christians, for 
example, an action is morally correct whenever it is in agreement with the rules and
duties established by God. 
Duty Theories: an action is morally right if it is in accord with some list of duties and 
obligations. 
Rights Theories: an action is morally right if it adequately respects the rights of all 
humans (or at least all members of society). This is also sometimes referred to as 
Libertarianism, the political philosophy that people should be legally free to do whatever 
they wish so long as their actions do not impinge upon the rights of others. 
Contractarianism: an action is morally right if it is in accordance with the rules that 
rational moral agents would agree to observe upon entering into a social relationship 
(contract) for mutual benefit. This is also sometimes referred to as Contractualism. 
Monistic Deontology: an action is morally right if it agrees with some single 
deontological principle which guides all other subsidiary principles. 
Problems with Deontological Ethics 
A common criticism of deontological moral systems is that they provide no clear way to 
resolve conflicts between moral duties. a deontological moral system should include 
both a moral duty not to lie and one to keep others from harm, for example, but in the 
above situation how is a person to choose between those two moral duties? A popular 
response to this is to simply choose the "lesser of two evils," but that means relying on 
which of the two has the least evil consequences and, therefore, the moral choice is 
being made on a consequentialitist rather than a deontological basis. 
Some critics argue that deontological moral systems are, in fact, consequentialist moral 
systems in disguise. According to this argument, duties and obligations which set forth 
in deontological systems are actually those actions which have been demonstrated over 
long periods of time to have the best consequences. Eventually, they become enshrined 
in custom and law and people stop giving them or their consequences much thought — 
they are simply assumed to be correct. Deontological ethics are thus ethics where the 
reasons for particular duties have been forgotten, even if things have completely 
changed. 
A second criticism is that deontological moral systems do not readily allow for grey 
areas where the morality of an action is questionable. They are, rather, systems which 
are based upon absolutes — absolute principles and absolute conclusions. In real life, 
however, moral questions more often involve grey areas than absolute black & white 
choices. We typically have conflicting duties, interests, and issues that make things 
difficult.
Another common criticism of deontological ethical theories is the question of just which 
duties qualify as those which we should all follow, regardless of the consequences. 
Duties which might have been valid in the 18th century are not necessarily valid now, 
but who is to say which ones should be abandoned and which are still valid? And if any 
are to be abandoned, how can we say that they really were moral duties back in the 
18th century? 
If these were duties created by God, how can they possibly stop being duties today? 
Many attempts to develop deontological systems focus on explaining how and why 
certain duties are valid at any time or at all times and how we can know that. Religious 
believers are often in the difficult position of trying to explain what believers of the past 
treated certain duties as objective, absolute ethical requirements created by God but 
today they aren't — today we have different absolute, objective ethical requirements 
created by God. These are all reasons why irreligious atheists rarely subscribe to 
deontological ethical systems, though it can't be denied that they can at times have 
ethical insights to offer. 
Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism 
Because deontological theories are best understood in contrast to consequentialist 
ones, a brief look at consequentialism and a survey of the problems with it that motivate 
its deontological opponents, provides a helpful prelude to taking up deontological 
theories themselves. Consequentialists hold that choices—acts and/or intentions—are 
to be morally assessed solely by the states of affairs they bring about. 
Consequentialists thus must specify initially the states of affairs that are intrinsically 
valuable—often called, collectively, “the Good.” They then are in a position to assert that 
whatever choices increase the Good, that is, bring about more of it, are the choices that 
it is morally right to make and to execute. (The Good in that sense is said to be prior to 
“the Right.”) 
Consequentialists can and do differ widely in terms of specifying the Good. Some 
consequentialists are monists about the Good. Utilitarians, for example, identify the 
Good with pleasure, happiness, desire satisfaction, or “welfare” in some other sense. 
Other consequentialists are pluralists regarding the Good. Some of such pluralists 
believe that how the Good is distributed among persons (or all sentient beings) is itself 
partly constitutive of the Good, whereas conventional utilitarians merely add or average 
each person's share of the Good to achieve the Good's maximization. 
Moreover, there are some consequentialists who hold that the doing or refraining from 
doing, of certain kinds of acts are themselves intrinsically valuable states of affairs 
constitutive of the Good. An example of this is the positing of rights not being violated, 
or duties being kept, as part of the Good to be maximized—the so-called “utilitarianism 
of rights” (Nozick 1974).
None of these pluralist positions erase the difference between consequentialism and 
deontology. For the essence of consequentialism is still present in such positions: an 
action would be right only insofar as it maximizes these Good-making states of affairs 
being caused to exist. 
However much consequentialists differ about what the Good consists in, they all agree 
that the morally right choices are those that increase (either directly or indirectly) the 
Good. Moreover, consequentialists generally agree that the Good is “agent-neutral” 
(Parfit 1984; Nagel 1986). That is, valuable states of affairs are states of affairs that all 
agents have reason to achieve without regard to whether such states of affairs are 
achieved through the exercise of one's own agency or not. 
Consequentialism is frequently criticized on a number of grounds. Two of these are 
particularly apt for revealing the temptations motivating the alternative approach to 
deontic ethics that is deontology. The two criticisms pertinent here are that 
consequentialism is, on the one hand, overly demanding, and, on the other hand, that it 
is not demanding enough. The criticism regarding extreme demandingness runs like 
this: for consequentialists, there is no realm of moral permissions, no realm of going 
beyond one's moral duty (supererogation), no realm of moral indifference. All acts are 
seemingly either required or forbidden. And there also seems to be no space for the 
consequentialist in which to show partiality to one's own projects or to one's family, 
friends, and countrymen, leading some critics of consequentialism to deem it a 
profoundly alienating and perhaps self-effacing moral theory (Williams 1973). 
On the other hand, consequentialism is also criticized for what it seemingly permits. It 
seemingly demands (and thus, of course, permits) that in certain circumstances 
