SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 18
Download to read offline
Memory, "Mimesis," Tragedy: The Scene before Philosophy
Author(s): Paul A. Kottman
Reviewed work(s):
Source: Theatre Journal, Vol. 55, No. 1, Ancient Theatre (Mar., 2003), pp. 81-97
Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25069181 .
Accessed: 23/09/2012 12:10

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

.




                The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
                Theatre Journal.




http://www.jstor.org
Memory, Mimesis, Tragedy:
                            The Scene Before Philosophy

                                                               Paul A. Kottman


                                                                  "Life   is the non-representable              origin    of representation."
                                                                                                                                        Derrida
                                                                                                                          ?Jacques




   The historical complicity of Greek tragedy with the emergence of the Athenian polis
has interested political thinkers and classicists alike for some time.1 Among classicists,
this interest has tended tomanifest      itself either in an analysis of particular dramatists;2
or certain thematic, conceptual, or linguistic patterns within        individual tragic works.3
In short, the political stakes of the theatre have derived from the exegetical analysis of
the theatrical works      themselves    in relation to their context of origin.4 The pre
dominance      that this sort of exegesis       continues   to enjoy is due not only to the
philological   care and attention with which classicists, especially, tend to proceed but
also to a tendency to understand     the dramatic work itself (both the textual artifact, and
whatever            the archives retain of its context of origin) as the repository of political or
social meaning.           And this means,    consequently,   that the political nature of tragedy is
 implicitly         regarded by  such amethodology      as an effect of the mimetic  character of the



Paul   A. Kottman        is Assistant                               at SUNY                     and Adjunct
                                        Professor    of English                  Albany,                         Professor      of
               Studies    at New    York University.   He    is currently             his first    book, tentatively    entitled
Performance                                                               revising
Between     Actors     and Witnesses:       A Politics     of the Scene.       His     recent                      include     the
                                                                                                  publications
Introduction           to                 Narratives,          by Adriana    Cavarero, and articles on Shakespeare                        and
                            Relating                                                                                                            literary
 theory      that have                        in Shakespeare         Studies   and The Oxford     Literary Review.
                             appeared



    1
     See, as a start, Karen Hermassi,      Polity and Theater in Historical  Perspective    (Berkeley: University      of
California    Press,   1977), and J. Peter Euben,  ed., Greek Tragedy and Political Theory (Berkeley: University
of California     Press,   1986), and The Tragedy of Political  Theory (Princeton:     Princeton                  Press,
                                                                                                    University
 1990); some of the essays         in John Winkler    and Froma Zeitlin,    ed., Nothing      to Do With Dionysus?:
Athenian   Drama     in Its Social Context     (Princeton:  Princeton    University     Press,  1990).
   2                                                    on
     See, for example,     Charles    Segal's work                        Iwill  return to Segal     later in this article.
                                                           Euripides.
    3
    One might     think, for example,       of the various                          of Antigone  over the past
                                                            political   readings                                   thirty years
or of Froma Zeitlin's       and Nicole    Loraux's work      on                      and ritual in the Greek       context.
                                                                  gender, myth,
   4
     For a good account       of the German       roots of this philological     methodology,
                                                                                                   as well   as its relation   to
more                                      to interpretations       of Greek                 see Simon Goldhill,        "Modern
            archaeological            approaches                                tragedy,
Critical                               to Greek        in The Cambridge        Companion       to Greek Tragedy,       ed. P. E.
              Approaches                            Tragedy,"
Easterling     (Cambridge:     Cambridge     University      Press,   1997), 324-48.      Even    the most    philosophically
 inclined   classicists  tend to insist upon       the exegetical      character    of their labor. Notably,        Jean-Pierre
Vernant    has offered     a number    of eloquent     and convincing       defenses     of careful   contextual                of
                                                                                                                     analysis
classical      Greek        works.      See   especially   Jean-Pierre Vernant,         "Greek                      Problems         of    Interpreta
                                                                                                     Tragedy:
 tion,"     in The Structuralist            Controversy,    ed. Richard Macksey           and    Eugenio         Donato        (Baltimore:       Johns
Hopkins        University            Press,  1970), 273-95.


                   Theatre      Journal       55 (2003)   81-97   ?   2003 by The    Johns Hopkins                             Press
                                                                                                           University
82        /       PaulA. Kottman

dramatic work. The determination                          of tragedy as first and foremost amimetic work in
turn reduces the political essence                        of tragedy to the legible features of this or that
production.


  Among political thinkers, the situation is perhaps more complex. Hannah Arendt, in
an exemplary     and influential discussion     of the origins of tragedy, declared that "the
theater is the political art par excellence; only there is the political sphere of human life
transposed    into art."5 For Arendt,    the political essence of the theatre arises from its
"pre-philosophical"     presentation   of human affairs.6 By "pre-philosophical,"     Arendt
simply  means    that the theatre is an experience of speech and action as pure actuality,
 through which each actor reveals "who" s/he is by speaking and acting among others.
 Indeed, from Arendt's perspective,        the theatre?like    the praxis it imitates?is     also pre
political,   for it is precisely the interaction that adheres in speaking and action among
a plurality that opens the space of the polis.7 Thus, what makes the theatre
                                                                                         political, in
Arendt's view, is not the imitative or mimetic         quality   of the work as such; rather it is
 the fact that tragedy "imitates" "man in his relation to others."8 Put simply, it is the
relationality of the scene that lends the theater its political sense.
   Given   these seemingly contradictory  approaches    to the problem, one is thus left to
wonder:    does the political   essence of the theatre arise from a pre-philosophical
theatrical experience    as such? Or, does the political nature of theatrical experience
come from the mimetic or imitative quality of the dramatic work, as the philosophical
 tradition        since Plato defines            it?

    Before addressing     these questions myself,     itmay be helpful to recall that already
with Aristotle,   one finds significant resistance to the Platonic definition of tragedy as
poetic production      (poiesis) or m?meseos en ontos. Indeed, it was precisely      in order to
 assert a political   sense for tragedy?over        and against Plato's banishment        of the
 tragedians   in the Republic?that     Aristotle defined    tragedy in the Poetics as m?meseos
praxis.9 For unlike the m?meseos en ontos which,         for Plato, made   the theatre a poetic
                     or work,       based     on mere                        that   lead   its audience              from    the
production                                                 appearances                                    astray

onto-theological      order of Ideas?Aristotle     sought to orient the theatre toward praxis.
This is why, as Jacques Taminiaux has demonstrated,           Arendt's   take on tragedy might
be read as a partial recuperation         of Aristotle's  rejoinder   to Plato.10 It is therefore
 important to note that the debate over how to account for the political essence of
tragedy?is      it a function of the mimetic, poetic work, or does it adhere in the scene of
action??is     a problem that is inscribed in Aristotle's      agon with Plato over the term
mimesis itself. For this reason, and others, the terms mimesis and mimetic         can hardly be



     5
     Hannah         Arendt,     The Human     Condition     (Chicago: University    of Chicago   Press,   1958), 188.
     61 take     the phrase     "pre-philosophical"       from Hannah    Arendt's    The Life ofMind    (New York: Harcourt
Brace,        1971), 129-40.
   7
   Hannah        Arendt,     The Human       Condition,    179-89.   For an excellent    discussion     of Arendt's    views   on
 action   and   the theatre, see lacques Taminiaux,             "From Aristotle    to Bios Theoretikos    and Tragic Theoria,"
 in The Thracian Maid and the Professional           Thinker (Albany: State University        of New York Press, 1997), 89
 121.
    8
     Arendt,     The Human        Condition,   188.
    9
      See Aristotle,     Poetics,    tran. Stephen    Halliwell     (Chapel Hill: University        of North   Carolina    Press,
 1998), 1449b,       25.
    10
      See note       5.
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                                    PHILOSOPHY /                                                83

used   in any univocal way; where I use them inwhat                                          follows,        I have   inmind        primarily
Plato's use of mimesis in Republic X.

    It is not my intention here to rehearse Aristotle's   riposte to his teacher in any detail;
it has already been the topic of numerous     studies.11 Nor am I interested in taking sides
in order to simply privilege Aristotle's views over those of Plato. Given the history and
character of the problem, which      Iwould    like to bear in mind throughout       this essay,
one can hardly hope to offer anything like a final solution.

   Instead, having outlined      the problem of how to relate the theatre to                                                  politics        in a
broad?albeit    cursory?fashion,      Iwould    like to approach it from another                                              perspective,
for itmay become clear along the way that the parameters of the ancient                                                       debate itself
can be shifted. In this spirit, Iwould    like to consider another way inwhich                                                 to articulate
a "pre-philosophical"   (i.e. not simply imitative or representational) political essence of
theatrical experience?one       which would    be irreducible   to the mimetic work, and
adhere in the living scene as such?by      returning to an ancient anecdote.
   Around    493 BCE one of the very first works of Greek tragedy?The      Fall of
                                                                                 Miletus by
 the tragic poet Phrynichus?was     staged   inAthens only two years after the events with
which it dealt actually occurred.12 No script of the play is extant, but it appears to have
been a theatrical representation   of a military defeat that the Milesians   suffered at the
hands   of the Persians.13 The play was therefore received not as a representation   of a
familiar myth, or distant       legend.14 Rather, the play presented   something that the
audience members       themselves    remembered,  and in so doing both brought about and
 confirmed           this living recollection.

       Indeed,      so unsettled       were         the Athenians      by what they saw that they were reduced
 to weeping.           Herodotus           provides         the following account of the audience's   reaction to
 the
        performance:

         The     Athenians        . . . showed      their profound      distress     at the loss of Miletus                 in a number           of
         ways,       but     in none       so            than   in their                    of Phrynichus7                         for when
                                              clearly                        reception                                    play;
         Phrynichus          produced      his Fall ofMiletus,     the audience       in the theater burst              into tears, and the
         author was          fined a thousand           drachmae       for reminding    them of a disaster            which     touched them
         so             [hos anamnesanta          oikeia kaka]. A      law was
             closely                                                              subsequently    passed              forbidding       anybody
         ever to                     on
                     put the play               stage   again.15

While   this account is, as far as is known,  the first surviving report of the earliest
performance    of a tragedy of which we are informed, The Fall ofMiletus was certainly



       11
        Two                      to start are: Gerald                Plato   and Aristotle     on
             good      places                                Else,                                   Poetry   (Chapel Hill:      University       of
North     Carolina      Press,    1986),    74-88; and      Stephen     Halliwell,     Aristotle's      Poetics                                   of
                                                                                                                  (Chicago:      University
Chicago   Press,  1986), 109-38,            331-36.
    12           on the date,
     For more                    see
                                     Joseph Roisman,                     "On Phrynichos'             Sack    of Miletus    and     Phoinissai,"
?ranos   86 (1988):    15-16. The    timeline at the                   end  of Easterling's            The                                     lists
                                                                                                              Cambridge     Companion
                                     as the first
Phyrnichus'      Fall ofMiletus                   tragedy on record, 352.
    13
      See William      Ridgeway,       The Origin    of Tragedy   (New York: Benjamin    Bloom,   1966), 66. See also,
Malcolm     Heath,    The Poetics of Greek Tragedy        (London: Duckworth,    1987), 67.
    14
      See Sir Hugh                        "Problems    of Early Greek Tragedy,"   in The Academic
                        Lloyd-Jones,                                                               Papers of Sir Hugh
Lloyd-Jones     (Oxford: Clarendon         Press, 1990), 230-33.
    15
     Herodotus,       The Histories,      tran. Aubrey     de Selincourt  (New York: Penguin      Books,   1966), 366,
 emphasis   mine.
84        /    PaulA. Kottman

not  the only play of its time to represent historical     events within   living memory.16
Phrynichus   himself returned to historical material     about fifteen years later with The
Phoenician Women (476?) and Aeschylus'       The Persians (472), the oldest extant work of
tragedy, portrayed   the defeat of the Persians at Salamis in 484. The obvious difference
between   The Fall of
                    Miletus and these later historical plays, of course, is the fact that the
latter did not (as far as is known)   lead to this sort of weeping;      additionally,  their
authors were not fined and the plays were not banned.

   Although      it is true that Herodotus     says that this reminder then led to the ban and
 fine, I shall be more concerned inwhat follows with the weeping           of the Athenians   than
with the fine and the ban that were subsequently             imposed,  since the act of weeping
 spontaneously      occurred on the scene itself. The fine came next, according toHerodotus,
while    the ban came later; they may have been anything but spontaneous.17 Thus, for
 the moment,       I would     like to focus on the scene of the actual performance            that
Herodotus      describes: namely,      the performance     of The Fall ofMiletus    and the tears
produced by the reminder of catastrophe. This may seem a counter-intuitive                 way to
proceed, given       that the ban and the fine have received the most attention from readers
of Herodotus'       account. However,     given how little we know about the actual motives
 for the fine and the ban, I would           like to focus instead upon the more        immediate
 connection, manifested     on the scene described                            by Herodotus,           between        the Athenians'
memory      of the catastrophe and their tears.

    It is, of course, hardly surprising     to find an audience weeping       at the close of a
 tragedy.  What     is striking, however,    is the way    in which    the tears described    by
Herodotus     do not appear to be a manifestation       of katharsis, nor do the tears seem to
 result primarily from the mimetic      force of Phrynichus'    play. Indeed, already a certain
revision of Aristotle's     account of tragedy in the Poetics is in order; for the tears that
 resulted from the performance       of The Fall ofMiletus     are not reducible solely to the
effect of its   "imitation of action" let alone to the plot or script of Phrynichus'       play.
                   the   lamentation        was      not      kathartic;          it didn't                   to   have    educated,
Evidently                                                                                       appear
 instructed,               some moral; nothing was learned from Phrynichus' play.18 Nor
                   or instilled
does    it seem, according     to Herodotus,   that the audience wept because   they were
 simply    affected emotionally    by what   they saw,  the way a contemporary    audience
might    be affected by a play about the Second World War. Rather, it seems that their
 lamentation was the result of a shared recollection of a suffering that was theirs?oikeia


      16           on the authority                                         see
        For more                        of Herodotus'         account,            Joseph   Roisman,      "On Phrynichos'    Sack,"     16
 17, especially    n. 7.
    17
      Sir Hugh    Lloyd-Jones     has suggested     that the ban and fine were        imposed    because       of "an event

 connecting    Phrynichus    with   the archon Themistocles,"     who wanted       the Athenians        to prepare    for war

 against   the Persians    ("Problems,"    233-38).  Joseph  Roisman    has suggested       that this "interpretation        of
 the Phrynichus     affair in terms of the politics   of the time has proved                        ...            is known
                                                                                unsatisfactory           nothing
 of the play    to indicate whether     it was pro- or anti- Persian      in tone and message"           ("On Phrynichos'
 Sack," 16). In any event,        the ban   and   fine?like     most       acts of censorship?may             likely have had motives
 that extend   far beyond       the performance            of Phyrnichus'        play   itself. My       interest here,   rather, is the

specific  interaction     of the scene as such.
    18
     Obviously,      the term katharsis would     require a more      lengthy     interpretation      than can be provided
here. For a good overview         of the problem,     see
                                                          Stephen    Halliwell,     Aristotle's   Poetics, 350-57; Andrew
Ford, "Katharsis: The Ancient      Problem,"   in Performativity   and Performance,       ed. A. Parker and Eve Sedgwick

 (New York: Routledge       Press, 1995), 109-32; also see Jonathan Lear's contribution                to Essays on Aristotle's
Poetics, ed. Am?lie     Oksenberg    Rorty   (Princeton:   Princeton    University       Press,  1992), 315-40.
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                          PHILOSOPHY /                                       85

kaka, "something bad that touched home";                      the play "reminded                them"     [anamnesanta] of
what they already remembered.

  At   the very dawn of the Western       theatrical tradition, therefore, it is possible    to
glimpse   an effect of tragedy that differs markedly     from the way in which      theatrical
                                                                   a century later,
experience gets described by Plato and Aristotle more than                           descrip
tions which have characterized    thinking   about the theatre ever since. That is to say, it
may be possible       to discern           a singular, unrepeatable    and un-representable?and
 therefore "pre-philosophical"            scene?the   features of which are irreducible to the work
 that is performed.