innocents be killed, beaten, lied to, or deprived of material goods to produce greater 
benefits for others. Consequences—and only consequences—can conceivably justify 
any kind of act, for it does not matter how harmful it is to some so long as it is more 
beneficial to others. 
A well-worn example of this over-permissiveness of consequentialism is that of a case 
standardly called, Transplant. A surgeon has five patients dying of organ failure and one 
healthy patient whose organs can save the five. In the right circumstances, surgeon will 
be permitted (and indeed required) by consequentialism to kill the healthy patient to 
obtain his organs, assuming there are no relevant consequences other than the saving 
of the five and the death of the one. Likewise, consequentialism will permit (in a case 
that we shall call, Fat Man) that a fat man be pushed in front of a runaway trolley if his 
being crushed by the trolley will halt its advance towards five workers trapped on the 
track. We shall return to these examples later on. 
Consequentialists are of course not bereft of replies to these two criticisms. Some 
retreat from maximizing the Good to “satisficing”—that is, making the achievement of 
only a certain level of the Good mandatory (Slote 1984). This move opens up some 
space for personal projects and relationships, as well as a realm of the morally 
permissible. It is not clear, however, that satisficing is adequately motivated, except to
avoid the problems of maximizing. Nor is it clear that the level of mandatory satisficing 
can be nonarbitrarily specified, or that satisficing will not require deontological 
constraints to protect satisficers from maximizers. 
Another move is to introduce a positive/negative duty distinction within 
consequentialism. On this view, our (negative) duty is not to make the world worse by 
actions having bad consequences; lacking is a corresponding (positive) duty to make 
the world better by actions having good consequences (Bentham 1789 (1948); Quinton 
2007). We thus have a consequentialist duty not to kill the one in Transplant or in Fat 
Man; and there is no counterbalancing duty to save five that overrides this. Yet as with 
the satisficing move, it is unclear how a consistent consequentialist can motivate this 
restriction on all-out optimization of the Good. 
Yet another idea popular with consequentialists is to move from consequentialism as a 
theory that directly assesses acts to consequentialism as a theory that directly assesses 
rules—or character-trait inculcation—and assesses acts only indirectly by reference to 
such rules (or character-traits) (Alexander 1985). Its proponents contend that indirect 
consequentialism can avoid the criticisms of direct (act) consequentialism because it will 
not legitimate egregious violations of ordinary moral standards—e.g., the killing of the 
innocent to bring about some better state of affairs—nor will it be overly demanding and 
thus alienating each of us from our own projects. 
The relevance here of these defensive maneuvers by consequentialists is their common 
attempt to mimic the intuitively plausible aspects of a non-consequentialist, 
deontological approach to ethics. For as we shall now explore, the strengths of 
deontological approaches lies: (1) in their categorical prohibition of actions like the 
killing of innocents, even when good consequences are in the offing; and (2) in their 
permission to each of us to pursue our own projects free of any constant demand that 
we shape those projects so as to make everyone else well off. 
Consequences resulting from the reverence Ghanaians give to the affluent 
Ghanaians have hyped the affluent in society in such a way that the poor is not 
recognized as an important figure n our society. The rich in our societies have used 
their wealth to control the minds of most Ghanaians which have prevented them from 
discovering the source of the rich’s wealth. There is a saying that “money answers 
everything”, so the outcome of the affluent actions is not considered. I would like to 
stress some consequences emanating from these attitudes of Ghanaians towards the 
affluent. These are: 
 Increase in Non Governmental Organizations (NGO) 
 The creation of power 
 Societal corruption
The affluent in Ghana have used nongovernmental organizations as a 
means of preventing people from discovering the sources of their wealth. 
These days if a person wants to be recognized in society as a good person, the best is 
to engage in or establish charity foundations or orphanage which is also beneficial to 
the vulnerable in society. This is an opportunity Ghanaians have given to the affluent 
without making any internal and effective control measures to check or verify what 
actually the affluent the resources to undertake such projects those who take it upon 
themselves to ask of the source of their wealth are answered that funds are being 
solicited from various corporate bodies and institutions to support the project. 
Meanwhile this may not be the case, it is a justification for fraudulent activity they have 
engaged in. managers In corporate institutions are embezzling funds, District Chief 
executives are using common funds for their own personal interest, Ministers are 
appropriating the budget for a project in order to to use the remaining money for their 
own benefit., etc. Today, politicians and their relatives are engaging in charity 
foundations with the intension to cover their corrupt attitudes. For example, the first lady 
of Ghana, Mrs. Lordina Mahama , has been running charity foundations that enhances 
health promotion and advocacy and encourage women employment through capacity 
building and sustained income generation among other benefits that has made her a 
woman who listens, love and care for others especially the less privileged, children and 
women. 
A look at her work through the Lordina Foundation shows that the foundation has 
helped in areas such as orphanage support, support for Persons Living with HIV/AIDS, 
Scholarships for brilliant but needy students, promoting women’s empowerment through 
entrepreneurship, raising awareness and advocating for cervical and breast cancer 
prevention and treatment. 
The foundation is also providing suitable accommodation for ostracized women in 
“Witch Camps and still goes to the aid of the weak, sick and lass privileged in society. 
According to her, the multiplier effects of such philanthropic gestures will help many 
indigent people in the society to become self reliant by getting employment. The first 
Lady is described by the less privileged in society as an honest and intelligent woman-” 
a great mother and a comforter”. She is described by many as a source of 
encouragement in her advocacy for health, Education, peace and unity in the country. 
Ghana’s First lady, Lordina Mahama have received recognition from development 
partners and organizations in the USA and across the globe for her philanthropic work 
through the Lordina Foundation in Ghana and being active in helping in his husband’s 
social policy interventions such as the development of deprived children and women in 
both rural and urban areas of Ghana. 
Although it is a good project, nobody has ever questioned her source of her wealth. I am 
saying this because when Mrs. Lordina mahama was not the first lady, she was not 
engaging in this philanthropic foundation. According to the utilitarian theory, which 
states that the consequence of your action must bring more happiness to the greater 
number of people and less harm to the least number of people (Jeremy Bentham), this 
project is very welcoming in Ghana because it has helped many people from perishing
through sickness. Whereas, deontological theory states that doing good or bad does not 
base on the consequence of your action. This is a situational issue because a person is 
seen as good in Ghana if the society benefit from him or her no matter he 
consequences the goodness will bring to society. For instance, if Mrs. Lordina Mahama 
is embezzling funds from the government coffers in undertaken this project then, the 
consequences will badly affect the state’s financial position with the intension (according 
to Garrett proportionality framework) of gaining political power at the end. 
Most affluent in Ghana are revered for the good they do to their societies although they 
might be engaging in ‘juju’ for blood money. These and many more are some 
opportunities Ghanaians have given to the affluent in society. 
The reverence Ghanaians give to the affluent has given them power to 
control everything in societies in fraudulent manner. 
Our Ghanaian family system is structured in a way that the rich men in the family are 
recognized as the backbone of the family. Because of this, the influence the rich have 
on the family is very high. When it comes to family meeting the rich are always 
recognized, they (rich0 decisions to suit their own interest, any decision made against 
their interest will be disregarded by them because they (the rich) are those the whole 
family looks onto when problems evolves. This issue has compelled most people the 
ambition for riches even if the means are not there. Parents are forcing their children in 
bringing huge sums of money to their house. Our family system has been a platform to 
show one’s riches and belongings. Most people are embezzling funds from their 
workplaces, others are using lies to claim huge sums of money from people, others also 
are killing to get wealth, and whiles others are also dealing in drugs for wealth without 
questioning them the source of their wealth. Today, the one in flashy cars, who wears 
expensive clothing, living in beautiful house etc, is seen as a rich person and is 
therefore respected by Ghanaians but the person who is not riding in posh cars and in 
expensive clothing is seen as an ordinary man, lazy man, poor man etc. this attitude 
has also given the affluent the opportunity to seek for political power. 
Societal corruption 
The complexity of our social structure is such that those who succeed can hide their 
corruption. Corruption is seen only when someone fails. If you succeed no one will know 
that you have been corrupt; success will hide everything. You have only to succeed and 
you will become a pinnacle of goodness, thus you will become everything that is good, 
pure, and innocent. That means you can succeed in any way you like, but you must 
succeed. Once you succeed, once you are successful, nothing that you may have done 
is wrong.
This has been true throughout history. A person is only a thief if he is a small thief. If he 
is a great thief, then he becomes an Alexander the Great, a hero. No one ever sees that 
there is no qualitative difference between the two, that it is only a qualitative difference. 
No one will call Alexander the Great a great thief because the measure of your 
goodness is success: the more successful you are the more good. Means are only 
questioned if you are failure, then you will be called both corrupt and a fool. 
If this is the attitude, how is it possible to create an uncorrupt society? To ask a person 
to be moral in this immoral situation is to ask something absurd. An individual cannot be 
moral in an immoral society. If he tries to be moral, his morality will only make his 
egoistic and ego is as immoral and corrupt as anything else. 
This situation is a human creation. We have created a society with a mad rush for 
wealth, power, politics; we go on supporting it, and then we ask why there is corruption. 
Where there is ambition, corruption will be the logical consequence. You cannot check 
corruption unless the whole basic structure that encourages ambitions is destroyed. 
In conclusion 
Our Ghanaian societies are structured in a way that respect is given to someone 
according to the measure of his or her riches. Everything in our societies is controlled by 
the affluent (rich men) who are citizens in that society 
Wealth has been the only instrument that commands respect in Ghana. This is because 
success is measured according to materiality 
Ghanaians have generated the attitude of measuring success with goodness. Thus, the 
more good you are the more success (deontological theory) which has been a historical 
issue. This issue has driven people who engage in fraudulent means for wealth to rather 
do good in their society in order for them to be seen as good citizens. Most corrupt 
individuals are engaging in charity and orphanage foundations just to hide their 
intensions. 
Garrett provides what is termed a ‘proportionality’ framework and is usefully compared 
with Ross’s prima facie duties framework. 
His framework combines the utilitarian concern with outcomes (consequences) with the 
Kantian preoccupation with process (intentions and means). 
For Garrett, ethical decisions comprise three components: intention, means and end 
In philosophy, Deontological ethics refers to ethical theories that place special 
emphasis on the relationship between duty and the morality of human actions. 
In deontological ethics an action is considered morally good because of some 
characteristic of the action itself, not because the product of the action is good.
Deontological ethics holds that at least some acts are morally obligatory regardless of 
their consequences for human welfare. Descriptive of such ethics are such expressions 
as “Duty for duty’s sake,” “Virtue is its own reward,” and “Let justice be done though the 
heavens fall.” 
Some examples of deontological ethical theories are Divine Command, Duty Theories, 
Contractarianism, Rights Theories, Monistic Deontology. 
A common criticism of deontological moral systems is that they provide no clear way to 
resolve conflicts between moral duties 
Some critics argue that deontological moral systems are, in fact, consequentialist moral 
systems in disguise. 
A second criticism is that deontological moral systems do not readily allow for grey 
areas where the morality of an action is questionable. 
Another common criticism of deontological ethical theories is the question of just which 
duties qualify as those which we should all follow, regardless of the consequences. 
Consequences resulting from the reverence Ghanaians give to the affluent are 
Increase in Non Governmental Organizations (NGO), the creation of power, societal 
corruption. 
Ghanaians have revered the affluent as a result of their goodness without questioning 
them the source of their wealth. 
References 
Alexander, L., 1985, “Pursuing the Good—Indirectly,” Ethics, 95(2): 315–332. 
Brook, R., 2007, “Deontology, Paradox, and Moral Evil,” Social Theory and Practice, 
33(3): 431–40. 
encyclopedia 
Kant, Immanuel. 1785. “First Section: Transition from the Common Rational Knowledge of 
Morals to the Philosophical”, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. 
Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 
Waller, Bruce N. 2005. Consider Ethics: Theory, Readings, and Contemporary Issues. New 
York: Pearson Longman: 23