   Clearly, Herodotus     is describing   a highly unusual     scene. Were Phrynichus'      play
performed    today, or even one hundred years after Phrynichus' death, weeping            from a
shared memory would be an unlikely result. This is not simply due to the fact that
such historical tragedies gained wider acceptance among the Athenians;           the point here
is not simply that Phrynichus       or the archon Themistocles     failed to make the material
palatable to the audience?although     it is true that, "after a perhaps tactful interval of
fifteen years or so" and after the defeat of the Persians           themselves   in 48(M79,
              and then Aeschylus   were able to stage historical dramas
Phyrnichus,                                                                    successfully.19
Rather, according    to Herodotus'  account,     the tears had to do precisely with          the
uniqueness   of that audience. Apparently     the tears were the manifestation     of a lived
recollection of a traumatic event, a memory          that of course died with the people who
bore it. The memory       in question is, of course, not an individual or private recollection
of a psychic     injury or trauma?but        rather a shared, public, mortal memory             of a
"catastrophe"     [kaka]. The term "memory"         therefore needs to be understood          in this
context as designating          an essential  part of the singular,         finite relation of the
spectatorship?for      it is this shared memory    that,  in large part, distinguishes    them from
all other potential audiences of the play. Indeed, what Herodotus'    description  of the
scene makes clear above all else is the singularity of this relation among witnesses.

   Thus; ^although Phrynichus was fined and the play censored, we ourselves might
hesitate before blaming        the tears exclusively    on the play or dramatic work        itself.
Phrynichus'     production    no doubt "imitated a complete action" (to use Aristotle's
definition)   that called to mind something        that those Athenians who saw itwished         to
forget.   But this "imitation of action" in and of itself would,         again,  not result in an
identical reaction were it performed         elsewhere, or at another time, before a different
group of spectators. What is decisive inHerodotus'           account is not the work by the poet
Phrynichus,    nor the form or content of the theatrical oeuvre, but rather the scene of its
singular performance       as it is recounted by the historian.

   Moreover     Iwould   like to suggest that this makes possible an analytical distinction,
which Iwill try to elaborate inwhat follows, between the scene and the work. That is
 to say, by relying upon Herodotus'      testimony we can see clearly that the scene itself?
 the actual   enactment of the play and spontaneous weeping           that followed?is   ulti
mately    irreducible to the work that was performed,    to any archival content or remnant
 that could survive the lives of those on the scene.


   19
    But   then, what would                the fact   that   "no known       Greek                after Aeschylus'      Persians
                               explain                                                tragedy
dealt with   a contemporary     theme    centered    on historical   events"?       See Paul     Cartledge,   "'Deep    Plays':
Theatre   as Process  in Greek Life,"    in Easterling,     The Cambridge                       24-25.
                                                                              Companion,
86        /      Paul A. Kottman


    In this spirit, I shall not begin with an exegesis of Phrynichus'      play itself, nor shall
 I attempt   to analyze the particular mode of its performance.20 Such an analysis would
be impossible       anyway, since no copy of the play's script is extant. It may            seem
 somewhat disingenuous         to take advantage of that fact; one would hardly like to rejoice
 in the loss or destruction of a play. But in this case, the very lack of the work, or text,
provides    a certain window       of opportunity, or, rather, the occasion for a critical and
methodological       purchase. That is to say, it produces a state of affairs in which one is
 forced, as it were,     to consider the theatrical experience     of the scene itself, through
Herodotus'              testimony,      as distinct        from the play or work.

     Of       course,     Herodotus   himself             gives us little to go on. We do not learn how
Phrynichus'             play was performed,              or what in the actors' speech or gesture would have
been particularly             unwelcome             to the Athenians.   In fact, it is as ifHerodotus    intuitively
                                                  of the  scene lay not in the performance      as such, but rather
grasped that the significance
with the reaction of the Athenians. While     this paucity of information might generate
 some frustration,   it is here something    of a bonus. For, in this case, Herodotus'
narration stands, interestingly,  in contrast to the sort of historical discourse of which
he is, according   to Cicero, the "father," since his focus is not so much        on what

happened but rather on the lived scene of that happening.21 It is the spectatorship,         and
not the spectacle, which      is decisive here. Or, better, it is that particular spectatorship
which   is decisive, for it is of those who constituted a community of witnesses,         in that
 they collectively   recalled the events recounted by Phrynichus'          play upon seeing it
performed.

   The Fall ofMiletus was what we might call a reminder that triggered this remem
brancer?but    itwas not itself fully responsible   for it, since, after all, the memory was
already   in the hearts of those Athenians      well before they attended          that ill-fated
performance.     Indeed, the fact that an audience    today would most likely not react in
the same manner means that those Athenians were already, prior to the performance,
 a                                                                       Their      shared      remembrance              of   the   capture       of
     unique      polity?or         potential        community.
Miletus   itself iswhat distinguishes   them from any other potential audience and what
makes their reaction so singular. This singularity is in fact what Herodotus'    account of
 the scene leads us to consider, for it becomes   clear that the  tears of those Athenians
 confirmed their collective recollection of the original battle.



     20                                                                                                               an excuse
       Obviously,         the fact that there is no extant script of Phyrnichus'                 play gives me                        to "refuse"
 to read it. Nevertheless,           even if the             were   extant, Iwould       want     to proceed with        a                       that
                                                    play                                                                   methodology
                                                                                                                          textual    traces from
 differs     somewhat        from that of classicists          who     interpret Greek drama based upon
 the period       and the philological          or social contexts         of the plays      themselves.      For my purposes            the point
  is not to debate         the extent     to which      a
                                                            comprehensive         reading    of a play by Sophocles,            for example,        is

                Rather,     Iwould                 note that?in         the case of Herodotus'           account    of Phrynichus,         we are
 possible.                              simply
 not reading        the play itself?but          rather trying to come to terms with Herodotus'                        testimony        regarding
 one                    scene. As a result, I cannot hope              to offer an account       of Herodotus'        testimony       that would
        particular
 derive      from our current understanding                   of Greek     tragedy     in its context,    for the context of the memory
 of the original battle is illegible and irretrievable.                  Rather, one might         begin    to look for ways        inwhich       the
                  of such understanding              is perhaps      put into question        by the anecdote       Herodotus          provides.
 possibility
      21                                                                                            from a lecture on Herodotus
       Cicero, De legibus 1,5; De oratore II, 55.1 take my cue here as well                                                                   given
                   White      at U. C. Berkeley            in the Fall, 1995. White          suggested       that Herodotus,         rather than
 by Hayden
                               facts or focusing          on the events         themselves,      creates memorable             scenes
  simply       imparting                                                                                                                   through
                      narrative      techniques.
  sophisticated
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                                           PHILOSOPHY /                                                87

   We    are dealing,                         a scene wherein
                                        therefore, with              the political    identity of the
                is not                                    a pre-existing                       class, or
participants                            simply defined
                                               through                    membership,
national affiliation?although        those attributes clearly play a role here?nor              through
 anything that they might have in common outside remembering                  the fall of Miletus and
witnessing     its theatrical representation.     In fact, this is borne out of a close reading of
Herodotus'     own account?in     which the nature of the recollection itself (hos anamnesanta
 oikeia kaka) hinges upon how one reads oikeia kaka, "their own catastrophe." As David
Rosenbloom       points out, in the period in question (478-456 BCE), "the relation between
 the inside and the outside of the city, between oikeia and allotria" was undergoing                    a
kind        of     transformation;             what        "one's          own"      means        here      is very    much        in
                                                                                                                                         question.22
 Indeed, the very fact that the Athenians    could identify themselves so strongly with the
Milesians,    such that the Milesians'   catastrophe   (kaka) refers "to the Athenians'    own
 troubles and misfortunes,"   underscores    the extent towhich the polity?in     its emergent
 form?is    defined not by fixed borders, allegiances,      or blood-ties.23 Rather, the polis
emerges    here, to borrow Arendt's phrase, as "a kind of organized remembrance."24 Put
simply, what defines and distinguishes        that spectatorship   of Athenians     from all other
potential    (or actual) spectatorship   of the play is the remembrance         they shared, and
their ability to confirm that remembrance       to one another.25 Or better, what defines their
relationship    is not something    that could be abstracted from, or that is foreign to, the
 scene  itself; rather, it arises from the living confirmation?the                                                     actual     relation?of             a
 shared remembrance made possible by the scene.

  Now,    it could be objected that my choice of Phrynichus'        The Fall of Miletus    is
somewhat disingenuous,     given both its peculiar content and the fact that the text did
not survive. What about, at the very least, Aeschylus'   The Persians, which   is an entire,
extant example of a tragedy whose subject matter was within the living memory          of its
 audience? In a sense, they make a natural pair. And admittedly, any comparison of the
 two ought to begin by asking why the earlier work was banned and its author fined,
while the later work won first prize at the festival? What was it that made The Fall of
Miletus so disagreeable   in comparison  to the well-received Persians?

       Interesting          as they are, however,                    Iwould            like to refrain from pursuing                     them here
 since                aim     is not    to                 the works              themselves,       but      rather    to focus     on     the    scene
           my                                analyze
of one particular performance.     Indeed pursuing    these questions presupposes    that the
tears produced by The Fall of  Miletus can be attributed, at some level, to the content or
the form of Phrynichus'    work?and        that Aeschlyus'    play succeeded,    as it were,
because          of    some      discernable           difference          between           the works        themselves.26       This      is, again,




       22
         See David      Rosenbloom, "Myth, History        and Hegemony        in Aeschylus,"      in History,    Tragedy, Theory,
 ed.     Barbara      Goff    (Austin:
                                 University       of Texas     Press,   1995), 102. Roisman          points    out that oikeia is

 "patently         contrasted"    with
                                   allotria throughout       Herodotus,     which    makes     Rosenbloom's         argument       all
 the more pertinent     for the passage       in question    here ("On Phrynichos'          Sack," 17-18).
    23
     Roisman,     "On Phrynichos'        Sack," 18-19.
    24
     Arendt,    The Human     Condition,     198.
    25
       It has been suggested      that the Athenians        wept     not just out of memory,          but in anticipation      of a
similar disaster. However,       there is no evidence        to support   such a view. On the contrary,           a close
                                                                                                                           reading
of Herodotus'      own    text appears      to suggest,                  that the conflation        of memory       and political
                                                            precisely,
              are very much     at stake here. See, again, Roiseman,             "On Phrynichos'         Sack."
belonging
    26
      Such differences     could be characterized          in any number       of ways.    Vernant,      for example,     suggests
 that     the events                                                were     not                          the Athenians,      in contrast        to their
                            presented        by Aeschylus                            regarded     by
88      /      Paul A. Kottman


precisely    the presupposition     that I wish    to challenge. By focusing on Herodotus'
narrative about a non-extant play?as         opposed     to reading The Persians?I would        like
 to strip bare some of our assumptions        about locating the political sense of tragedy in
 the legible features of any given work. The point, from my perspective,          is not finally to
determine why the Athenians wept at seeing The Fall of          Miletus, while The Persians was
 lauded. Given how little we know about the former, any explanation would                         be
 speculation   anyway. Put simply, I am interested instead in the fact that they wept, and
 the fact that this is the focus of Herodotus'     account of the scene. Rather than compare
 the two plays, therefore, it seems tome that a certain analytical purchase can be gained
by insisting here on the difference between           a singular scene, like the one to which
Herodotus     draws our attention, and a particular work like The Persians.

  Obviously, it is not always (though                     it is sometimes)   the case that the performance    of
a dramatic work     stages something                      that corresponds     so recognizably     to the lived
memory     of the spectators. Admittedly,                   the story that Herodotus    provides   is hardly the
most    typical sort of theatrical experience.         for that matter,
                                                                    Nor  is Aeschlyus' The
Persians. Indeed Imight imagine an ulterior    objection   tomy guiding example: What is
the political sense when what is performed, while itmay recount a familiar story, does
not correspond     to anyone's living memory,    for instance, in the case of a legend like
Oedipus,   or a morality play like Everyman, or for that matter, one of Samuel Beckett's
enigmatic    short works? One might    safely assume that Beckett's Waiting for Godot or
Luigi Pirandello's          Sei personaggi in cerca d'autore does not actively recount actual events
that any potential          spectator could remember as part of their own lived experience.27

  What,      then, could be said?from     the position proposed    in this essay?about      the
political   or communal significance of a performance     of a purely fictional work? Does
 it even make sense to speak, politically, of a rigorous distinction       between historical
works     (like The Fall ofMiletus or The Persians) and manifestly   fictional works?

  What Iwould        like to argue is that the political sense of the theatre is not to be found
in the distinction of any genre, form, or content of the work, nor even in any possible
referential relation between the play and an outside reality or history upon which            it is
closely  or loosely based. As far as the political essence of tragedy is concerned,            the
relation between      the artwork and reality, or between discourse and its outside, is not
decisive. What      is decisive   is the relation that is brought    into being by the scene?
through    the action and speech of those present, or through the performed affirmation
of a shared recollection.

     Consequently,        it does not matter whether a play is pure fiction (Beckett) or a history
play        (Shakespeare's Richard IJJ or Henry V). The genre of the work it is not essential




 reaction   to The Fall ofMiletus,     as "their own"      (Jean-Pierre   Vernant    and Pierre Vidal-Naquet,          Myth      and
            tran. Janet Lloyd       [New York: Zone Books,          1990], 245). My point, however,           is that whatever
Tragedy,
differences    one traces, the fact remains       that the singular     scene recounted     by Herodotus        is not reducible
to any describable       features of Phrynichus'       work.
    27                                                         in the United    States still make     disavowals      of this sort
                             motion    pictures  produced
      Symptomatically,
                that any relation between       the characters    and events of the film and actual persons              or events
by claming
are coincidental.      This disavowal,       of course,   seeks in principle      to affirm    (or hide behind)        a
                                                                                                                          rigorous
distinction    between    fiction and truth?while         at the same time                   or                   to, its possible
                                                                               admitting,        responding
 confusion.
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                                    PHILOSOPHY /                                                      89

here, nor is the dramatic work itself. For the Athenians,           at least inHerodotus'    view, the
political   value and significance of that peculiar early performance            of Phrynichus' play
 lay in the relation among those gathered, rather than in the Aristotelian             elements of the
performance       itself (mythos, lexis, opsis, etc.) or the historical meaning      of the capture of
Miletus.     Indeed, the relation that is inaugurated          by a shared remembrance          of the
original    scene is the theatrical scene that Herodotus         describes?quite       apart from any
 consideration of the artistry, representation,       or imitative
                                                                     quality of Phrynichus' The Fall
 ofMiletus.
    It is clear, after all, that the scenes recounted by Herodotus,         both the battle itself and
 its ill-fated theatrical resurrection?like          any singular   scene worthy   of the name?are
not reducible to representation,            imitation, or artistry. While   this may seem counter
intuitive, given the fact that we tend to think of a scene as that which             is representable
or repeatable by definition,          it is nevertheless    the singular unrepresentability      of the
scene that distinguishes        it from the work or the artifice. Indeed, it could even be said
that a scene becomes awork or an artifice precisely when it is abandoned                  to repetition
or                                        work                  in   some        sense      the                             or    effect      of     this
      re-presentation?the                           being                                          consequence
                     or continual
 "iterability"                              re-staging.28

    In contrast, while   the events of the battle of Miletus   (or, for that matter, the Trojan
       the French Revolution,     or the killings in Jenin) can be
war,                                                                  re-staged or represented
 (theatrically, verbally, televisually)  ad infinitum, well beyond      the lives of those who
were there, the lived relation of those on the scene?which             results from the actions
themselves, and the shared memory        they leave behind?absolutely       resists representa
tion or repetition beyond    their life span. Put formulaically, while any word or deed
{praxis, lexis) can be archived, recorded, or even re-enacted         (visibly, audibly) well
beyond   the time and place of the event itself, in a potentially   infinite way, the relation
of those on the scene ismortal and cannot be archived. It resists representation.