Más contenido relacionado

La actualidad más candente

La actualidad más candente (20)

Emmanuel Kant Ethics
Emmanuel Kant EthicsEmmanuel Kant Ethics
Emmanuel Kant Ethics
 
Ethical theories
Ethical theoriesEthical theories
Ethical theories
 
Pollock ethics 8e_ch04
Pollock ethics 8e_ch04Pollock ethics 8e_ch04
Pollock ethics 8e_ch04
 
Moral Framework
Moral FrameworkMoral Framework
Moral Framework
 
Introduction to Ethical Theories
Introduction to Ethical TheoriesIntroduction to Ethical Theories
Introduction to Ethical Theories
 
Duty theory
Duty theoryDuty theory
Duty theory
 
Chapter 9
Chapter  9Chapter  9
Chapter 9
 
Ethics, integrity & aptitude
Ethics, integrity & aptitudeEthics, integrity & aptitude
Ethics, integrity & aptitude
 
Deontological ethics
Deontological ethicsDeontological ethics
Deontological ethics
 
ETHICAL THEORIES
ETHICAL THEORIESETHICAL THEORIES
ETHICAL THEORIES
 
Mod 1 notes
Mod 1 notesMod 1 notes
Mod 1 notes
 
Ethics
EthicsEthics
Ethics
 
Propersonal Issue
Propersonal IssuePropersonal Issue
Propersonal Issue
 
What Is Morality
What Is MoralityWhat Is Morality
What Is Morality
 
Moral agent
Moral agentMoral agent
Moral agent
 
Deontology intro
Deontology introDeontology intro
Deontology intro
 
Ethics Chapter 2
Ethics Chapter 2Ethics Chapter 2
Ethics Chapter 2
 
1111298173 282417 9
1111298173 282417 91111298173 282417 9
1111298173 282417 9
 
Module 1 - CSR and Good Governance
Module 1 - CSR and Good GovernanceModule 1 - CSR and Good Governance
Module 1 - CSR and Good Governance
 
The study of ethics
The study of ethicsThe study of ethics
The study of ethics
 

Destacado

2 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_2013
2 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_20132 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_2013
2 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_2013DENY160478
 
Center for Non Profit Excellence Building for Sustainability
Center for Non Profit Excellence Building for SustainabilityCenter for Non Profit Excellence Building for Sustainability
Center for Non Profit Excellence Building for SustainabilityWatulatsu Samuel
 
Sjabloondankdag
SjabloondankdagSjabloondankdag
Sjabloondankdagcorneh
 
Gregor Mendel y la Genética
Gregor Mendel y la GenéticaGregor Mendel y la Genética
Gregor Mendel y la GenéticaAnita Lopez Moure
 
Криптография.
Криптография.Криптография.
Криптография.SvetlanaFIT
 
Trabajo de jorge 108
Trabajo de jorge  108Trabajo de jorge  108
Trabajo de jorge 108jolsjors15
 
1. konsep dasar_1
1. konsep dasar_11. konsep dasar_1
1. konsep dasar_1DENY160478
 
10 prinsip ekonomi
10 prinsip ekonomi10 prinsip ekonomi
10 prinsip ekonomiDENY160478
 

Destacado (14)

2 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_2013
2 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_20132 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_2013
2 pembaharuan evaluasi_pembelajaran_fatirul_2013
 
Center for Non Profit Excellence Building for Sustainability
Center for Non Profit Excellence Building for SustainabilityCenter for Non Profit Excellence Building for Sustainability
Center for Non Profit Excellence Building for Sustainability
 
Anwar CK
Anwar CKAnwar CK
Anwar CK
 
Sjabloondankdag
SjabloondankdagSjabloondankdag
Sjabloondankdag
 
Gregor Mendel y la Genética
Gregor Mendel y la GenéticaGregor Mendel y la Genética
Gregor Mendel y la Genética
 
Криптография.
Криптография.Криптография.
Криптография.
 
updated profile
updated profile updated profile
updated profile
 
Trabajo de jorge 108
Trabajo de jorge  108Trabajo de jorge  108
Trabajo de jorge 108
 
1. konsep dasar_1
1. konsep dasar_11. konsep dasar_1
1. konsep dasar_1
 
Lateral training
Lateral trainingLateral training
Lateral training
 
Homo erectus
Homo erectusHomo erectus
Homo erectus
 
10 prinsip ekonomi
10 prinsip ekonomi10 prinsip ekonomi
10 prinsip ekonomi
 
Islas Galápagos
Islas GalápagosIslas Galápagos
Islas Galápagos
 
Com
ComCom
Com
 

Similar a Focus

Overview of ethics and information technology
Overview of ethics and information technologyOverview of ethics and information technology
Overview of ethics and information technologySJBennett228
 
INTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docx
INTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docxINTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docx
INTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docxnormanibarber20063
 
Health Care Ethics documents designed fo
Health Care Ethics documents designed foHealth Care Ethics documents designed fo
Health Care Ethics documents designed foCynthiaLuay3
 
Week 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdf
Week 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdfWeek 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdf
Week 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdfARVINCRUZ16
 
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docxhoney725342
 
Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1Andy Lopez
 
Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)
Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)
Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)Mario Phillip
 
Ethics 1228346034059584-8
Ethics 1228346034059584-8Ethics 1228346034059584-8
Ethics 1228346034059584-8Mario Phillip
 
Chapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docx
Chapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docxChapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docx
Chapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docxtiffanyd4
 

Similar a Focus (12)

What is ethics.pptx
What is ethics.pptxWhat is ethics.pptx
What is ethics.pptx
 
Overview of ethics and information technology
Overview of ethics and information technologyOverview of ethics and information technology
Overview of ethics and information technology
 
INTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docx
INTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docxINTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docx
INTRODUCTION THINKING ETHICALLY A Framework for Moral Decisio.docx
 
Health Care Ethics documents designed fo
Health Care Ethics documents designed foHealth Care Ethics documents designed fo
Health Care Ethics documents designed fo
 
Week 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdf
Week 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdfWeek 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdf
Week 11 Ethical Decision Making (1).pdf
 
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
- Government InvolvementBioethics Environmental Ethics.docx
 
Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1Notes for exam 1
Notes for exam 1
 
Moral Relativism Essay
Moral Relativism EssayMoral Relativism Essay
Moral Relativism Essay
 
Ethical Argument Paper
Ethical Argument PaperEthical Argument Paper
Ethical Argument Paper
 
Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)
Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)
Ethics 1228346034059584-8 (1)
 
Ethics 1228346034059584-8
Ethics 1228346034059584-8Ethics 1228346034059584-8
Ethics 1228346034059584-8
 
Chapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docx
Chapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docxChapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docx
Chapter 9. Can We Reason about MoralityChapter 8Can We Re.docx
 

Focus

  • 1. university of cape coast SCHOOL OF BUSINESS DEPARTMENT OF MANAGEMENT STUDIES LECTURER: DR.ABORAMPA AMOAH MENSAH ASSIGNMENT: BUS 207 Question: Ghanaians revere the affluent without questioning the sources of their wealth. Garrett proportionality framework is therefore of no relevance to them. Discuss. INDEX NUMBER :SB/BMS/13/0045 11/12/2014
  • 2. Introduction Our Ghanaian societies are structured in a way that respect is given to someone according to the measure of his or her riches. Everything in our societies is controlled by the affluent (rich men) who are citizens in that society. Before a child begins to attend school, there is the ambition of wealth creation in his or her mind. Wealth has been the only instrument that commands respect in Ghana. This is because success is measured according to materiality. If someone want to tease his or her enemy, the best way is to expensive clothing or prepare a delicious meal if only they stay in the same house or even do something that shows riches. As a result of the ambition for wealth by most Ghanaians, our able youths are travelling oversees for greener pastures. Most of these youths travel by illegal means (stoway), others to by stealing family properties or other fraudulent means in order to fetch him or her some money to live by. Our family system is structured in a way that the poor is regarded as a failure, as a result, his or her (the poor) contribution in the family meeting is not adhered to. It does not matter the wisdom in what they (the poor) say, all that drives Ghanaians is riches but not advice. If a member of a family arrives from oversees, he or she wi ll be regarded as an important figure in the family, and whatever he or she says is final. It does not matter whether what he or she is saying contains senses all because such a person has money on herself or himself. These people have refused to ask the sources of their family member’s riches. Children are refusing to ask their parent the sources of their wealth, parent are also not asking the sources of their children riches. The only question that comes into their mind is “what kind of job do you do?” whatever reply given them is final. Instead of the children and the parent to find out whether what was told is true or not , they rather hail their parent or children for their good works. Ghanaians have generated the attitude of measuring success with goodness. Thus, the more good you are the more success (deontological theory) which has been a historical issue. This issue has driven people who engage in fraudulent means for wealth to rather do good in their society in order for them to be seen as good citizens. Most corrupt individuals are engaging in charity and orphanage foundations just to hide their intensions. Our churches have been made in such a way that the rich men (affluent) are given Eldership positions without questioning then source of their wealth. Such people have used the church to cover their evil means of creating wealth. During appeal for funds, harvest or even fund raising, they (the affluent in church) will be quoting the highest bid for a clap from the congregation. The desperation for money by modern pastors has created way for corrupt citizens to be in the church with no fear of God. This attitude has defiled our churches, because the congregation too has refused to question the source of the affluent wealth. The ambition for wealth creation has made doctors to use fraud and also have lost their integrity in serving the nation. Today doctors are building their own private hospitals and no one has ever asked them the sources of their wealth.
  • 3. Small thief in society is regarded as a menace to the society and is even imprisoned but the great thief for example, the business man Alfred Agbesi Woyome is now regarded a hero although he has used fraud to take GHC52.1 million from the government. His name has been in dailies reports and the television but not regarded as a thief. Even his thievery has given political parties opportunity to make unnecessary propaganda. Therefore, Ghanaians regard the most corrupt as a hero without thinking the consequence of their (the corrupt) actions to the nation. After all, they have been a blessing to others lives. . Affluent: this refers to having an abundance of wealth, property, or other material goods; prosperous; rich: an affluent person.(encyclopedia) Garrett’s proportionality framework (1966) Garrett provides what is termed a ‘proportionality’ framework and is usefully compared with Ross’s prima facie duties framework. His framework combines the utilitarian concern with outcomes (consequences) with the Kantian preoccupation with process (intentions and means). For Garrett, ethical decisions comprise three components: intention, means and end. The sequence in the decision-making model then becomes: · Intention or that which is willed. What is the motivation behind a person’s actions? Are the intentions ethical? · Means. What methods or processes are used to bring about certain ends? Are they ethical? An unforeseen harm, resulting from risk, is permissible because it is not willed (intended). A foreseen harm, however, is only permissible if there is a proportionate reason for taking the risk of the harm. For instance, it is permissible when the outcomes will be clearly of great good and the risks are minimal (the notion of restricted risk). · End. Garrett’s view is that ends should be measured in terms of the intrinsic value (nature) foreseen of the acts rather than by the consequences produced by these acts. In other words, the end should not justify the means. Also, his notion of restricted responsibility should not be applied in the sense that anything is permissible if the ends justify the means. The Garrett proportionality framework combines the deontological theory with the utilitarian theory. These theories are explained below. Deontological ethics The word deontology comes from the Greek roots deon, which means duty, and logos, which means science. Thus, deontology is the "science of duty." Key questions which deontological ethical systems ask include: What is my moral duty?