    For this reason, Iwish to argue, it is the relation?always     unique, each time brought
 into being either through words and deeds, or through a shared, living (and therefore
potentially   utterable) memory?which        constitutes  the scene as such, and is the most
essential condition     for any political sense. In short, a political account of theatrical
                             to             not     so much      with       an                    of what        is
experience           ought        begin                                          analysis                             performed            (whether
 the play is fictional or historical)?but     rather with an understanding        of the relational
aspect of the scene itself. In the same way, what happens          in a historical or journalistic
 sense ought not to be the final place for                                                 for it is
                                                   contemporary     political meaning,
precisely  the reduction of politics to the representable        content of this or that event,
which obscures the mortality       and fragility of the political relation, the lives, which are
at   stake.


   Back to the place of theatre in all this, it could be said that the performance                                                                  of a
fictional play or theatrical work?as   witnessed    by this or that spectatorship?is                                                                also
first and foremost itself an actual event that is immediately political regardless                                                                 of its
form     or     content.     In other      words,                    to any      consideration              of    its   form      or   content,         a
                                                        prior



     28
      Here     and                  this discussion,        I have   in mind
                      throughout                                                Jacques Derrida's      work     regarding     the
constitutive      nature of repetition     or                                     as in            to the literary work.    See,
                                               representation,     particularly           regards
for instance,     Derek Attridge's      interview with Derrida         in Acts of Literature   (New York: Routledge       Press,
1992).
90         /      Paul A. Kottman


 theatrical performance?like                          any combination                      of action and speech?is                      political       only
 if, and        insofar        as,   there      remains         ex                        more         than     one               who        can
                                                                      post     facto                                  person                          speak
 together         inmemory             of having           been on the scene with                        others.

      To    return        to   the                         of   the    scene,          therefore,       means         to return     to     the     relation
                                     essentiality
 that is brought about by the shared, living memory           of what is collectively witnessed?
a memory        that is, through a paradoxical     temporality which will need to be explored,
 constitutive     of the scene itself, even as it appears         to be merely     its consequence.
Whereas      a work or representation      survives through its radical indifference to the lives
of the witnesses,      the scene is nothing other than a lived relation that is?like the words
 and deeds    from which    it springs?absolutely    mortal and contingent. Unpredictability
 and mortality    are in fact constitutive   of the scene, for in order to be what it is a scene
 requires?without      any prior guarantee?that       someone speak in itsmemory, especially
 to and  for another who also bears that memory.      Therefore,    this subsequent   testi
mony?the     speech  that follows action?is not ontologically    separate  from the scene,
no matter how much time passes between scene and testimony. Rather, the subsequent
                     is the      scene's     most         essential          trait.
 testimony

  With          all of this in mind,
                                 Iwould    like now to situate that anomalous performance
 recounted    by Herodotus    within    the distinction between  scene and work      that I am
 elaborating.   For, inmy view, this is a distinction whose emergence       is contemporane
 ous, both historically    and conceptually, with the birth of tragedy in the traditional
 sense. Tragedy is born, according to tradition, precisely when the work breaks with the
 living scene and appears to stand alone as mimetic,        over and against the sociality of
 life?in        tension with               life, but always            at some distance                   from it.

   Where   does the performance      of Phrynichus'  play, which occurred alongside     the
birth of tragedy, fitwithin this history? Is there something within the logic of the scene
Herodotus    describes that resists the conventional wisdom    regarding the bond between
 tragedy  and the polis? Let me first give a brief summary of the dominant view.

     Now,  at first glance itmight appear that the sort of "common grief" (koinon achos)
provoked by Phrynichus' play resembles the sort of public weeping                 that has come to
be understood       as one of the defining characteristics of Greek tragedy, as it developed
especially    in the works of Euripides and Sophocles.29 According            to Charles Segal, for
 instance,   the staging of "rituals of lamentation" marks the emergence of a polis that
recognizes      and confirms      itself through the theatrical performance          of communal
practices,   such as collective grieving.30 The difference between this sort of performance
and the scene recounted by Herodotus,           of course, lies in the fact that Phrynichus' play
did not (as far as we know) stage this common grief within                 the performance     itself;
rather the performance        actually produced     it spontaneously   among those gathered. In
 this sense, the response of the audience is itself part of the action of the scene, over and
 beyond          the unpredictable                  character          of the performance                       itself. In other words,                 there
was        no   artifice,       no    ritualistic     character              to   their
                                                                                            grief.31



      29
       Koinon achos is a phrase  taken from the chorus at the end of Euripides'              Hippolytus,
                                                                                                          tran. Rober Bagg

 (Oxford: Oxford    University    Press,   1973), 1462.
    30
      See Charles   Segal, Euripides and the Poetics of Sorrow (Durham: Duke University                  Press,  1993).
    31                                                                                    scene that Herodotus
     Again,   this iswhy we are more        interested    in analyzing    the singular                            describes
 than we are in interpreting      the particular     character    of Phrynichus'    work.
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                              PHILOSOPHY /                                        91

   Nevertheless,      it is worth   pausing     briefly to consider  the difference  between
Herodotus'     account of Phrynichus'      play   and more contemporary   accounts of subse
quent works of Greek tragedy, which often contain scenes that explicitly perform or
 imitate acts of communal       lamentation. This will help make clearer the difference I am
 trying  to articulate between what        I am calling the scene and the work to which      it
remains        irreducible.

   The connection most     frequently drawn among modern        scholars between   the
evolution of tragedy and the theatrical appropriation or representation  of communal
life begins from the fact that a number of Greek tragedies appear self-consciously   to
appropriate                 rites of lamentation, or burial.32 In Sophocles' Antigone and
                      communal
Euripides' Hippolytus,   for example, we find climactic scenes in which       lamentation   is
both performed within      the drama and implicitly elicited from the audience as well.33
To tarry with    the example offered a moment         ago, we might briefly recall Segal's
analysis  of Euripides' Hippolytus.    In Euripides' play, as Segal argues convincingly,  the
performance      of "rituals of lamentation"      can be regarded as characterizing      and
reflecting   an emerging polis that is "conscious" of itself as a community   and cognizant
of the theatre as an artifice through which        that community   is both represented and
constituted.    Segal suggests,  for instance, that the chorus at the close of Hippolytus
reveals that "koinon achos is the emotion proper to a theater that has become conscious
of itself as a uniquely communal form." Indeed, the shift inHippolytus from the private
grief of Phaedra that opens the play to the "common grief" with which the play closes
 seems to suggest, as Segal puts it, that "personal grief is lifted from the level of
 individual response to the level of self-consciously    communal reaction."34 What Segal
wants    to underscore   is the fact that tragedy represents an important moment    in the
 formation of the polis's own self-awareness,    an awareness  that only emerged through
 the work       of tragic representation. Ritual commemoration   or suffering, he argues, was
 imitated       in order to "reflect on the ways    in which Greek society represents     itself
               such    collective                        as            rituals,       festivals."35
 through                                expressions           myth,

  Now, what is important for our purposes   is not so much Segal's ostensible   focus on
rituals of lamentation or the fact that the Greeks represented    their own rituals to
themselves   through the performance    of tragedies. Again,    the perspective     I am




   32       a start see Charles
    As                                                 Alcestis: How      to Die a Normal     Death  in Greek Tragedy,"
                                   Segal, "Euripides'
 in Death     and Representation,      ed. Sarah Webster     Goodwin       and Elizabeth     Bronfen    (Baltimore:    Johns
Hopkins       University    Press,    1993), 213-41;   Charles    Segal,     "Lament   and Closure       in Antigone,"      in

Sophocles'     Tragic World                    MA: Harvard       University     Press,   1995), 119-37; Nicole      Loraux,
                                (Cambridge,
                              a Woman                  MA: Harvard                   Press,   1987).
Tragic Ways      of Killing              (Cambridge,                  University
   33
     Charles     Segal has    written  about the cues within  both Antigone     and Hippolytus     that call the audience
to respond      with pity     and fear at appropriate   moments    in the play     ("Lament     and Closure,"     120, and
"Catharsis,     Audience      and Closure,"   in Tragedy and the Tragic, ed. M. S. Silk [Oxford: Clarendon           Press,
 1996], 149-72).   See also P. E. Easterling's     response  to Segal's piece    in the same collection.
    34
      Segal, Euripides,    127. See also Segal, "Catharsis,  Audience      and Closure,"      in Tragedy and the Tragic:
Greek Theatre and Beyond, ed. M. S. Silk (Oxford: Clarendon            Press,  1966), 157. In this latter piece, Segal
seeks    to expand    Aristotle's    notion   of katharsis by giving                              to the collective  . . .
                                                                        "greater    emphasis
communal      experience."      That is, Segal seeks to understand     the participatory     nature   of lamentation   as

 something     that opens up katharsis          beyond   the individual's         experience     of pity   and   fear, examined   by
Aristotle    in the Poetics.
    35
      Segal, "Catharsis,"    157.
92         /       Paul A. Kottman


proposing     is neither anthropological  nor hermeneutical.     Rather than focusing on what
was represented, or how the polis represented       itself to itself through dramatic works,       it
 is important to recognize simply that Segal's thesis presupposes             that the polis found
 itself?that   is, it seems to have accomplished   a certain self-identification    and organiza
 tion?through      whatever was represented      to it. Indeed, Segal's analysis leads us to
 conclude    that the emergence      of Greek tragedy marks         a fundamental      shift in the
 formation   of community,      a shift that is manifested   especially   in the city's nascent
 reflection upon    itself through tragic representation.     Put simply, the very fact that
Greek tragedy develops         through a self-conscious     appropriation    of the communal
experience   of lamentation signals, for Segal, a shift away from a community           that was
constituted   through    the spontaneity of lived ritual as such, towards a community         that
gathers   around a shared representation      of the act of mourning.

   The peculiarity     of tragedy, from this perspective,    is that it emerges as a communal
experience     in which    the communal    itself is ex-propriated    by the dramatic work or
 spectacle.36 Or put another way, with the birth of tragedy, communal          life itself appears
 to have been given over, and henceforth          subjected   to, the order of representation.37
With the birth of tragedy the community          of spectators begins to find itself in, and in
 fact to constitute itself through, the work of a shared self-representation.

   Of course, this self-representation    ismore than amere self-reflection. For the Greeks,
 according    to Jean-Pierre Vernant, tragedy did not simply offer an uncritical mirror of
 the polis; rather tragedy was the putting-into-question     of the polis itself. That is to say,
 tragedy "depicted     the city rent and divided against itself" in at least two senses38: first,
 insofar as the tragedies themselves?in         both form and content?presented        the polis
                           various        crises,     and       second,          insofar     as   the   dramatic                                 itself
undergoing                                                                                                               representation
 could be seen as taking on a life of its own, quite apart from the lives of the spectators,
 even as that representation  also played a crucial role in the social life of the polis, at
 city-sponsored  competitions    and festivals.39 In other words,      the order of tragic
                                             a constitutive               role    in   the                         of   social    life,
 representation                played                                                        organization                                 paradoxi

 cally by mamtaining                       an essential           distance         from, or indifference                to, that living reality.




    36
       For this reason,       the phenomenon         of Greek    tragedy    already brings about the expropriation                  of lived
                   that Guy Debord                       as the mark      of contemporary                     At the beginning         of his
 community                               postulates                                                society.
 treatise, Debord        claims that "all that once was directly             lived has become mere              representation."       Is this
not also the very shift that defines              the emergence        of Greek                  for instance      as it is traced in the
                                                                                     tragedy,
work      of Jean-Pierre      Vernant?     See Guy Debord,          The Society of the Spectacle,            tran. Donald      Nicholson
Smith      (New    York: Zone Books,         1995), 12.
    37
       It is true that, in the context we                 are
                                                               discussing,       this order      of representation           is manifestly
                  or dramatic.      However,      it ought    to be understood         as                discursive      as well.   Indeed,
 spectacular                                                                               implicitly
Aristotle     himself      is already                  toward                      the dramatic        or theatrical      as reducible      to
                                        disposed                 considering
discourse       (lexis), especially    where     the question      of mimetic       representation        is concerned.      See Aristotle
 Poetics, chapter    3; Halliwill,     Aristotle's,   128; and Domenico    Pesce's   excellent                  essay                                to the
                                                                                                 introductory
 Italian translation     of Aristotle's     Poetics   (Milan: Bompiani,   2000), 26.
     38                                             and Tragedy, 33.
       Vernant   and Vidal-Naquet,          Myth
     39
       Vernant    and others have          shown     that the very   form of Greek      tragedy,   for instance   the                            lexical
 difference        between           the chorus     and     the protagonists,         depicts   the structural   distance  between           the social
 life of       the polis    and      the dramatic          representation         that is essential    to tragedy.    See Vernant          and Vidal

Naquet,         Myth       and Tragedy,       29-48       and passim.
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                                 PHILOSOPHY /                                          93

   Vernant     has offered perhaps      the most    articulate account of this phenomenon,
regarding     the origins of Greek tragedy. For him, the polis acquires its democratic       form
precisely    at the moment     in which  it learns to find itself through what it represents to
 itself. But this self-finding now has the paradoxical       character of a "putting into crisis/'
For that which       is found is now at once the most familiar and intimate being of the
 community              and its ex-propriated               representation.

    Indeed, Vernant claims that the newly democratic polis "turned itself into a                                                theater"
 through the performance      of tragedy in festivals or contests, at the same time                                             putting
 itself "into question."40 Like Arendt, or Aristotle  for that matter, Vernant sees                                             the polis
 itself as emerging like a sort of stage whereupon     the cultural phenomenon    of
                                                                                   tragedy
 served to open the city up for debate.41 Noting,  for example, that Greek tragedy "takes
heroic legend as its material," Vernant emphasizes      that tragedy presents the hero not
as a model,   like in epic, but instead as a problem or subject of debate.42 First of all,
Tragedy does this, of course, by setting the heroic or tragic figure on stage, before the
eyes of the spectator, as opposed     to relying upon verbal narration. Thus, the tragic
heroes "are made to seem present, characters truly there, although at the same time
 they are portrayed   as figures who   cannot possibly  be there since they belong      to
 somewhere    else, to an invisible beyond."43 The tragic performance        is therefore
 regarded as in some way both familiar to and distant from the spectatorship?familiar
 enough to allow for identification and distant enough to allow for reflection, critique,
 and subsequent discussion.