  • 4. What are my moral obligations? How do I weigh one moral duty against another? Deontological ethics, in philosophy, ethical theories that place special emphasis on the relationship between duty and the morality of human actions. Deontology (Greek Deon, “duty,” and logos, “science”) consequently focuses on logic and ethics. No attempt is made in such theories to explicate specific moral obligations. In deontological ethics an action is considered morally good because of some characteristic of the action itself, not because the product of the action is good. Deontological ethics holds that at least some acts are morally obligatory regardless of their consequences for human welfare. Descriptive of such ethics are such expressions as “Duty for duty’s sake,” “Virtue is its own reward,” and “Let justice be done though the heavens fall.” By contrast, teleological ethics holds that the basic standard of morality is precisely the value of what an action brings into being. Deontological theories have been termed formalistic because their central principle lies in the conformity of an action to some rule or law. The first great philosopher to define deontological principles was Immanuel Kant, the 18th-century German founder of critical philosophy, whose ethics were much influenced by Christianity as well as by the Rationalism of the Enlightenment. Kant held that nothing is good without qualification except a good will, which is one that wills to act in accord with the moral law and out of respect for that law, rather than out of natural inclinations. He saw the moral law as a categorical imperative—i.e., an unconditional command—and believed that its content could be established by human reason alone. Reason begins with the principle “Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law.” Kant’s critics, however, have questioned his view that all duties can be derived from this purely formal principle and have argued that, in his preoccupation with rational consistency; he neglected the concrete content of moral obligation. This objection was faced in the 20th century by the British philosopher W.D. Ross, who held that numerous “prima facie duties,” rather than a single formal principle for deriving them, are themselves immediately self-evident. Ross distinguished these prima facie duties (such as promise keeping, reparation, gratitude, and justice) from actual duties, for “any possible act has many sides to it which are relevant to its rightness or wrongness”; and these facets have to be weighed before “forming a judgment on the totality of its nature” as an actual obligation in the given circumstances. Types of Deontological Ethics Some examples of deontological ethical theories: Divine Command: the most common forms of deontological moral theories are those which derive their set of moral obligations from a god. According to many Christians, for example, an action is morally correct whenever it is in agreement with the rules and
  • 5. duties established by God. Duty Theories: an action is morally right if it is in accord with some list of duties and obligations. Rights Theories: an action is morally right if it adequately respects the rights of all humans (or at least all members of society). This is also sometimes referred to as Libertarianism, the political philosophy that people should be legally free to do whatever they wish so long as their actions do not impinge upon the rights of others. Contractarianism: an action is morally right if it is in accordance with the rules that rational moral agents would agree to observe upon entering into a social relationship (contract) for mutual benefit. This is also sometimes referred to as Contractualism. Monistic Deontology: an action is morally right if it agrees with some single deontological principle which guides all other subsidiary principles. Problems with Deontological Ethics A common criticism of deontological moral systems is that they provide no clear way to resolve conflicts between moral duties. a deontological moral system should include both a moral duty not to lie and one to keep others from harm, for example, but in the above situation how is a person to choose between those two moral duties? A popular response to this is to simply choose the "lesser of two evils," but that means relying on which of the two has the least evil consequences and, therefore, the moral choice is being made on a consequentialitist rather than a deontological basis. Some critics argue that deontological moral systems are, in fact, consequentialist moral systems in disguise. According to this argument, duties and obligations which set forth in deontological systems are actually those actions which have been demonstrated over long periods of time to have the best consequences. Eventually, they become enshrined in custom and law and people stop giving them or their consequences much thought — they are simply assumed to be correct. Deontological ethics are thus ethics where the reasons for particular duties have been forgotten, even if things have completely changed. A second criticism is that deontological moral systems do not readily allow for grey areas where the morality of an action is questionable. They are, rather, systems which are based upon absolutes — absolute principles and absolute conclusions. In real life, however, moral questions more often involve grey areas than absolute black & white choices. We typically have conflicting duties, interests, and issues that make things difficult.
  • 6. Another common criticism of deontological ethical theories is the question of just which duties qualify as those which we should all follow, regardless of the consequences. Duties which might have been valid in the 18th century are not necessarily valid now, but who is to say which ones should be abandoned and which are still valid? And if any are to be abandoned, how can we say that they really were moral duties back in the 18th century? If these were duties created by God, how can they possibly stop being duties today? Many attempts to develop deontological systems focus on explaining how and why certain duties are valid at any time or at all times and how we can know that. Religious believers are often in the difficult position of trying to explain what believers of the past treated certain duties as objective, absolute ethical requirements created by God but today they aren't — today we have different absolute, objective ethical requirements created by God. These are all reasons why irreligious atheists rarely subscribe to deontological ethical systems, though it can't be denied that they can at times have ethical insights to offer. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism Because deontological theories are best understood in contrast to consequentialist ones, a brief look at consequentialism and a survey of the problems with it that motivate its deontological opponents, provides a helpful prelude to taking up deontological theories themselves. Consequentialists hold that choices—acts and/or intentions—are to be morally assessed solely by the states of affairs they bring about. Consequentialists thus must specify initially the states of affairs that are intrinsically valuable—often called, collectively, “the Good.” They then are in a position to assert that whatever choices increase the Good, that is, bring about more of it, are the choices that it is morally right to make and to execute. (The Good in that sense is said to be prior to “the Right.”) Consequentialists can and do differ widely in terms of specifying the Good. Some consequentialists are monists about the Good. Utilitarians, for example, identify the Good with pleasure, happiness, desire satisfaction, or “welfare” in some other sense. Other consequentialists are pluralists regarding the Good. Some of such pluralists believe that how the Good is distributed among persons (or all sentient beings) is itself partly constitutive of the Good, whereas conventional utilitarians merely add or average each person's share of the Good to achieve the Good's maximization. Moreover, there are some consequentialists who hold that the doing or refraining from doing, of certain kinds of acts are themselves intrinsically valuable states of affairs constitutive of the Good. An example of this is the positing of rights not being violated, or duties being kept, as part of the Good to be maximized—the so-called “utilitarianism of rights” (Nozick 1974).