     In this way,           too, writes       Vernant,      tragedy   "played       a decisive      role inman's          apprehen
 sion     of     'fiction,'"44    for   the    characters      that were                    on                before      the          of
                                                                              presented             stage,                      eyes
 the public,          afforded at once a phenomenal
                       were                                  reality and a fictitious    status,
According     to Vernant, a certain "consciousness     of fiction" emerged    in fifth-century
Athens; one that remained "essential to the dramatic spectacle," such that "it seems to
be both its condition        and its product."45 That is to say, while      it is impossible
unconditionally     to locate the origin of tragedy in a nascent "consciousness     of fiction,"
or vice-versa,             it is nevertheless         impossible to dissociate fully the former from the latter.
Each appears               as the condition           for the birth of the other.46




    40
      Although       tragedy   "appears     rooted    in social reality/'     he writes,      "it does not merely        reflect that

reality, but calls it into question."       See Jean-Pierre Vernant,         "Myth and Tragedy,"         in Essays on Aristotle's
Poetics, ed. Am?lie       O. Rorty    (Princeton:    Princeton  University       Press,     1992), 36.
    41
       Ibid.
    42
      Vernant    and Vidal-Naquet,       Myth      and Tragedy, 23-29 and passim.
    43
       Ibid., 243; Segal makes       a similar     claim: "Tragedy        combines       the distancing    effects    of myth    and
fiction, with     the agonistic model      of debate     and conflict.    It speaks    to the assembled      citizens    of the polis
 in the here        and now of a time full of crises, dangers             and conflicts;      but it uses a frame of remote,

 legendary       events    that enables  the poet     to look far beyond         the passions    and anxieties   of the present
moment"         (Euripides, 5).
     44
      Vernant        and Vidal-Naquet,   Myth      and Tragedy, 242-43.
     45
        Ibid., 244.
     46
      As if to drive        this point home, Vernant         notes   that this "new experience          afforded   by the tragic
 spectacle"       (ibid., 242) was most     likely
                                                    a decisive
                                                                   impetus     behind     the theory of mimesis-as-imitation
 articulated     by Plato and Aristotle.      Not    surprisingly,     theatrical    experience    turns out to be prior, so to
               to the                determination      of mimesis-as-imitation;          indeed,      the   theatrical   scene    deter
 speak,               conceptual
mines      the mode      of its philosophical      emergence.
94         /      Paul A. Kottman


   Now, inmy view, what is decisive in Vernant's analysis is the way inwhich tragedy
           as an imitative reflection, or self-conscious
works                                                             performance    only insofar as it
portrayed      something      that was already historically       or temporally distant from the
audience.47 Interestingly, Vernant notes that this distance had less to do with the mere
passage of time than with the fact that the events represented by Greek tragedy did not
belong to the living memory          of the Athenian    spectators. Likewise, he suggests that the
 representational,    fictitious,  or mimetic    quality of the play was not simply due to the
 technique of the production,         the labor of the actor, or the fact that tragedy comprises
 spectacle, not just speech. To be sure, all of these things played a role in the becoming
 fiction of tragedy, its break with epic, and its emerging place as the problematic
 reflection of the polis. But Vernant's analysis allows us to direct our attention beyond
 these more formal qualities of tragedy to the fact that theatrical experience               exceeds
myth      and becomes      a fictional representation       (mimesis) only insofar as the events
portrayed are, a priori, understood          as "happening     somewhere    else" or belonging    to a
mythical     past that is by now beyond the grasp of living remembrance.48
     Put        another    it is precisely
                               way,          by becoming    a                  itself over to
                                                               work?giving
representation,   repetition,   and reproduction?that    tragedy simultaneously      differenti
ates itself from myth, which is to say, differentiates   itself from the immediacy between
 living memory   and communal       life inwhich myth finds its home.49 The birth of tragedy
signals, ifwe follow Vernant's logic, an irreparable rift between the work as it appears
before the community        in dramatic representation,  and the living memory       of what is
being          represented.
    In the terms of my argument here, Vernant's          account     leads to the following
 conclusion:  the birth of tragedy lies in nothing other than the radical separation of
work from scene. Interestingly,    it is in the light of this division    that Vernant names
Phrynichus'             Miletus as somewhat anomalous. While we know of other plays
              The Fall of




     47
      An    important   exception   to this account      of tragedy      is the chorus.  Vernant       and Vidal-Naquet

suggest    that the chorus embodies     "the collective     truth ... of the polis" over and against      the "otherness"
of the tragic hero (ibid., 243). More      recently,   other scholars have argued        that the chorus     is even more
democratic      than the Athenian     polis in that it included         old men,    women,     slaves,    and foreigners;
 therefore,       the chorus    represents     an ulterior   and complex      set of problems   with              to the relation
                                                                                                        regard
between          the  emerging      democracy       and dramatic     practices.    Given    the inevitable     limits of scope,
however,         I cannot   include    a discussion     of the chorus here. The interested      reader could see, as a start,
the following:       Vernant     and Vidal-Naquet,     Myth   and Tragedy; Oddone       Longo,   "The Theater   of the
Polis,"    in Nothing     to Do with Dionysus?:     Athenian  Drama    in Its Social Context,  ed. John Winkler    and
Froma      Zeitlin    (Princeton:    Princeton   University   Press,   1990),  12-19;   John Gould,    "Tragedy    and
Collective     Experience,"     in Tragedy and the Tragic, ed. M. S. Silk (Oxford: Oxford University     Press,  1996),
217-43,     and Simon GoldhiU's         response   to Gould's piece  in the same volume.
     ^Vernant          and                              and Tragedy,         246     and  passim.     In contrast   to tragedy,     the
                            Vidal-Naquet,      Myth
 transmission          of myth                     was      tantamount         to the    transmission     of memory     itself; living
                                   through    epic
 remembrance,            in short, is absolutely    essential    to epic     song.    For more     on this, see Eric Havelock,     The
Muse   Learns          to Write      (New Haven:    Yale    University     Press,    1986),   especially 70-73; Albert  Lord, Epic
 Singers and Oral            Tradition   (Ithaca: Cornell   University     Press,     1991)   and The Singer of Tales (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard     University      Press, 2000).
     491 am       indebted        here
                                and throughout        to Jean-Luc Nancy's         analysis   of myth    in The Inoperative

                                University    of Minnesota     Press,  1991), especially    45-47, which    has helped me
 Community      (Minneapolis:
 to understand      the stakes of Vernant's                 in ways   I otherwise     would    not have   seen.
                                                 analysis                                                       Especially
 relevant   here is Nancy's    elaboration    of the relation between      myth     and scene in the third chapter.
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                                         PHILOSOPHY /                                    95

whose    subject was historical,  Phrynichus'     is "the first tragedy of which we are
informed."50 For Vernant, Phrynichus'    play?perhaps       because it lies at the begirvning
of the tradition?represents    something   like an alternative to the trajectory that Greek
tragedy, in his view, seems to have followed.
      the one hand, we have the dominant
      On                                      tradition described by Segal, Vernant, and
others, which  establishes tragedy's   emergence   as fiction or mimetic art through the
appropriation  of communal     rituals or heroic legends that already belonged      to an
immemorial past. This view, which is recognizable     in nearly every theory of perform
ance that has its foundations   in classical Greek philosophy,       tends to regard the
development  of theatrical experience    as dependent     upon   a fundamental mimetic
distance  between the spectacle and the lives of the spectators.51 Vernant's and Segal's
analyses  would belong to this tradition, even while attempting    to account for it. They
could even be said to be the very product of this tradition, for this mimetic distance is,
according    to the philosophical and critical tradition to which we belong, the most
essential          feature of any artwork or discursive  representation. And this distance                                                   is
generally           thought  to be commensurate with its foreignness    to the living memory                                                 of
 those     who       encounter            the mimetic
                                                                  performance.

   On the other hand, we have Phrynichus' play, which was "not a legendary" tragedy,
 as Vernant notes, but rather "a tragedy of contemporary            events."52 Now, Vernant
 concludes   that the public condemnation     of The Fall ofMiletus    resulted from the fact
 that the play portrayed    events, which he says "were too close" to the lives of the
 spectators. The play, he writes, "did not allow for the distancing,    the transposition   that
made it possible for feelings of pity or terror to be displaced   into a different register, no
 longer experienced     in the same way as in real life, but immediately apprehended  and
understood    as fiction."53 Vernant thus imagines Phrynichus' play to be an irregularity,
which did not meet the criteria for "fiction" or "mimesis" towhich the Athenians were
gradually becoming        accustomed.  The scene was too close to "real life." Although
Vernant does not say so, the logic of his argument leads one to conclude that the scene
Herodotus            describes               cannot  properly be understood  as an artwork                              or discursive
representation. Indeed,                        for Vernant the censure of Phrynichus' work                             was   a conse
quence of an already accepted                             and established              "consciousness      of fiction," which         was
 in     fact    offended                 a              that    was       too-close-to-the-bone.54         What     made        the
                                  by          play                                                                                    play
exceptional,  it would  seem, was that it could not be received as mere fiction. For
Vernant, of course, this is an exception that only serves to confirm the rule, that is, to
confirm the account of tragedy as commensurate with the distance between fiction and
life.




      50
       David  Rosenbloom,        "Myth, History,"      102. For a list of other non-extant    tragedies  that allegedly
dealt    with historical               see H. D. Broadhead,        "Introduction,"  Persae of Aeschylus
                            subjects,                                                                      (Cambridge:
Cambridge      University      Press, 1960), xvii.
   51
      In a sense, this claim calls for no justification.       Since Plato and Aristotle,  at least in the tradition    of

thought which       this article attempts    to analyze, mimesis     has been the key to the question   of the relation
between     artworks                    dramatic               works)     and    the world    or nature.
                            (especially
   52
     Vernant, Myth          and Tragedy, 244.
   53
      Ibid.
   54
      Ibid. Malcolm        Heath         makes        a similar                                that Phrynichus'            was    censured
                                                                    assumption,    claiming                          play
"because         the tears were        shed    over misfortunes          that touched    the audience    too closely,                  them
                                                                                                                         reminding
of their own         troubles."        See Heath,       The Poetics     of Greek Tragedy,       9.
96          /       Paul A. Kottman


    But are things so clear? Given that Phrynichus' play (494 BCE) is the first tragedy of
which   we have any record, can it be certain that the censure of The Fall Miletus after
                                                                                 of
 this early performance was a consequence            of its failure to be "immediately    appre
hended and understood          as fiction?" Particularly what if, as Vernant himself claims,
this "consciousness     of fiction" itself emerged partly as a consequence     of the intensify
ing consumption       of tragedy? What,     after all, accounts for the appetite for fiction as
opposed     to real life that Vernant supposes      to have existed? Why must the history of
tragedy begin    with the self-reflective   apprehension     of mimesis?

   Might    it not be the case that the trajectory outlined by Vernant, Segal, and all those
who follow in Aristotle's      footsteps?which       equates tragedy and the emergence of a
 formal theatrical consciousness      with the contemplative      apprehension   of tragedy-as
 imitation?presupposes       a prior recognition of fiction that may in fact be the conse
quence of a lived remembrance            that distinguishes,  without    thought or reflection,
between     the real and the imitation? Perhaps the scene described by Herodotus           forces
us to consider the living scene as a condition without which                      like imitation
                                                                      something
or     a consciousness                  of    fiction      would         not      emerge.

  After all, it seems clear that those Athenians who banned Phrynichus'         play were
aware that the play was not the same         as the events that it portrayed. That is, they
                                       thing
recognized  the performance   for what itwas and quite naturally did not confuse itwith
the real capture of Miletus.   Indeed, this recognition   is what was manifested     in the
                censure.       After         all,   one      can                censure       a work,         not    historical      events.
play's                                                               only

   And it is equally clear that this recognition of the play as an imitative performance
was not the result of a formal convention or "consciousness        of fiction." Still less does
 the play's reception seem to suggest that the performance       of this tragedy signaled a
questioning   of the city or anything    like Aristotle's phronesis. It could even be said,
without    exaggeration,     that the recognition of Phrynichus'        play as an "imitation" of
 real events    came to those Athenians         without      reflection, without    a "conscious"
 apprehension      of fiction. Indeed,    the apprehension         of theatrical mimesis    by the
Athenians     in the scene Herodotus     describes   is utterly foreign to the sort of theoretical
 contemplation     that will come to characterize the philosopher's        noetic grasp of mimesis
 in Plato's         work         a                      later.
                                      century

   First of all, therefore, this scene marks       the dissociation of the apprehension       of
mimesis from the act of thoughtful         debate, understanding,     or collective wisdom
 (phronesis) that, according  to Aristotle   and Vernant, characterizes     theatrical experi
ence.55 Indeed, to paraphrase Arendt,        it could be said axiomatically     that theatrical
experience in fact antedates the vita contemplativa presupposed  by classical philosophy's
account of the theatre,56 for Herodotus'   account presents us with a scene inwhich the
conscious  recognition   of theatrical artifice fails to result in, or coincide with,      the
 "fictional          distance"               that characterizes                 Aristotle's         definition           of theatrical          experience.
 Instead,           the    artifice                              "calamaties"             that were,     as Herodotus                          "too   close       to
                                        presented                                                                                  says,




       55
        Aristotle         underscores          the way       in which       the pleasure       of watching           or            an imitation       coincides
                                                                                                                        hearing
with      a sort of consciousness                  or                                         the imitative         nature    of the spectacle        itself.   See
                                                          knowledge         regarding
Poetics   1448M4-15.
   56
      See Arendt's   discussion                     of Pythagoras           in The Life ofMind,         93.
THE SCENEBEFORE
                                                                        PHILOSOPHY /                              97

home"     (oikeia kaka), too close to allow the play to stand as a subject for debate, or for
the feelings      that it inspired to mature      into detached,  deliberative   reflection. The
recognition     of the play's artifice, therefore, appears to be a result of the immediacy
between the mimesis of Phrynichus' play and the living remembrance of its spectators,
rather than the result of the play's distance          from their living memory,      as Vernant
supposes.     It is as if the mimetic   aspect  of Phrynichus'   play lay   not so much     in the
artifice of its theatrical manifestation,   but rather in the play's function as a witness     for
events    that the spectators had themselves          seen. The theatrical scene Herodotus
describes    is constituted most essentially      through the very relation between        living
memory     and mimetic performance        that, according to tradition, characterizes myth as
opposed     to tragedy.

  Thus, something    like an alternative account of the origins of the theatrical scene,
and consequently    of the relation between mimesis and politics as well, begins to
emerge?an    account whose origins lie at the very outset of the political and theatrical
tradition that we inherit. Rather than focus on a nascent consciousness      of fiction or
 imitation, or on the self-conscious  representation  of the polis in a dramatic work, it is
 instead the singularity of the scene that comes to the fore here, from which the political
 sense of the event (both the battle itself and its representation)         arises. Revising
Aristotle's  account of tragedy in the Poetics, we could say that the mimetic     character of
 the scene does not lie necessarily    in the event of the performance      (opsis), or in the
structure     of the artistic work (plot, diction, mythos, lexis). Likewise,    the habit of
reducing      the term mimesis to a general, essentially  Platonic,  determination    of the
relation    between       "art   and   nature"   or   "imitation   and              often   obscures   the   term's
                                                                         reality"
own    ambiguity. The problem        lies in this: the political sense of mimesis?that     which
relates  the theatrical experience of being on the scene to political life?cannot         be fully
grasped in terms of the fictional or artistic character of performance           or work, and its
relation to an outside reality. Rather, mimesis acquires its political sense in theatrical
experience insofar as it corresponds       to the living relation of the scene. A radical politics
of mimesis, in sum, would      therefore need tomove beyond the centrality of representa
tion, of what         is represented,      and begin     to take account     of this correspondence.

More Related Content

What's hot

Nietzsche the birth of tragedy
Nietzsche  the birth of tragedyNietzsche  the birth of tragedy
Nietzsche the birth of tragedyalessapi
 
The impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_the
The impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_theThe impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_the
The impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_theGoswami Mahirpari
 
No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...
No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...
No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...Goswami Mahirpari
 
Salman rushdies midnights_children_as_a
Salman rushdies midnights_children_as_aSalman rushdies midnights_children_as_a
Salman rushdies midnights_children_as_aGoswami Mahirpari
 
Historiographical Metafiction
Historiographical MetafictionHistoriographical Metafiction
Historiographical MetafictionSt:Mary's College
 
Literature "romantic movement and ghotic
Literature "romantic movement and ghoticLiterature "romantic movement and ghotic
Literature "romantic movement and ghoticjuli ani
 
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. FreedRobert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. FreedMariane Farias
 
The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...
The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...
The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...iosrjce
 
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentationClassical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentationPatrick Dave
 
Anatomy Of Criticism
Anatomy Of  CriticismAnatomy Of  Criticism
Anatomy Of Criticismdavidjackson
 
Sculpting historiography as_a_narrative
Sculpting historiography as_a_narrativeSculpting historiography as_a_narrative
Sculpting historiography as_a_narrativeGoswami Mahirpari
 
The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in " Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...
The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in "  Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in "  Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...
The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in " Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...Goswami Mahirpari
 

What's hot (20)

Larida
LaridaLarida
Larida
 
Nietzsche the birth of tragedy
Nietzsche  the birth of tragedyNietzsche  the birth of tragedy
Nietzsche the birth of tragedy
 
Metafiction
MetafictionMetafiction
Metafiction
 
The impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_the
The impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_theThe impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_the
The impact of_space_on_the_psyche_of_the
 
No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...
No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...
No Home like place The Lesson of History in Kazip Ishiguro's An Artist of the...
 
Salman rushdies midnights_children_as_a
Salman rushdies midnights_children_as_aSalman rushdies midnights_children_as_a
Salman rushdies midnights_children_as_a
 
160 Slides for Aristotle
160 Slides for Aristotle160 Slides for Aristotle
160 Slides for Aristotle
 
Realism & existentialism
Realism & existentialismRealism & existentialism
Realism & existentialism
 
Historiographical Metafiction
Historiographical MetafictionHistoriographical Metafiction
Historiographical Metafiction
 
Review of On Beauty
Review of On BeautyReview of On Beauty
Review of On Beauty
 
Literature "romantic movement and ghotic
Literature "romantic movement and ghoticLiterature "romantic movement and ghotic
Literature "romantic movement and ghotic
 
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. FreedRobert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
Robert Musil's other postmodernism, by M. Freed
 
The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...
The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...
The Depiction of the Metaphysical in German and African Fiction: a study of s...
 
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentationClassical criticism in eng lit. presentation
Classical criticism in eng lit. presentation
 
Anatomy Of Criticism
Anatomy Of  CriticismAnatomy Of  Criticism
Anatomy Of Criticism
 
Emile Zola
Emile ZolaEmile Zola
Emile Zola
 
Theory of Modes
Theory of ModesTheory of Modes
Theory of Modes
 
Sculpting historiography as_a_narrative
Sculpting historiography as_a_narrativeSculpting historiography as_a_narrative
Sculpting historiography as_a_narrative
 
The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in " Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...
The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in "  Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in "  Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...
The Selective Narrator " construction of the past in " Kazuo Ishiguro's An A...
 
Lucero
LuceroLucero
Lucero
 

Similar to Memory, mimeses, tragedy

French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damenFrench scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damenMariane Farias
 
Annotated Bibliography History Of Art History
Annotated Bibliography History Of Art HistoryAnnotated Bibliography History Of Art History
Annotated Bibliography History Of Art HistoryKelly Lipiec
 
Anecdote And History
Anecdote And HistoryAnecdote And History
Anecdote And HistoryMary Calkins
 
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_aAnalysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_asaimaPerveen4
 
Ancient Greece And Film
Ancient Greece And FilmAncient Greece And Film
Ancient Greece And FilmJoe Osborn
 
Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener...
 Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener... Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener...
Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener...English Literature and Language Review ELLR
 
LESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptx
LESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptxLESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptx
LESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptxClemartContaoi
 
Literary theory an-overview
Literary theory an-overviewLiterary theory an-overview
Literary theory an-overviewsharanuholal
 
An End To Cosmic Loneliness Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist Enchantment
An End To Cosmic Loneliness  Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist EnchantmentAn End To Cosmic Loneliness  Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist Enchantment
An End To Cosmic Loneliness Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist EnchantmentSandra Long
 
Paper - 3 Literary Criticism and Theory
Paper - 3 Literary Criticism and TheoryPaper - 3 Literary Criticism and Theory
Paper - 3 Literary Criticism and Theorypriyanka baraiya
 
The Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docx
The Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docxThe Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docx
The Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docxoreo10
 
Hieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdf
Hieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdfHieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdf
Hieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdfMichaelCP3
 
Thury mythology modern lit
Thury mythology modern litThury mythology modern lit
Thury mythology modern litherusalatiga
 
POSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdf
POSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdfPOSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdf
POSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdfNguyenChu11
 
Borislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art Portfolio
Borislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art PortfolioBorislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art Portfolio
Borislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art PortfolioBorislav Dimitrov
 

Similar to Memory, mimeses, tragedy (20)

Antigone Now
Antigone NowAntigone Now
Antigone Now
 
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damenFrench scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
French scenes in greek tragedy, by mark damen
 
Annotated Bibliography History Of Art History
Annotated Bibliography History Of Art HistoryAnnotated Bibliography History Of Art History
Annotated Bibliography History Of Art History
 
4Q LESSON 1.pptx
4Q LESSON 1.pptx4Q LESSON 1.pptx
4Q LESSON 1.pptx
 
Anecdote And History
Anecdote And HistoryAnecdote And History
Anecdote And History
 
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_aAnalysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
Analysis of sophocles_oedipus_the_king_a
 
Literary theory
Literary theoryLiterary theory
Literary theory
 
Ancient Greece And Film
Ancient Greece And FilmAncient Greece And Film
Ancient Greece And Film
 
Literary Terms
Literary TermsLiterary Terms
Literary Terms
 
Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener...
 Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener... Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener...
Elements of Dystopian Science Fiction in David Mitchell's Cloud Atlas: Gener...
 
LESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptx
LESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptxLESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptx
LESSON 1 THEORIES OF DRAMA.pptx
 
Literary Comparison Essay
Literary Comparison EssayLiterary Comparison Essay
Literary Comparison Essay
 
Literary theory an-overview
Literary theory an-overviewLiterary theory an-overview
Literary theory an-overview
 
An End To Cosmic Loneliness Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist Enchantment
An End To Cosmic Loneliness  Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist EnchantmentAn End To Cosmic Loneliness  Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist Enchantment
An End To Cosmic Loneliness Alice Walker S Essays As Abolitionist Enchantment
 
Paper - 3 Literary Criticism and Theory
Paper - 3 Literary Criticism and TheoryPaper - 3 Literary Criticism and Theory
Paper - 3 Literary Criticism and Theory
 
The Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docx
The Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docxThe Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docx
The Prudent Dissident Unheroic Resistancein Sophocles’ Anti.docx
 
Hieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdf
Hieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdfHieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdf
Hieroglyph_Emblem_and_Renaissance_Pictog (1).pdf
 
Thury mythology modern lit
Thury mythology modern litThury mythology modern lit
Thury mythology modern lit
 
POSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdf
POSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdfPOSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdf
POSTAPOCALYPTIC_CURATING_CULT.pdf
 
Borislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art Portfolio
Borislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art PortfolioBorislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art Portfolio
Borislav Dimitrov’ Fine Art Portfolio
 

More from Mariane Farias

Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), CoetzeeMecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), CoetzeeMariane Farias
 
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich SchillerA Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich SchillerMariane Farias
 
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre KojèveIntrodução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre KojèveMariane Farias
 
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanalAristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanalMariane Farias
 
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbertAesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbertMariane Farias
 
Aristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaper
Aristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaperAristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaper
Aristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaperMariane Farias
 
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenPoetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenMariane Farias
 
What is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugomWhat is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugomMariane Farias
 
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhuMyth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhuMariane Farias
 
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doeringHume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doeringMariane Farias
 
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnottThe lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnottMariane Farias
 
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstagTragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstagMariane Farias
 
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steinerTragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steinerMariane Farias
 
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donaldThe performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donaldMariane Farias
 
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardieThe poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardieMariane Farias
 
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxbyThe doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxbyMariane Farias
 
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphyPostdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphyMariane Farias
 
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...Mariane Farias
 
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennettNietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennettMariane Farias
 
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelvenHeidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelvenMariane Farias
 

More from Mariane Farias (20)

Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), CoetzeeMecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
Mecanismos internos (ensaios sobre literatura), Coetzee
 
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich SchillerA Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
A Educação Estética do Homem, Friedrich Schiller
 
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre KojèveIntrodução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
Introdução à leitura de Hegel, Alexandre Kojève
 
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanalAristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
Aristotle definition of poetry, by robert j. yanal
 
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbertAesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
Aesthetic imitation and imitators in aristotle, by katherine e. gilbert
 
Aristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaper
Aristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaperAristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaper
Aristotles catharsis and aesthetic pleasure, by eva shaper
 
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillenPoetics as system, by claudio guillen
Poetics as system, by claudio guillen
 
What is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugomWhat is poetics, by stein haugom
What is poetics, by stein haugom
 
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhuMyth and philosophy, by rui zhu
Myth and philosophy, by rui zhu
 
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doeringHume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
Hume and the theory of tragedy, by j. frederick doering
 
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnottThe lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
The lost dimension of greek tragedy, by peter d. arnott
 
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstagTragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
Tragedy, pessimism, nietzsche, by joshua foa dienstag
 
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steinerTragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
Tragedy reconsidered, by george steiner
 
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donaldThe performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
The performative basis of modern literary theory, by henry mc donald
 
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardieThe poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
The poetics of aristotle, by r. p hardie
 
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxbyThe doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
The doleful airs of euripides, by blair hoxby
 
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphyPostdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy
 
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
Pity, fear, and catharsis in aristotles poetics, by charles b. daniels and sa...
 
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennettNietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
Nietzsche's idea of myth, by benjamin bennett
 
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelvenHeidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
Heidegger and tragedy, by michael gelven
 

Recently uploaded

Unraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing Postmodern Elements in Literature.pptx
Unraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing  Postmodern Elements in  Literature.pptxUnraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing  Postmodern Elements in  Literature.pptx
Unraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing Postmodern Elements in Literature.pptxDhatriParmar
 
MS4 level being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdf
MS4 level   being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdfMS4 level   being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdf
MS4 level being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdfMr Bounab Samir
 
Man or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptx
Man or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptxMan or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptx
Man or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptxDhatriParmar
 
4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptx
4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptx4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptx
4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptxmary850239
 
ROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptx
ROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptxROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptx
ROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptxVanesaIglesias10
 
Mental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young minds
Mental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young mindsMental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young minds
Mental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young mindsPooky Knightsmith
 
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptxINTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptxHumphrey A Beña
 
Congestive Cardiac Failure..presentation
Congestive Cardiac Failure..presentationCongestive Cardiac Failure..presentation
Congestive Cardiac Failure..presentationdeepaannamalai16
 
Q-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWQ-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWQuiz Club NITW
 
ClimART Action | eTwinning Project
ClimART Action    |    eTwinning ProjectClimART Action    |    eTwinning Project
ClimART Action | eTwinning Projectjordimapav
 
Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4
Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4
Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4JOYLYNSAMANIEGO
 
Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...
Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...
Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...DhatriParmar
 
Q-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWQ-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWQuiz Club NITW
 
Concurrency Control in Database Management system
Concurrency Control in Database Management systemConcurrency Control in Database Management system
Concurrency Control in Database Management systemChristalin Nelson
 
Mythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Mythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWMythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Mythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWQuiz Club NITW
 
DIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptx
DIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptxDIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptx
DIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptxMichelleTuguinay1
 
week 1 cookery 8 fourth - quarter .pptx
week 1 cookery 8  fourth  -  quarter .pptxweek 1 cookery 8  fourth  -  quarter .pptx
week 1 cookery 8 fourth - quarter .pptxJonalynLegaspi2
 

Recently uploaded (20)

Unraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing Postmodern Elements in Literature.pptx
Unraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing  Postmodern Elements in  Literature.pptxUnraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing  Postmodern Elements in  Literature.pptx
Unraveling Hypertext_ Analyzing Postmodern Elements in Literature.pptx
 
MS4 level being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdf
MS4 level   being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdfMS4 level   being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdf
MS4 level being good citizen -imperative- (1) (1).pdf
 
Man or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptx
Man or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptxMan or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptx
Man or Manufactured_ Redefining Humanity Through Biopunk Narratives.pptx
 
4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptx
4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptx4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptx
4.11.24 Poverty and Inequality in America.pptx
 
ROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptx
ROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptxROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptx
ROLES IN A STAGE PRODUCTION in arts.pptx
 
Mental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young minds
Mental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young mindsMental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young minds
Mental Health Awareness - a toolkit for supporting young minds
 
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptxINTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
 
Congestive Cardiac Failure..presentation
Congestive Cardiac Failure..presentationCongestive Cardiac Failure..presentation
Congestive Cardiac Failure..presentation
 
Q-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWQ-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor General Quiz-7th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
 
ClimART Action | eTwinning Project
ClimART Action    |    eTwinning ProjectClimART Action    |    eTwinning Project
ClimART Action | eTwinning Project
 
Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4
Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4
Daily Lesson Plan in Mathematics Quarter 4
 
Paradigm shift in nursing research by RS MEHTA
Paradigm shift in nursing research by RS MEHTAParadigm shift in nursing research by RS MEHTA
Paradigm shift in nursing research by RS MEHTA
 
Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...
Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...
Beauty Amidst the Bytes_ Unearthing Unexpected Advantages of the Digital Wast...
 
Q-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWQ-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Q-Factor HISPOL Quiz-6th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
 
Concurrency Control in Database Management system
Concurrency Control in Database Management systemConcurrency Control in Database Management system
Concurrency Control in Database Management system
 
Mythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Mythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITWMythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
Mythology Quiz-4th April 2024, Quiz Club NITW
 
DIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptx
DIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptxDIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptx
DIFFERENT BASKETRY IN THE PHILIPPINES PPT.pptx
 
week 1 cookery 8 fourth - quarter .pptx
week 1 cookery 8  fourth  -  quarter .pptxweek 1 cookery 8  fourth  -  quarter .pptx
week 1 cookery 8 fourth - quarter .pptx
 
INCLUSIVE EDUCATION PRACTICES FOR TEACHERS AND TRAINERS.pptx
INCLUSIVE EDUCATION PRACTICES FOR TEACHERS AND TRAINERS.pptxINCLUSIVE EDUCATION PRACTICES FOR TEACHERS AND TRAINERS.pptx
INCLUSIVE EDUCATION PRACTICES FOR TEACHERS AND TRAINERS.pptx
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Large Language Models"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Large Language Models"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Large Language Models"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Large Language Models"
 