  • 7. None of these pluralist positions erase the difference between consequentialism and deontology. For the essence of consequentialism is still present in such positions: an action would be right only insofar as it maximizes these Good-making states of affairs being caused to exist. However much consequentialists differ about what the Good consists in, they all agree that the morally right choices are those that increase (either directly or indirectly) the Good. Moreover, consequentialists generally agree that the Good is “agent-neutral” (Parfit 1984; Nagel 1986). That is, valuable states of affairs are states of affairs that all agents have reason to achieve without regard to whether such states of affairs are achieved through the exercise of one's own agency or not. Consequentialism is frequently criticized on a number of grounds. Two of these are particularly apt for revealing the temptations motivating the alternative approach to deontic ethics that is deontology. The two criticisms pertinent here are that consequentialism is, on the one hand, overly demanding, and, on the other hand, that it is not demanding enough. The criticism regarding extreme demandingness runs like this: for consequentialists, there is no realm of moral permissions, no realm of going beyond one's moral duty (supererogation), no realm of moral indifference. All acts are seemingly either required or forbidden. And there also seems to be no space for the consequentialist in which to show partiality to one's own projects or to one's family, friends, and countrymen, leading some critics of consequentialism to deem it a profoundly alienating and perhaps self-effacing moral theory (Williams 1973). On the other hand, consequentialism is also criticized for what it seemingly permits. It seemingly demands (and thus, of course, permits) that in certain circumstances innocents be killed, beaten, lied to, or deprived of material goods to produce greater benefits for others. Consequences—and only consequences—can conceivably justify any kind of act, for it does not matter how harmful it is to some so long as it is more beneficial to others. A well-worn example of this over-permissiveness of consequentialism is that of a case standardly called, Transplant. A surgeon has five patients dying of organ failure and one healthy patient whose organs can save the five. In the right circumstances, surgeon will be permitted (and indeed required) by consequentialism to kill the healthy patient to obtain his organs, assuming there are no relevant consequences other than the saving of the five and the death of the one. Likewise, consequentialism will permit (in a case that we shall call, Fat Man) that a fat man be pushed in front of a runaway trolley if his being crushed by the trolley will halt its advance towards five workers trapped on the track. We shall return to these examples later on. Consequentialists are of course not bereft of replies to these two criticisms. Some retreat from maximizing the Good to “satisficing”—that is, making the achievement of only a certain level of the Good mandatory (Slote 1984). This move opens up some space for personal projects and relationships, as well as a realm of the morally permissible. It is not clear, however, that satisficing is adequately motivated, except to
  • 8. avoid the problems of maximizing. Nor is it clear that the level of mandatory satisficing can be nonarbitrarily specified, or that satisficing will not require deontological constraints to protect satisficers from maximizers. Another move is to introduce a positive/negative duty distinction within consequentialism. On this view, our (negative) duty is not to make the world worse by actions having bad consequences; lacking is a corresponding (positive) duty to make the world better by actions having good consequences (Bentham 1789 (1948); Quinton 2007). We thus have a consequentialist duty not to kill the one in Transplant or in Fat Man; and there is no counterbalancing duty to save five that overrides this. Yet as with the satisficing move, it is unclear how a consistent consequentialist can motivate this restriction on all-out optimization of the Good. Yet another idea popular with consequentialists is to move from consequentialism as a theory that directly assesses acts to consequentialism as a theory that directly assesses rules—or character-trait inculcation—and assesses acts only indirectly by reference to such rules (or character-traits) (Alexander 1985). Its proponents contend that indirect consequentialism can avoid the criticisms of direct (act) consequentialism because it will not legitimate egregious violations of ordinary moral standards—e.g., the killing of the innocent to bring about some better state of affairs—nor will it be overly demanding and thus alienating each of us from our own projects. The relevance here of these defensive maneuvers by consequentialists is their common attempt to mimic the intuitively plausible aspects of a non-consequentialist, deontological approach to ethics. For as we shall now explore, the strengths of deontological approaches lies: (1) in their categorical prohibition of actions like the killing of innocents, even when good consequences are in the offing; and (2) in their permission to each of us to pursue our own projects free of any constant demand that we shape those projects so as to make everyone else well off. Consequences resulting from the reverence Ghanaians give to the affluent Ghanaians have hyped the affluent in society in such a way that the poor is not recognized as an important figure n our society. The rich in our societies have used their wealth to control the minds of most Ghanaians which have prevented them from discovering the source of the rich’s wealth. There is a saying that “money answers everything”, so the outcome of the affluent actions is not considered. I would like to stress some consequences emanating from these attitudes of Ghanaians towards the affluent. These are:  Increase in Non Governmental Organizations (NGO)  The creation of power  Societal corruption
  • 9. The affluent in Ghana have used nongovernmental organizations as a means of preventing people from discovering the sources of their wealth. These days if a person wants to be recognized in society as a good person, the best is to engage in or establish charity foundations or orphanage which is also beneficial to the vulnerable in society. This is an opportunity Ghanaians have given to the affluent without making any internal and effective control measures to check or verify what actually the affluent the resources to undertake such projects those who take it upon themselves to ask of the source of their wealth are answered that funds are being solicited from various corporate bodies and institutions to support the project. Meanwhile this may not be the case, it is a justification for fraudulent activity they have engaged in. managers In corporate institutions are embezzling funds, District Chief executives are using common funds for their own personal interest, Ministers are appropriating the budget for a project in order to to use the remaining money for their own benefit., etc. Today, politicians and their relatives are engaging in charity foundations with the intension to cover their corrupt attitudes. For example, the first lady of Ghana, Mrs. Lordina Mahama , has been running charity foundations that enhances health promotion and advocacy and encourage women employment through capacity building and sustained income generation among other benefits that has made her a woman who listens, love and care for others especially the less privileged, children and women. A look at her work through the Lordina Foundation shows that the foundation has helped in areas such as orphanage support, support for Persons Living with HIV/AIDS, Scholarships for brilliant but needy students, promoting women’s empowerment through entrepreneurship, raising awareness and advocating for cervical and breast cancer prevention and treatment. The foundation is also providing suitable accommodation for ostracized women in “Witch Camps and still goes to the aid of the weak, sick and lass privileged in society. According to her, the multiplier effects of such philanthropic gestures will help many indigent people in the society to become self reliant by getting employment. The first Lady is described by the less privileged in society as an honest and intelligent woman-” a great mother and a comforter”. She is described by many as a source of encouragement in her advocacy for health, Education, peace and unity in the country. Ghana’s First lady, Lordina Mahama have received recognition from development partners and organizations in the USA and across the globe for her philanthropic work through the Lordina Foundation in Ghana and being active in helping in his husband’s social policy interventions such as the development of deprived children and women in both rural and urban areas of Ghana. Although it is a good project, nobody has ever questioned her source of her wealth. I am saying this because when Mrs. Lordina mahama was not the first lady, she was not engaging in this philanthropic foundation. According to the utilitarian theory, which states that the consequence of your action must bring more happiness to the greater number of people and less harm to the least number of people (Jeremy Bentham), this project is very welcoming in Ghana because it has helped many people from perishing