Memory, mimeses, tragedy

  • 1. Memory, "Mimesis," Tragedy: The Scene before Philosophy Author(s): Paul A. Kottman Reviewed work(s): Source: Theatre Journal, Vol. 55, No. 1, Ancient Theatre (Mar., 2003), pp. 81-97 Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25069181 . Accessed: 23/09/2012 12:10 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theatre Journal. http://www.jstor.org
  • 2. Memory, Mimesis, Tragedy: The Scene Before Philosophy Paul A. Kottman "Life is the non-representable origin of representation." Derrida ?Jacques The historical complicity of Greek tragedy with the emergence of the Athenian polis has interested political thinkers and classicists alike for some time.1 Among classicists, this interest has tended tomanifest itself either in an analysis of particular dramatists;2 or certain thematic, conceptual, or linguistic patterns within individual tragic works.3 In short, the political stakes of the theatre have derived from the exegetical analysis of the theatrical works themselves in relation to their context of origin.4 The pre dominance that this sort of exegesis continues to enjoy is due not only to the philological care and attention with which classicists, especially, tend to proceed but also to a tendency to understand the dramatic work itself (both the textual artifact, and whatever the archives retain of its context of origin) as the repository of political or social meaning. And this means, consequently, that the political nature of tragedy is implicitly regarded by such amethodology as an effect of the mimetic character of the Paul A. Kottman is Assistant at SUNY and Adjunct Professor of English Albany, Professor of Studies at New York University. He is currently his first book, tentatively entitled Performance revising Between Actors and Witnesses: A Politics of the Scene. His recent include the publications Introduction to Narratives, by Adriana Cavarero, and articles on Shakespeare and Relating literary theory that have in Shakespeare Studies and The Oxford Literary Review. appeared 1 See, as a start, Karen Hermassi, Polity and Theater in Historical Perspective (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977), and J. Peter Euben, ed., Greek Tragedy and Political Theory (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986), and The Tragedy of Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton Press, University 1990); some of the essays in John Winkler and Froma Zeitlin, ed., Nothing to Do With Dionysus?: Athenian Drama in Its Social Context (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990). 2 on See, for example, Charles Segal's work Iwill return to Segal later in this article. Euripides. 3 One might think, for example, of the various of Antigone over the past political readings thirty years or of Froma Zeitlin's and Nicole Loraux's work on and ritual in the Greek context. gender, myth, 4 For a good account of the German roots of this philological methodology, as well as its relation to more to interpretations of Greek see Simon Goldhill, "Modern archaeological approaches tragedy, Critical to Greek in The Cambridge Companion to Greek Tragedy, ed. P. E. Approaches Tragedy," Easterling (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 324-48. Even the most philosophically inclined classicists tend to insist upon the exegetical character of their labor. Notably, Jean-Pierre Vernant has offered a number of eloquent and convincing defenses of careful contextual of analysis classical Greek works. See especially Jean-Pierre Vernant, "Greek Problems of Interpreta Tragedy: tion," in The Structuralist Controversy, ed. Richard Macksey and Eugenio Donato (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1970), 273-95. Theatre Journal 55 (2003) 81-97 ? 2003 by The Johns Hopkins Press University
  • 3. 82 / PaulA. Kottman dramatic work. The determination of tragedy as first and foremost amimetic work in turn reduces the political essence of tragedy to the legible features of this or that production. Among political thinkers, the situation is perhaps more complex. Hannah Arendt, in an exemplary and influential discussion of the origins of tragedy, declared that "the theater is the political art par excellence; only there is the political sphere of human life transposed into art."5 For Arendt, the political essence of the theatre arises from its "pre-philosophical" presentation of human affairs.6 By "pre-philosophical," Arendt simply means that the theatre is an experience of speech and action as pure actuality, through which each actor reveals "who" s/he is by speaking and acting among others. Indeed, from Arendt's perspective, the theatre?like the praxis it imitates?is also pre political, for it is precisely the interaction that adheres in speaking and action among a plurality that opens the space of the polis.7 Thus, what makes the theatre political, in Arendt's view, is not the imitative or mimetic quality of the work as such; rather it is the fact that tragedy "imitates" "man in his relation to others."8 Put simply, it is the relationality of the scene that lends the theater its political sense. Given these seemingly contradictory approaches to the problem, one is thus left to wonder: does the political essence of the theatre arise from a pre-philosophical theatrical experience as such? Or, does the political nature of theatrical experience come from the mimetic or imitative quality of the dramatic work, as the philosophical tradition since Plato defines it? Before addressing these questions myself, itmay be helpful to recall that already with Aristotle, one finds significant resistance to the Platonic definition of tragedy as poetic production (poiesis) or m?meseos en ontos. Indeed, it was precisely in order to assert a political sense for tragedy?over and against Plato's banishment of the tragedians in the Republic?that Aristotle defined tragedy in the Poetics as m?meseos praxis.9 For unlike the m?meseos en ontos which, for Plato, made the theatre a poetic or work, based on mere that lead its audience from the production appearances astray onto-theological order of Ideas?Aristotle sought to orient the theatre toward praxis. This is why, as Jacques Taminiaux has demonstrated, Arendt's take on tragedy might be read as a partial recuperation of Aristotle's rejoinder to Plato.10 It is therefore important to note that the debate over how to account for the political essence of tragedy?is it a function of the mimetic, poetic work, or does it adhere in the scene of action??is a problem that is inscribed in Aristotle's agon with Plato over the term mimesis itself. For this reason, and others, the terms mimesis and mimetic can hardly be 5 Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), 188. 61 take the phrase "pre-philosophical" from Hannah Arendt's The Life ofMind (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1971), 129-40. 7 Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition, 179-89. For an excellent discussion of Arendt's views on action and the theatre, see lacques Taminiaux, "From Aristotle to Bios Theoretikos and Tragic Theoria," in The Thracian Maid and the Professional Thinker (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), 89 121. 8 Arendt, The Human Condition, 188. 9 See Aristotle, Poetics, tran. Stephen Halliwell (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1998), 1449b, 25. 10 See note 5.
  • 4. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 83 used in any univocal way; where I use them inwhat follows, I have inmind primarily Plato's use of mimesis in Republic X. It is not my intention here to rehearse Aristotle's riposte to his teacher in any detail; it has already been the topic of numerous studies.11 Nor am I interested in taking sides in order to simply privilege Aristotle's views over those of Plato. Given the history and character of the problem, which Iwould like to bear in mind throughout this essay, one can hardly hope to offer anything like a final solution. Instead, having outlined the problem of how to relate the theatre to politics in a broad?albeit cursory?fashion, Iwould like to approach it from another perspective, for itmay become clear along the way that the parameters of the ancient debate itself can be shifted. In this spirit, Iwould like to consider another way inwhich to articulate a "pre-philosophical" (i.e. not simply imitative or representational) political essence of theatrical experience?one which would be irreducible to the mimetic work, and adhere in the living scene as such?by returning to an ancient anecdote. Around 493 BCE one of the very first works of Greek tragedy?The Fall of Miletus by the tragic poet Phrynichus?was staged inAthens only two years after the events with which it dealt actually occurred.12 No script of the play is extant, but it appears to have been a theatrical representation of a military defeat that the Milesians suffered at the hands of the Persians.13 The play was therefore received not as a representation of a familiar myth, or distant legend.14 Rather, the play presented something that the audience members themselves remembered, and in so doing both brought about and confirmed this living recollection. Indeed, so unsettled were the Athenians by what they saw that they were reduced to weeping. Herodotus provides the following account of the audience's reaction to the performance: The Athenians . . . showed their profound distress at the loss of Miletus in a number of ways, but in none so than in their of Phrynichus7 for when clearly reception play; Phrynichus produced his Fall ofMiletus, the audience in the theater burst into tears, and the author was fined a thousand drachmae for reminding them of a disaster which touched them so [hos anamnesanta oikeia kaka]. A law was closely subsequently passed forbidding anybody ever to on put the play stage again.15 While this account is, as far as is known, the first surviving report of the earliest performance of a tragedy of which we are informed, The Fall ofMiletus was certainly 11 Two to start are: Gerald Plato and Aristotle on good places Else, Poetry (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1986), 74-88; and Stephen Halliwell, Aristotle's Poetics of (Chicago: University Chicago Press, 1986), 109-38, 331-36. 12 on the date, For more see Joseph Roisman, "On Phrynichos' Sack of Miletus and Phoinissai," ?ranos 86 (1988): 15-16. The timeline at the end of Easterling's The lists Cambridge Companion as the first Phyrnichus' Fall ofMiletus tragedy on record, 352. 13 See William Ridgeway, The Origin of Tragedy (New York: Benjamin Bloom, 1966), 66. See also, Malcolm Heath, The Poetics of Greek Tragedy (London: Duckworth, 1987), 67. 14 See Sir Hugh "Problems of Early Greek Tragedy," in The Academic Lloyd-Jones, Papers of Sir Hugh Lloyd-Jones (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 230-33. 15 Herodotus, The Histories, tran. Aubrey de Selincourt (New York: Penguin Books, 1966), 366, emphasis mine.
  • 5. 84 / PaulA. Kottman not the only play of its time to represent historical events within living memory.16 Phrynichus himself returned to historical material about fifteen years later with The Phoenician Women (476?) and Aeschylus' The Persians (472), the oldest extant work of tragedy, portrayed the defeat of the Persians at Salamis in 484. The obvious difference between The Fall of Miletus and these later historical plays, of course, is the fact that the latter did not (as far as is known) lead to this sort of weeping; additionally, their authors were not fined and the plays were not banned. Although it is true that Herodotus says that this reminder then led to the ban and fine, I shall be more concerned inwhat follows with the weeping of the Athenians than with the fine and the ban that were subsequently imposed, since the act of weeping spontaneously occurred on the scene itself. The fine came next, according toHerodotus, while the ban came later; they may have been anything but spontaneous.17 Thus, for the moment, I would like to focus on the scene of the actual performance that Herodotus describes: namely, the performance of The Fall ofMiletus and the tears produced by the reminder of catastrophe. This may seem a counter-intuitive way to proceed, given that the ban and the fine have received the most attention from readers of Herodotus' account. However, given how little we know about the actual motives for the fine and the ban, I would like to focus instead upon the more immediate connection, manifested on the scene described by Herodotus, between the Athenians' memory of the catastrophe and their tears. It is, of course, hardly surprising to find an audience weeping at the close of a tragedy. What is striking, however, is the way in which the tears described by Herodotus do not appear to be a manifestation of katharsis, nor do the tears seem to result primarily from the mimetic force of Phrynichus' play. Indeed, already a certain revision of Aristotle's account of tragedy in the Poetics is in order; for the tears that resulted from the performance of The Fall ofMiletus are not reducible solely to the effect of its "imitation of action" let alone to the plot or script of Phrynichus' play. the lamentation was not kathartic; it didn't to have educated, Evidently appear instructed, some moral; nothing was learned from Phrynichus' play.18 Nor or instilled does it seem, according to Herodotus, that the audience wept because they were simply affected emotionally by what they saw, the way a contemporary audience might be affected by a play about the Second World War. Rather, it seems that their lamentation was the result of a shared recollection of a suffering that was theirs?oikeia 16 on the authority see For more of Herodotus' account, Joseph Roisman, "On Phrynichos' Sack," 16 17, especially n. 7. 17 Sir Hugh Lloyd-Jones has suggested that the ban and fine were imposed because of "an event connecting Phrynichus with the archon Themistocles," who wanted the Athenians to prepare for war against the Persians ("Problems," 233-38). Joseph Roisman has suggested that this "interpretation of the Phrynichus affair in terms of the politics of the time has proved ... is known unsatisfactory nothing of the play to indicate whether it was pro- or anti- Persian in tone and message" ("On Phrynichos' Sack," 16). In any event, the ban and fine?like most acts of censorship?may likely have had motives that extend far beyond the performance of Phyrnichus' play itself. My interest here, rather, is the specific interaction of the scene as such. 18 Obviously, the term katharsis would require a more lengthy interpretation than can be provided here. For a good overview of the problem, see Stephen Halliwell, Aristotle's Poetics, 350-57; Andrew Ford, "Katharsis: The Ancient Problem," in Performativity and Performance, ed. A. Parker and Eve Sedgwick (New York: Routledge Press, 1995), 109-32; also see Jonathan Lear's contribution to Essays on Aristotle's Poetics, ed. Am?lie Oksenberg Rorty (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), 315-40.
  • 6. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 85 kaka, "something bad that touched home"; the play "reminded them" [anamnesanta] of what they already remembered. At the very dawn of the Western theatrical tradition, therefore, it is possible to glimpse an effect of tragedy that differs markedly from the way in which theatrical a century later, experience gets described by Plato and Aristotle more than descrip tions which have characterized thinking about the theatre ever since. That is to say, it may be possible to discern a singular, unrepeatable and un-representable?and therefore "pre-philosophical" scene?the features of which are irreducible to the work that is performed. Clearly, Herodotus is describing a highly unusual scene. Were Phrynichus' play performed today, or even one hundred years after Phrynichus' death, weeping from a shared memory would be an unlikely result. This is not simply due to the fact that such historical tragedies gained wider acceptance among the Athenians; the point here is not simply that Phrynichus or the archon Themistocles failed to make the material palatable to the audience?although it is true that, "after a perhaps tactful interval of fifteen years or so" and after the defeat of the Persians themselves in 48(M79, and then Aeschylus were able to stage historical dramas Phyrnichus, successfully.19 Rather, according to Herodotus' account, the tears had to do precisely with the uniqueness of that audience. Apparently the tears were the manifestation of a lived recollection of a traumatic event, a memory that of course died with the people who bore it. The memory in question is, of course, not an individual or private recollection of a psychic injury or trauma?but rather a shared, public, mortal memory of a "catastrophe" [kaka]. The term "memory" therefore needs to be understood in this context as designating an essential part of the singular, finite relation of the spectatorship?for it is this shared memory that, in large part, distinguishes them from all other potential audiences of the play. Indeed, what Herodotus' description of the scene makes clear above all else is the singularity of this relation among witnesses. Thus; ^although Phrynichus was fined and the play censored, we ourselves might hesitate before blaming the tears exclusively on the play or dramatic work itself. Phrynichus' production no doubt "imitated a complete action" (to use Aristotle's definition) that called to mind something that those Athenians who saw itwished to forget. But this "imitation of action" in and of itself would, again, not result in an identical reaction were it performed elsewhere, or at another time, before a different group of spectators. What is decisive inHerodotus' account is not the work by the poet Phrynichus, nor the form or content of the theatrical oeuvre, but rather the scene of its singular performance as it is recounted by the historian. Moreover Iwould like to suggest that this makes possible an analytical distinction, which Iwill try to elaborate inwhat follows, between the scene and the work. That is to say, by relying upon Herodotus' testimony we can see clearly that the scene itself? the actual enactment of the play and spontaneous weeping that followed?is ulti mately irreducible to the work that was performed, to any archival content or remnant that could survive the lives of those on the scene. 19 But then, what would the fact that "no known Greek after Aeschylus' Persians explain tragedy dealt with a contemporary theme centered on historical events"? See Paul Cartledge, "'Deep Plays': Theatre as Process in Greek Life," in Easterling, The Cambridge 24-25. Companion,
  • 7. 86 / Paul A. Kottman In this spirit, I shall not begin with an exegesis of Phrynichus' play itself, nor shall I attempt to analyze the particular mode of its performance.20 Such an analysis would be impossible anyway, since no copy of the play's script is extant. It may seem somewhat disingenuous to take advantage of that fact; one would hardly like to rejoice in the loss or destruction of a play. But in this case, the very lack of the work, or text, provides a certain window of opportunity, or, rather, the occasion for a critical and methodological purchase. That is to say, it produces a state of affairs in which one is forced, as it were, to consider the theatrical experience of the scene itself, through Herodotus' testimony, as distinct from the play or work. Of course, Herodotus himself gives us little to go on. We do not learn how Phrynichus' play was performed, or what in the actors' speech or gesture would have been particularly unwelcome to the Athenians. In fact, it is as ifHerodotus intuitively of the scene lay not in the performance as such, but rather grasped that the significance with the reaction of the Athenians. While this paucity of information might generate some frustration, it is here something of a bonus. For, in this case, Herodotus' narration stands, interestingly, in contrast to the sort of historical discourse of which he is, according to Cicero, the "father," since his focus is not so much on what happened but rather on the lived scene of that happening.21 It is the spectatorship, and not the spectacle, which is decisive here. Or, better, it is that particular spectatorship which is decisive, for it is of those who constituted a community of witnesses, in that they collectively recalled the events recounted by Phrynichus' play upon seeing it performed. The Fall ofMiletus was what we might call a reminder that triggered this remem brancer?but itwas not itself fully responsible for it, since, after all, the memory was already in the hearts of those Athenians well before they attended that ill-fated performance. Indeed, the fact that an audience today would most likely not react in the same manner means that those Athenians were already, prior to the performance, a Their shared remembrance of the capture of unique polity?or potential community. Miletus itself iswhat distinguishes them from any other potential audience and what makes their reaction so singular. This singularity is in fact what Herodotus' account of the scene leads us to consider, for it becomes clear that the tears of those Athenians confirmed their collective recollection of the original battle. 20 an excuse Obviously, the fact that there is no extant script of Phyrnichus' play gives me to "refuse" to read it. Nevertheless, even if the were extant, Iwould want to proceed with a that play methodology textual traces from differs somewhat from that of classicists who interpret Greek drama based upon the period and the philological or social contexts of the plays themselves. For my purposes the point is not to debate the extent to which a comprehensive reading of a play by Sophocles, for example, is Rather, Iwould note that?in the case of Herodotus' account of Phrynichus, we are possible. simply not reading the play itself?but rather trying to come to terms with Herodotus' testimony regarding one scene. As a result, I cannot hope to offer an account of Herodotus' testimony that would particular derive from our current understanding of Greek tragedy in its context, for the context of the memory of the original battle is illegible and irretrievable. Rather, one might begin to look for ways inwhich the of such understanding is perhaps put into question by the anecdote Herodotus provides. possibility 21 from a lecture on Herodotus Cicero, De legibus 1,5; De oratore II, 55.1 take my cue here as well given White at U. C. Berkeley in the Fall, 1995. White suggested that Herodotus, rather than by Hayden facts or focusing on the events themselves, creates memorable scenes simply imparting through narrative techniques. sophisticated
  • 8. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 87 We are dealing, a scene wherein therefore, with the political identity of the is not a pre-existing class, or participants simply defined through membership, national affiliation?although those attributes clearly play a role here?nor through anything that they might have in common outside remembering the fall of Miletus and witnessing its theatrical representation. In fact, this is borne out of a close reading of Herodotus' own account?in which the nature of the recollection itself (hos anamnesanta oikeia kaka) hinges upon how one reads oikeia kaka, "their own catastrophe." As David Rosenbloom points out, in the period in question (478-456 BCE), "the relation between the inside and the outside of the city, between oikeia and allotria" was undergoing a kind of transformation; what "one's own" means here is very much in question.22 Indeed, the very fact that the Athenians could identify themselves so strongly with the Milesians, such that the Milesians' catastrophe (kaka) refers "to the Athenians' own troubles and misfortunes," underscores the extent towhich the polity?in its emergent form?is defined not by fixed borders, allegiances, or blood-ties.23 Rather, the polis emerges here, to borrow Arendt's phrase, as "a kind of organized remembrance."24 Put simply, what defines and distinguishes that spectatorship of Athenians from all other potential (or actual) spectatorship of the play is the remembrance they shared, and their ability to confirm that remembrance to one another.25 Or better, what defines their relationship is not something that could be abstracted from, or that is foreign to, the scene itself; rather, it arises from the living confirmation?the actual relation?of a shared remembrance made possible by the scene. Now, it could be objected that my choice of Phrynichus' The Fall of Miletus is somewhat disingenuous, given both its peculiar content and the fact that the text did not survive. What about, at the very least, Aeschylus' The Persians, which is an entire, extant example of a tragedy whose subject matter was within the living memory of its audience? In a sense, they make a natural pair. And admittedly, any comparison of the two ought to begin by asking why the earlier work was banned and its author fined, while the later work won first prize at the festival? What was it that made The Fall of Miletus so disagreeable in comparison to the well-received Persians? Interesting as they are, however, Iwould like to refrain from pursuing them here since aim is not to the works themselves, but rather to focus on the scene my analyze of one particular performance. Indeed pursuing these questions presupposes that the tears produced by The Fall of Miletus can be attributed, at some level, to the content or the form of Phrynichus' work?and that Aeschlyus' play succeeded, as it were, because of some discernable difference between the works themselves.26 This is, again, 22 See David Rosenbloom, "Myth, History and Hegemony in Aeschylus," in History, Tragedy, Theory, ed. Barbara Goff (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1995), 102. Roisman points out that oikeia is "patently contrasted" with allotria throughout Herodotus, which makes Rosenbloom's argument all the more pertinent for the passage in question here ("On Phrynichos' Sack," 17-18). 23 Roisman, "On Phrynichos' Sack," 18-19. 24 Arendt, The Human Condition, 198. 25 It has been suggested that the Athenians wept not just out of memory, but in anticipation of a similar disaster. However, there is no evidence to support such a view. On the contrary, a close reading of Herodotus' own text appears to suggest, that the conflation of memory and political precisely, are very much at stake here. See, again, Roiseman, "On Phrynichos' Sack." belonging 26 Such differences could be characterized in any number of ways. Vernant, for example, suggests that the events were not the Athenians, in contrast to their presented by Aeschylus regarded by
  • 9. 88 / Paul A. Kottman precisely the presupposition that I wish to challenge. By focusing on Herodotus' narrative about a non-extant play?as opposed to reading The Persians?I would like to strip bare some of our assumptions about locating the political sense of tragedy in the legible features of any given work. The point, from my perspective, is not finally to determine why the Athenians wept at seeing The Fall of Miletus, while The Persians was lauded. Given how little we know about the former, any explanation would be speculation anyway. Put simply, I am interested instead in the fact that they wept, and the fact that this is the focus of Herodotus' account of the scene. Rather than compare the two plays, therefore, it seems tome that a certain analytical purchase can be gained by insisting here on the difference between a singular scene, like the one to which Herodotus draws our attention, and a particular work like The Persians. Obviously, it is not always (though it is sometimes) the case that the performance of a dramatic work stages something that corresponds so recognizably to the lived memory of the spectators. Admittedly, the story that Herodotus provides is hardly the most typical sort of theatrical experience. for that matter, Nor is Aeschlyus' The Persians. Indeed Imight imagine an ulterior objection tomy guiding example: What is the political sense when what is performed, while itmay recount a familiar story, does not correspond to anyone's living memory, for instance, in the case of a legend like Oedipus, or a morality play like Everyman, or for that matter, one of Samuel Beckett's enigmatic short works? One might safely assume that Beckett's Waiting for Godot or Luigi Pirandello's Sei personaggi in cerca d'autore does not actively recount actual events that any potential spectator could remember as part of their own lived experience.27 What, then, could be said?from the position proposed in this essay?about the political or communal significance of a performance of a purely fictional work? Does it even make sense to speak, politically, of a rigorous distinction between historical works (like The Fall ofMiletus or The Persians) and manifestly fictional works? What Iwould like to argue is that the political sense of the theatre is not to be found in the distinction of any genre, form, or content of the work, nor even in any possible referential relation between the play and an outside reality or history upon which it is closely or loosely based. As far as the political essence of tragedy is concerned, the relation between the artwork and reality, or between discourse and its outside, is not decisive. What is decisive is the relation that is brought into being by the scene? through the action and speech of those present, or through the performed affirmation of a shared recollection. Consequently, it does not matter whether a play is pure fiction (Beckett) or a history play (Shakespeare's Richard IJJ or Henry V). The genre of the work it is not essential reaction to The Fall ofMiletus, as "their own" (Jean-Pierre Vernant and Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Myth and tran. Janet Lloyd [New York: Zone Books, 1990], 245). My point, however, is that whatever Tragedy, differences one traces, the fact remains that the singular scene recounted by Herodotus is not reducible to any describable features of Phrynichus' work. 27 in the United States still make disavowals of this sort motion pictures produced Symptomatically, that any relation between the characters and events of the film and actual persons or events by claming are coincidental. This disavowal, of course, seeks in principle to affirm (or hide behind) a rigorous distinction between fiction and truth?while at the same time or to, its possible admitting, responding confusion.
  • 10. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 89 here, nor is the dramatic work itself. For the Athenians, at least inHerodotus' view, the political value and significance of that peculiar early performance of Phrynichus' play lay in the relation among those gathered, rather than in the Aristotelian elements of the performance itself (mythos, lexis, opsis, etc.) or the historical meaning of the capture of Miletus. Indeed, the relation that is inaugurated by a shared remembrance of the original scene is the theatrical scene that Herodotus describes?quite apart from any consideration of the artistry, representation, or imitative quality of Phrynichus' The Fall ofMiletus. It is clear, after all, that the scenes recounted by Herodotus, both the battle itself and its ill-fated theatrical resurrection?like any singular scene worthy of the name?are not reducible to representation, imitation, or artistry. While this may seem counter intuitive, given the fact that we tend to think of a scene as that which is representable or repeatable by definition, it is nevertheless the singular unrepresentability of the scene that distinguishes it from the work or the artifice. Indeed, it could even be said that a scene becomes awork or an artifice precisely when it is abandoned to repetition or work in some sense the or effect of this re-presentation?the being consequence or continual "iterability" re-staging.28 In contrast, while the events of the battle of Miletus (or, for that matter, the Trojan the French Revolution, or the killings in Jenin) can be war, re-staged or represented (theatrically, verbally, televisually) ad infinitum, well beyond the lives of those who were there, the lived relation of those on the scene?which results from the actions themselves, and the shared memory they leave behind?absolutely resists representa tion or repetition beyond their life span. Put formulaically, while any word or deed {praxis, lexis) can be archived, recorded, or even re-enacted (visibly, audibly) well beyond the time and place of the event itself, in a potentially infinite way, the relation of those on the scene ismortal and cannot be archived. It resists representation. For this reason, Iwish to argue, it is the relation?always unique, each time brought into being either through words and deeds, or through a shared, living (and therefore potentially utterable) memory?which constitutes the scene as such, and is the most essential condition for any political sense. In short, a political account of theatrical to not so much with an of what is experience ought begin analysis performed (whether the play is fictional or historical)?but rather with an understanding of the relational aspect of the scene itself. In the same way, what happens in a historical or journalistic sense ought not to be the final place for for it is contemporary political meaning, precisely the reduction of politics to the representable content of this or that event, which obscures the mortality and fragility of the political relation, the lives, which are at stake. Back to the place of theatre in all this, it could be said that the performance of a fictional play or theatrical work?as witnessed by this or that spectatorship?is also first and foremost itself an actual event that is immediately political regardless of its form or content. In other words, to any consideration of its form or content, a prior 28 Here and this discussion, I have in mind throughout Jacques Derrida's work regarding the constitutive nature of repetition or as in to the literary work. See, representation, particularly regards for instance, Derek Attridge's interview with Derrida in Acts of Literature (New York: Routledge Press, 1992).
  • 11. 90 / Paul A. Kottman theatrical performance?like any combination of action and speech?is political only if, and insofar as, there remains ex more than one who can post facto person speak together inmemory of having been on the scene with others. To return to the of the scene, therefore, means to return to the relation essentiality that is brought about by the shared, living memory of what is collectively witnessed? a memory that is, through a paradoxical temporality which will need to be explored, constitutive of the scene itself, even as it appears to be merely its consequence. Whereas a work or representation survives through its radical indifference to the lives of the witnesses, the scene is nothing other than a lived relation that is?like the words and deeds from which it springs?absolutely mortal and contingent. Unpredictability and mortality are in fact constitutive of the scene, for in order to be what it is a scene requires?without any prior guarantee?that someone speak in itsmemory, especially to and for another who also bears that memory. Therefore, this subsequent testi mony?the speech that follows action?is not ontologically separate from the scene, no matter how much time passes between scene and testimony. Rather, the subsequent is the scene's most essential trait. testimony With all of this in mind, Iwould like now to situate that anomalous performance recounted by Herodotus within the distinction between scene and work that I am elaborating. For, inmy view, this is a distinction whose emergence is contemporane ous, both historically and conceptually, with the birth of tragedy in the traditional sense. Tragedy is born, according to tradition, precisely when the work breaks with the living scene and appears to stand alone as mimetic, over and against the sociality of life?in tension with life, but always at some distance from it. Where does the performance of Phrynichus' play, which occurred alongside the birth of tragedy, fitwithin this history? Is there something within the logic of the scene Herodotus describes that resists the conventional wisdom regarding the bond between tragedy and the polis? Let me first give a brief summary of the dominant view. Now, at first glance itmight appear that the sort of "common grief" (koinon achos) provoked by Phrynichus' play resembles the sort of public weeping that has come to be understood as one of the defining characteristics of Greek tragedy, as it developed especially in the works of Euripides and Sophocles.29 According to Charles Segal, for instance, the staging of "rituals of lamentation" marks the emergence of a polis that recognizes and confirms itself through the theatrical performance of communal practices, such as collective grieving.30 The difference between this sort of performance and the scene recounted by Herodotus, of course, lies in the fact that Phrynichus' play did not (as far as we know) stage this common grief within the performance itself; rather the performance actually produced it spontaneously among those gathered. In this sense, the response of the audience is itself part of the action of the scene, over and beyond the unpredictable character of the performance itself. In other words, there was no artifice, no ritualistic character to their grief.31 29 Koinon achos is a phrase taken from the chorus at the end of Euripides' Hippolytus, tran. Rober Bagg (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973), 1462. 30 See Charles Segal, Euripides and the Poetics of Sorrow (Durham: Duke University Press, 1993). 31 scene that Herodotus Again, this iswhy we are more interested in analyzing the singular describes than we are in interpreting the particular character of Phrynichus' work.
  • 12. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 91 Nevertheless, it is worth pausing briefly to consider the difference between Herodotus' account of Phrynichus' play and more contemporary accounts of subse quent works of Greek tragedy, which often contain scenes that explicitly perform or imitate acts of communal lamentation. This will help make clearer the difference I am trying to articulate between what I am calling the scene and the work to which it remains irreducible. The connection most frequently drawn among modern scholars between the evolution of tragedy and the theatrical appropriation or representation of communal life begins from the fact that a number of Greek tragedies appear self-consciously to appropriate rites of lamentation, or burial.32 In Sophocles' Antigone and communal Euripides' Hippolytus, for example, we find climactic scenes in which lamentation is both performed within the drama and implicitly elicited from the audience as well.33 To tarry with the example offered a moment ago, we might briefly recall Segal's analysis of Euripides' Hippolytus. In Euripides' play, as Segal argues convincingly, the performance of "rituals of lamentation" can be regarded as characterizing and reflecting an emerging polis that is "conscious" of itself as a community and cognizant of the theatre as an artifice through which that community is both represented and constituted. Segal suggests, for instance, that the chorus at the close of Hippolytus reveals that "koinon achos is the emotion proper to a theater that has become conscious of itself as a uniquely communal form." Indeed, the shift inHippolytus from the private grief of Phaedra that opens the play to the "common grief" with which the play closes seems to suggest, as Segal puts it, that "personal grief is lifted from the level of individual response to the level of self-consciously communal reaction."34 What Segal wants to underscore is the fact that tragedy represents an important moment in the formation of the polis's own self-awareness, an awareness that only emerged through the work of tragic representation. Ritual commemoration or suffering, he argues, was imitated in order to "reflect on the ways in which Greek society represents itself such collective as rituals, festivals."35 through expressions myth, Now, what is important for our purposes is not so much Segal's ostensible focus on rituals of lamentation or the fact that the Greeks represented their own rituals to themselves through the performance of tragedies. Again, the perspective I am 32 a start see Charles As Alcestis: How to Die a Normal Death in Greek Tragedy," Segal, "Euripides' in Death and Representation, ed. Sarah Webster Goodwin and Elizabeth Bronfen (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993), 213-41; Charles Segal, "Lament and Closure in Antigone," in Sophocles' Tragic World MA: Harvard University Press, 1995), 119-37; Nicole Loraux, (Cambridge, a Woman MA: Harvard Press, 1987). Tragic Ways of Killing (Cambridge, University 33 Charles Segal has written about the cues within both Antigone and Hippolytus that call the audience to respond with pity and fear at appropriate moments in the play ("Lament and Closure," 120, and "Catharsis, Audience and Closure," in Tragedy and the Tragic, ed. M. S. Silk [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996], 149-72). See also P. E. Easterling's response to Segal's piece in the same collection. 34 Segal, Euripides, 127. See also Segal, "Catharsis, Audience and Closure," in Tragedy and the Tragic: Greek Theatre and Beyond, ed. M. S. Silk (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1966), 157. In this latter piece, Segal seeks to expand Aristotle's notion of katharsis by giving to the collective . . . "greater emphasis communal experience." That is, Segal seeks to understand the participatory nature of lamentation as something that opens up katharsis beyond the individual's experience of pity and fear, examined by Aristotle in the Poetics. 35 Segal, "Catharsis," 157.