  • 10. through sickness. Whereas, deontological theory states that doing good or bad does not base on the consequence of your action. This is a situational issue because a person is seen as good in Ghana if the society benefit from him or her no matter he consequences the goodness will bring to society. For instance, if Mrs. Lordina Mahama is embezzling funds from the government coffers in undertaken this project then, the consequences will badly affect the state’s financial position with the intension (according to Garrett proportionality framework) of gaining political power at the end. Most affluent in Ghana are revered for the good they do to their societies although they might be engaging in ‘juju’ for blood money. These and many more are some opportunities Ghanaians have given to the affluent in society. The reverence Ghanaians give to the affluent has given them power to control everything in societies in fraudulent manner. Our Ghanaian family system is structured in a way that the rich men in the family are recognized as the backbone of the family. Because of this, the influence the rich have on the family is very high. When it comes to family meeting the rich are always recognized, they (rich0 decisions to suit their own interest, any decision made against their interest will be disregarded by them because they (the rich) are those the whole family looks onto when problems evolves. This issue has compelled most people the ambition for riches even if the means are not there. Parents are forcing their children in bringing huge sums of money to their house. Our family system has been a platform to show one’s riches and belongings. Most people are embezzling funds from their workplaces, others are using lies to claim huge sums of money from people, others also are killing to get wealth, and whiles others are also dealing in drugs for wealth without questioning them the source of their wealth. Today, the one in flashy cars, who wears expensive clothing, living in beautiful house etc, is seen as a rich person and is therefore respected by Ghanaians but the person who is not riding in posh cars and in expensive clothing is seen as an ordinary man, lazy man, poor man etc. this attitude has also given the affluent the opportunity to seek for political power. Societal corruption The complexity of our social structure is such that those who succeed can hide their corruption. Corruption is seen only when someone fails. If you succeed no one will know that you have been corrupt; success will hide everything. You have only to succeed and you will become a pinnacle of goodness, thus you will become everything that is good, pure, and innocent. That means you can succeed in any way you like, but you must succeed. Once you succeed, once you are successful, nothing that you may have done is wrong.
  • 11. This has been true throughout history. A person is only a thief if he is a small thief. If he is a great thief, then he becomes an Alexander the Great, a hero. No one ever sees that there is no qualitative difference between the two, that it is only a qualitative difference. No one will call Alexander the Great a great thief because the measure of your goodness is success: the more successful you are the more good. Means are only questioned if you are failure, then you will be called both corrupt and a fool. If this is the attitude, how is it possible to create an uncorrupt society? To ask a person to be moral in this immoral situation is to ask something absurd. An individual cannot be moral in an immoral society. If he tries to be moral, his morality will only make his egoistic and ego is as immoral and corrupt as anything else. This situation is a human creation. We have created a society with a mad rush for wealth, power, politics; we go on supporting it, and then we ask why there is corruption. Where there is ambition, corruption will be the logical consequence. You cannot check corruption unless the whole basic structure that encourages ambitions is destroyed. In conclusion Our Ghanaian societies are structured in a way that respect is given to someone according to the measure of his or her riches. Everything in our societies is controlled by the affluent (rich men) who are citizens in that society Wealth has been the only instrument that commands respect in Ghana. This is because success is measured according to materiality Ghanaians have generated the attitude of measuring success with goodness. Thus, the more good you are the more success (deontological theory) which has been a historical issue. This issue has driven people who engage in fraudulent means for wealth to rather do good in their society in order for them to be seen as good citizens. Most corrupt individuals are engaging in charity and orphanage foundations just to hide their intensions. Garrett provides what is termed a ‘proportionality’ framework and is usefully compared with Ross’s prima facie duties framework. His framework combines the utilitarian concern with outcomes (consequences) with the Kantian preoccupation with process (intentions and means). For Garrett, ethical decisions comprise three components: intention, means and end In philosophy, Deontological ethics refers to ethical theories that place special emphasis on the relationship between duty and the morality of human actions. In deontological ethics an action is considered morally good because of some characteristic of the action itself, not because the product of the action is good.
  • 12. Deontological ethics holds that at least some acts are morally obligatory regardless of their consequences for human welfare. Descriptive of such ethics are such expressions as “Duty for duty’s sake,” “Virtue is its own reward,” and “Let justice be done though the heavens fall.” Some examples of deontological ethical theories are Divine Command, Duty Theories, Contractarianism, Rights Theories, Monistic Deontology. A common criticism of deontological moral systems is that they provide no clear way to resolve conflicts between moral duties Some critics argue that deontological moral systems are, in fact, consequentialist moral systems in disguise. A second criticism is that deontological moral systems do not readily allow for grey areas where the morality of an action is questionable. Another common criticism of deontological ethical theories is the question of just which duties qualify as those which we should all follow, regardless of the consequences. Consequences resulting from the reverence Ghanaians give to the affluent are Increase in Non Governmental Organizations (NGO), the creation of power, societal corruption. Ghanaians have revered the affluent as a result of their goodness without questioning them the source of their wealth. References Alexander, L., 1985, “Pursuing the Good—Indirectly,” Ethics, 95(2): 315–332. Brook, R., 2007, “Deontology, Paradox, and Moral Evil,” Social Theory and Practice, 33(3): 431–40. encyclopedia Kant, Immanuel. 1785. “First Section: Transition from the Common Rational Knowledge of Morals to the Philosophical”, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Waller, Bruce N. 2005. Consider Ethics: Theory, Readings, and Contemporary Issues. New York: Pearson Longman: 23