  • 13. 92 / Paul A. Kottman proposing is neither anthropological nor hermeneutical. Rather than focusing on what was represented, or how the polis represented itself to itself through dramatic works, it is important to recognize simply that Segal's thesis presupposes that the polis found itself?that is, it seems to have accomplished a certain self-identification and organiza tion?through whatever was represented to it. Indeed, Segal's analysis leads us to conclude that the emergence of Greek tragedy marks a fundamental shift in the formation of community, a shift that is manifested especially in the city's nascent reflection upon itself through tragic representation. Put simply, the very fact that Greek tragedy develops through a self-conscious appropriation of the communal experience of lamentation signals, for Segal, a shift away from a community that was constituted through the spontaneity of lived ritual as such, towards a community that gathers around a shared representation of the act of mourning. The peculiarity of tragedy, from this perspective, is that it emerges as a communal experience in which the communal itself is ex-propriated by the dramatic work or spectacle.36 Or put another way, with the birth of tragedy, communal life itself appears to have been given over, and henceforth subjected to, the order of representation.37 With the birth of tragedy the community of spectators begins to find itself in, and in fact to constitute itself through, the work of a shared self-representation. Of course, this self-representation ismore than amere self-reflection. For the Greeks, according to Jean-Pierre Vernant, tragedy did not simply offer an uncritical mirror of the polis; rather tragedy was the putting-into-question of the polis itself. That is to say, tragedy "depicted the city rent and divided against itself" in at least two senses38: first, insofar as the tragedies themselves?in both form and content?presented the polis various crises, and second, insofar as the dramatic itself undergoing representation could be seen as taking on a life of its own, quite apart from the lives of the spectators, even as that representation also played a crucial role in the social life of the polis, at city-sponsored competitions and festivals.39 In other words, the order of tragic a constitutive role in the of social life, representation played organization paradoxi cally by mamtaining an essential distance from, or indifference to, that living reality. 36 For this reason, the phenomenon of Greek tragedy already brings about the expropriation of lived that Guy Debord as the mark of contemporary At the beginning of his community postulates society. treatise, Debord claims that "all that once was directly lived has become mere representation." Is this not also the very shift that defines the emergence of Greek for instance as it is traced in the tragedy, work of Jean-Pierre Vernant? See Guy Debord, The Society of the Spectacle, tran. Donald Nicholson Smith (New York: Zone Books, 1995), 12. 37 It is true that, in the context we are discussing, this order of representation is manifestly or dramatic. However, it ought to be understood as discursive as well. Indeed, spectacular implicitly Aristotle himself is already toward the dramatic or theatrical as reducible to disposed considering discourse (lexis), especially where the question of mimetic representation is concerned. See Aristotle Poetics, chapter 3; Halliwill, Aristotle's, 128; and Domenico Pesce's excellent essay to the introductory Italian translation of Aristotle's Poetics (Milan: Bompiani, 2000), 26. 38 and Tragedy, 33. Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth 39 Vernant and others have shown that the very form of Greek tragedy, for instance the lexical difference between the chorus and the protagonists, depicts the structural distance between the social life of the polis and the dramatic representation that is essential to tragedy. See Vernant and Vidal Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 29-48 and passim.
  • 14. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 93 Vernant has offered perhaps the most articulate account of this phenomenon, regarding the origins of Greek tragedy. For him, the polis acquires its democratic form precisely at the moment in which it learns to find itself through what it represents to itself. But this self-finding now has the paradoxical character of a "putting into crisis/' For that which is found is now at once the most familiar and intimate being of the community and its ex-propriated representation. Indeed, Vernant claims that the newly democratic polis "turned itself into a theater" through the performance of tragedy in festivals or contests, at the same time putting itself "into question."40 Like Arendt, or Aristotle for that matter, Vernant sees the polis itself as emerging like a sort of stage whereupon the cultural phenomenon of tragedy served to open the city up for debate.41 Noting, for example, that Greek tragedy "takes heroic legend as its material," Vernant emphasizes that tragedy presents the hero not as a model, like in epic, but instead as a problem or subject of debate.42 First of all, Tragedy does this, of course, by setting the heroic or tragic figure on stage, before the eyes of the spectator, as opposed to relying upon verbal narration. Thus, the tragic heroes "are made to seem present, characters truly there, although at the same time they are portrayed as figures who cannot possibly be there since they belong to somewhere else, to an invisible beyond."43 The tragic performance is therefore regarded as in some way both familiar to and distant from the spectatorship?familiar enough to allow for identification and distant enough to allow for reflection, critique, and subsequent discussion. In this way, too, writes Vernant, tragedy "played a decisive role inman's apprehen sion of 'fiction,'"44 for the characters that were on before the of presented stage, eyes the public, afforded at once a phenomenal were reality and a fictitious status, According to Vernant, a certain "consciousness of fiction" emerged in fifth-century Athens; one that remained "essential to the dramatic spectacle," such that "it seems to be both its condition and its product."45 That is to say, while it is impossible unconditionally to locate the origin of tragedy in a nascent "consciousness of fiction," or vice-versa, it is nevertheless impossible to dissociate fully the former from the latter. Each appears as the condition for the birth of the other.46 40 Although tragedy "appears rooted in social reality/' he writes, "it does not merely reflect that reality, but calls it into question." See Jean-Pierre Vernant, "Myth and Tragedy," in Essays on Aristotle's Poetics, ed. Am?lie O. Rorty (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), 36. 41 Ibid. 42 Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 23-29 and passim. 43 Ibid., 243; Segal makes a similar claim: "Tragedy combines the distancing effects of myth and fiction, with the agonistic model of debate and conflict. It speaks to the assembled citizens of the polis in the here and now of a time full of crises, dangers and conflicts; but it uses a frame of remote, legendary events that enables the poet to look far beyond the passions and anxieties of the present moment" (Euripides, 5). 44 Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy, 242-43. 45 Ibid., 244. 46 As if to drive this point home, Vernant notes that this "new experience afforded by the tragic spectacle" (ibid., 242) was most likely a decisive impetus behind the theory of mimesis-as-imitation articulated by Plato and Aristotle. Not surprisingly, theatrical experience turns out to be prior, so to to the determination of mimesis-as-imitation; indeed, the theatrical scene deter speak, conceptual mines the mode of its philosophical emergence.
  • 15. 94 / Paul A. Kottman Now, inmy view, what is decisive in Vernant's analysis is the way inwhich tragedy as an imitative reflection, or self-conscious works performance only insofar as it portrayed something that was already historically or temporally distant from the audience.47 Interestingly, Vernant notes that this distance had less to do with the mere passage of time than with the fact that the events represented by Greek tragedy did not belong to the living memory of the Athenian spectators. Likewise, he suggests that the representational, fictitious, or mimetic quality of the play was not simply due to the technique of the production, the labor of the actor, or the fact that tragedy comprises spectacle, not just speech. To be sure, all of these things played a role in the becoming fiction of tragedy, its break with epic, and its emerging place as the problematic reflection of the polis. But Vernant's analysis allows us to direct our attention beyond these more formal qualities of tragedy to the fact that theatrical experience exceeds myth and becomes a fictional representation (mimesis) only insofar as the events portrayed are, a priori, understood as "happening somewhere else" or belonging to a mythical past that is by now beyond the grasp of living remembrance.48 Put another it is precisely way, by becoming a itself over to work?giving representation, repetition, and reproduction?that tragedy simultaneously differenti ates itself from myth, which is to say, differentiates itself from the immediacy between living memory and communal life inwhich myth finds its home.49 The birth of tragedy signals, ifwe follow Vernant's logic, an irreparable rift between the work as it appears before the community in dramatic representation, and the living memory of what is being represented. In the terms of my argument here, Vernant's account leads to the following conclusion: the birth of tragedy lies in nothing other than the radical separation of work from scene. Interestingly, it is in the light of this division that Vernant names Phrynichus' Miletus as somewhat anomalous. While we know of other plays The Fall of 47 An important exception to this account of tragedy is the chorus. Vernant and Vidal-Naquet suggest that the chorus embodies "the collective truth ... of the polis" over and against the "otherness" of the tragic hero (ibid., 243). More recently, other scholars have argued that the chorus is even more democratic than the Athenian polis in that it included old men, women, slaves, and foreigners; therefore, the chorus represents an ulterior and complex set of problems with to the relation regard between the emerging democracy and dramatic practices. Given the inevitable limits of scope, however, I cannot include a discussion of the chorus here. The interested reader could see, as a start, the following: Vernant and Vidal-Naquet, Myth and Tragedy; Oddone Longo, "The Theater of the Polis," in Nothing to Do with Dionysus?: Athenian Drama in Its Social Context, ed. John Winkler and Froma Zeitlin (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990), 12-19; John Gould, "Tragedy and Collective Experience," in Tragedy and the Tragic, ed. M. S. Silk (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 217-43, and Simon GoldhiU's response to Gould's piece in the same volume. ^Vernant and and Tragedy, 246 and passim. In contrast to tragedy, the Vidal-Naquet, Myth transmission of myth was tantamount to the transmission of memory itself; living through epic remembrance, in short, is absolutely essential to epic song. For more on this, see Eric Havelock, The Muse Learns to Write (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), especially 70-73; Albert Lord, Epic Singers and Oral Tradition (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991) and The Singer of Tales (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000). 491 am indebted here and throughout to Jean-Luc Nancy's analysis of myth in The Inoperative University of Minnesota Press, 1991), especially 45-47, which has helped me Community (Minneapolis: to understand the stakes of Vernant's in ways I otherwise would not have seen. analysis Especially relevant here is Nancy's elaboration of the relation between myth and scene in the third chapter.
  • 16. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 95 whose subject was historical, Phrynichus' is "the first tragedy of which we are informed."50 For Vernant, Phrynichus' play?perhaps because it lies at the begirvning of the tradition?represents something like an alternative to the trajectory that Greek tragedy, in his view, seems to have followed. the one hand, we have the dominant On tradition described by Segal, Vernant, and others, which establishes tragedy's emergence as fiction or mimetic art through the appropriation of communal rituals or heroic legends that already belonged to an immemorial past. This view, which is recognizable in nearly every theory of perform ance that has its foundations in classical Greek philosophy, tends to regard the development of theatrical experience as dependent upon a fundamental mimetic distance between the spectacle and the lives of the spectators.51 Vernant's and Segal's analyses would belong to this tradition, even while attempting to account for it. They could even be said to be the very product of this tradition, for this mimetic distance is, according to the philosophical and critical tradition to which we belong, the most essential feature of any artwork or discursive representation. And this distance is generally thought to be commensurate with its foreignness to the living memory of those who encounter the mimetic performance. On the other hand, we have Phrynichus' play, which was "not a legendary" tragedy, as Vernant notes, but rather "a tragedy of contemporary events."52 Now, Vernant concludes that the public condemnation of The Fall ofMiletus resulted from the fact that the play portrayed events, which he says "were too close" to the lives of the spectators. The play, he writes, "did not allow for the distancing, the transposition that made it possible for feelings of pity or terror to be displaced into a different register, no longer experienced in the same way as in real life, but immediately apprehended and understood as fiction."53 Vernant thus imagines Phrynichus' play to be an irregularity, which did not meet the criteria for "fiction" or "mimesis" towhich the Athenians were gradually becoming accustomed. The scene was too close to "real life." Although Vernant does not say so, the logic of his argument leads one to conclude that the scene Herodotus describes cannot properly be understood as an artwork or discursive representation. Indeed, for Vernant the censure of Phrynichus' work was a conse quence of an already accepted and established "consciousness of fiction," which was in fact offended a that was too-close-to-the-bone.54 What made the by play play exceptional, it would seem, was that it could not be received as mere fiction. For Vernant, of course, this is an exception that only serves to confirm the rule, that is, to confirm the account of tragedy as commensurate with the distance between fiction and life. 50 David Rosenbloom, "Myth, History," 102. For a list of other non-extant tragedies that allegedly dealt with historical see H. D. Broadhead, "Introduction," Persae of Aeschylus subjects, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), xvii. 51 In a sense, this claim calls for no justification. Since Plato and Aristotle, at least in the tradition of thought which this article attempts to analyze, mimesis has been the key to the question of the relation between artworks dramatic works) and the world or nature. (especially 52 Vernant, Myth and Tragedy, 244. 53 Ibid. 54 Ibid. Malcolm Heath makes a similar that Phrynichus' was censured assumption, claiming play "because the tears were shed over misfortunes that touched the audience too closely, them reminding of their own troubles." See Heath, The Poetics of Greek Tragedy, 9.
  • 17. 96 / Paul A. Kottman But are things so clear? Given that Phrynichus' play (494 BCE) is the first tragedy of which we have any record, can it be certain that the censure of The Fall Miletus after of this early performance was a consequence of its failure to be "immediately appre hended and understood as fiction?" Particularly what if, as Vernant himself claims, this "consciousness of fiction" itself emerged partly as a consequence of the intensify ing consumption of tragedy? What, after all, accounts for the appetite for fiction as opposed to real life that Vernant supposes to have existed? Why must the history of tragedy begin with the self-reflective apprehension of mimesis? Might it not be the case that the trajectory outlined by Vernant, Segal, and all those who follow in Aristotle's footsteps?which equates tragedy and the emergence of a formal theatrical consciousness with the contemplative apprehension of tragedy-as imitation?presupposes a prior recognition of fiction that may in fact be the conse quence of a lived remembrance that distinguishes, without thought or reflection, between the real and the imitation? Perhaps the scene described by Herodotus forces us to consider the living scene as a condition without which like imitation something or a consciousness of fiction would not emerge. After all, it seems clear that those Athenians who banned Phrynichus' play were aware that the play was not the same as the events that it portrayed. That is, they thing recognized the performance for what itwas and quite naturally did not confuse itwith the real capture of Miletus. Indeed, this recognition is what was manifested in the censure. After all, one can censure a work, not historical events. play's only And it is equally clear that this recognition of the play as an imitative performance was not the result of a formal convention or "consciousness of fiction." Still less does the play's reception seem to suggest that the performance of this tragedy signaled a questioning of the city or anything like Aristotle's phronesis. It could even be said, without exaggeration, that the recognition of Phrynichus' play as an "imitation" of real events came to those Athenians without reflection, without a "conscious" apprehension of fiction. Indeed, the apprehension of theatrical mimesis by the Athenians in the scene Herodotus describes is utterly foreign to the sort of theoretical contemplation that will come to characterize the philosopher's noetic grasp of mimesis in Plato's work a later. century First of all, therefore, this scene marks the dissociation of the apprehension of mimesis from the act of thoughtful debate, understanding, or collective wisdom (phronesis) that, according to Aristotle and Vernant, characterizes theatrical experi ence.55 Indeed, to paraphrase Arendt, it could be said axiomatically that theatrical experience in fact antedates the vita contemplativa presupposed by classical philosophy's account of the theatre,56 for Herodotus' account presents us with a scene inwhich the conscious recognition of theatrical artifice fails to result in, or coincide with, the "fictional distance" that characterizes Aristotle's definition of theatrical experience. Instead, the artifice "calamaties" that were, as Herodotus "too close to presented says, 55 Aristotle underscores the way in which the pleasure of watching or an imitation coincides hearing with a sort of consciousness or the imitative nature of the spectacle itself. See knowledge regarding Poetics 1448M4-15. 56 See Arendt's discussion of Pythagoras in The Life ofMind, 93.
  • 18. THE SCENEBEFORE PHILOSOPHY / 97 home" (oikeia kaka), too close to allow the play to stand as a subject for debate, or for the feelings that it inspired to mature into detached, deliberative reflection. The recognition of the play's artifice, therefore, appears to be a result of the immediacy between the mimesis of Phrynichus' play and the living remembrance of its spectators, rather than the result of the play's distance from their living memory, as Vernant supposes. It is as if the mimetic aspect of Phrynichus' play lay not so much in the artifice of its theatrical manifestation, but rather in the play's function as a witness for events that the spectators had themselves seen. The theatrical scene Herodotus describes is constituted most essentially through the very relation between living memory and mimetic performance that, according to tradition, characterizes myth as opposed to tragedy. Thus, something like an alternative account of the origins of the theatrical scene, and consequently of the relation between mimesis and politics as well, begins to emerge?an account whose origins lie at the very outset of the political and theatrical tradition that we inherit. Rather than focus on a nascent consciousness of fiction or imitation, or on the self-conscious representation of the polis in a dramatic work, it is instead the singularity of the scene that comes to the fore here, from which the political sense of the event (both the battle itself and its representation) arises. Revising Aristotle's account of tragedy in the Poetics, we could say that the mimetic character of the scene does not lie necessarily in the event of the performance (opsis), or in the structure of the artistic work (plot, diction, mythos, lexis). Likewise, the habit of reducing the term mimesis to a general, essentially Platonic, determination of the relation between "art and nature" or "imitation and often obscures the term's reality" own ambiguity. The problem lies in this: the political sense of mimesis?that which relates the theatrical experience of being on the scene to political life?cannot be fully grasped in terms of the fictional or artistic character of performance or work, and its relation to an outside reality. Rather, mimesis acquires its political sense in theatrical experience insofar as it corresponds to the living relation of the scene. A radical politics of mimesis, in sum, would therefore need tomove beyond the centrality of representa tion, of what is represented, and begin to take account of this correspondence.