SlideShare una empresa de Scribd logo
1 de 32
Descargar para leer sin conexión
GENETIC TESTING OF HUMAN EMBRYOS: 
ETHICAL CHALLENGES AND POLICY CHOICES 
Kathy Hudson, Ph.D., Susannah Baruch, J.D., Gail Javitt, J.D., M.P.H. 
The Genetics and Public Policy Center 
Berman Bioethics Institute 
Johns Hopkins University* 
Introduction 
Today, there are some one million people for whom the journey toward 
personhood began when a fertility specialist, peering through a microscope, carefully 
added sperm to egg in a glass petri dish – a process known as in vitro fertilization. There 
have also been dramatic advances in our scientific understanding of the human genome 
during this time period, which has led to the ability to test for genetic alterations 
associated with diseases and other inherited characteristics. Currently there are tests for 
over 1000 genetic diseases available or under development, and the number is steadily 
growing.1 
The independent fields of IVF and genetic testing each present a host of issues 
that are technically, legally and ethically complicated. But now, the worlds of genetic 
testing and assisted reproduction have converged, most notably in preimplantation 
genetic diagnosis (PGD)—technology that allows parents to choose which embryos to 
implant in a woman’s womb based on genetic test results. The arrival of PGD has 
engendered a host of new scientific, social, ethical and political quandaries. Many people 
have begun to consider not just the implications of this new genetic diagnostic tool but 
whether core ethical and practical concerns surrounding IVF are really all that settled. 
* This chapter was written with the generous support of the Pew Charitable Trusts. The opinions expressed 
are those of the authors. 
1 <http://www.genetests.org/>.
Adding genetic testing to the IVF process means that medical providers and 
scientists can now be deeply involved in the molecular mechanics of the most profound 
and mysterious of human activities: creating life. This intercession of technology into 
human reproduction evokes a range of responses. For some, it is a deeply offensive act in 
which science literally subsumes the role of God. For others, it allows science to alleviate 
the anguish of genetic disease and infertility. These dueling opinions reveal both PGD’s 
potential benefits and its possible risks. As with much modern scientific research, there is 
a basic tension between concerns about the adverse consequences of unregulated research 
and fears that we may fail to develop important technologies if we apply too much 
restraint. Regardless of how one feels about it, PGD is a powerful tool, for it allows 
parents to identify and select the genetic characteristics of their children. As a society, we 
must ask whether and under what conditions PGD should be used. 
In this chapter, we provide an overview of PGD and an analysis of the ethical, 
legal and social issues that surround it. We then present an array of policy options that 
could be employed to govern PGD’s development and use. This essay surveys the 
situation of PGD in order to encourage discussion and facilitate policymaking; it does not 
endorse one course of action over another. The challenge with new biomedical 
technology is for the public and policymakers to keep informed despite the rapid pace of 
change. We believe that new genetic technologies that alter how we have babies, and 
indeed what babies we have, are so important that the public and its representatives must 
be engaged in the discussion and formulation of policies. 
2
I. What is Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis? 
PGD is a process in which embryos developed outside of the womb are tested for 
particular genetic characteristics, usually genetic abnormalities that cause serious disease, 
before being transferred to a woman’s uterus.2 It is always performed within the context 
of in vitro fertilization (IVF), for reasons that will be developed below. 
PGD derives from recent advances in both reproductive medicine and genetics. In 
1978, scientists achieved the first viable human pregnancy from an egg fertilized outside 
the womb. Around this time, geneticists’ understanding of the basis of inherited disorders 
increased. Genetic researchers developed a number of tests to detect specific disorders. 
Eventually clinicians were able to apply these tests to a small amount of genetic material 
taken from an egg or embryo. The use of these tests in a human embryo (in vitro) or fetus 
(in utero) enabled prenatal detection of genetic abnormalities. 
PGD is a multi-step process involving egg extraction, in vitro fertilization, cell 
biopsy, genetic analysis and embryo transfer. Eggs removed from the mother (after she 
has been given drugs to stimulate egg production) are fertilized in the laboratory. Once 
the egg is fertilized in vitro, it develops into an embryo. Most commonly, genetic tests 
are performed on one or two cells taken from an embryo two to four days after 
fertilization.3 The sample may be analyzed two ways: by chromosomal analysis to assess 
the number or structure of chromosomes present in the cells; or by DNA analysis to detect 
specific gene mutations. Regardless of the methods, the results of preimplantation genetic 
diagnosis are used to inform the selection of embryos for transfer to a woman’s uterus. 
2 Munne, Wells 239. 
3 Handyside, Delhanty 271. Alternatively, genetic tests can be performed on polar body cells, which are 
cast off by the egg as it matures and is fertilized. Verlinsky, Kuliev (1996) 13. 
3
PGD enables two types of reproductive decisions. First, it permits doctors and 
prospective parents to select embryos for implantation that do not have a genetic 
abnormality associated with a specific disease, such as cystic fibrosis. Second, it enables 
doctors and parents to select embryos that possess a desired genetic trait, such as a tissue 
type that matches that of an ailing sibling. 
Since PGD was first made available to facilitate embryo selection, more than 
1,000 babies have been born worldwide following a preimplantation genetic test.4 PGD 
was initially developed to detect serious single gene disorders5 and not to alleviate 
infertility. More recently, however, PGD has been used as an adjunct to standard IVF to 
detect abnormalities in chromosome number, called aneuploidy, that arise during egg or 
embryo development. Some IVF providers recommend PGD for patients over 35 or those 
with repeated IVF failure.6 Since over 1% of all U.S. newborns are IVF babies, and since 
more than half of IVF patients are of advanced reproductive age,7 aneuploidy screening 
likely accounts for the biggest growth area in the use of PGD. There is no required 
tracking of the number of PGD procedures performed or of the purpose for which they 
are performed, however, so a definitive breakdown of how many PGD procedures are 
performed to detect single gene mutations versus aneuploidy is not available. 
Virtually any of the hundreds of genetic tests now commercially available (and 
the many more in development) could be used in PGD. The more tests available, the 
more options there are for embryonic selection. Possible (but controversial) applications 
4 Kuliev, Verlinsky (2004) 229. 
5 The first PGD cases were performed to determine embryo sex, in order to avoid X-linked disease. 
Munne, Wells 239. Other early uses included detection of genes causing cystic fibrosis, Tay Sachs disease, 
and Lesch-Nyhan syndrome. Verlinsky et al. (1992) 103-110; Delhanty 1217-1227. 
6 Ferraretti et al. 694-699; Munne (2003) S70-S76. 
7 Kuliev, Verlinsky (2003) 233. 
4
of PGD include its use to select an embryo that is an immunological match for a sick 
sibling;8 to select the sex of an embryo in the absence of a sex-linked disease risk;9 to test 
embryos for gene mutations associated with diseases such as early-onset Alzheimer 
disease10 or Huntington disease11 that do not appear until later in life; or to test for 
mutations that indicate a heightened but uncertain risk of developing a particular disease 
such as cancer.12 
There are inherent limits to the use of PGD to avoid disease or select for certain 
traits. First, not all diseases have a clearly diagnosable genetic component. Many diseases 
and traits are the result of a complex interaction between multiple genetic and 
environmental factors. Second, if PGD is used to detect genes that indicate a heightened 
risk for a particular disease, such as hereditary breast cancer, the fact that such a gene is 
detected in the embryo does not mean that a person who developed from that embryo 
would definitely develop the disease. Finally, it is important to remember that PGD 
cannot create new genetic characteristics that neither parent has. PGD can allow parents 
to select only among the genetic combinations present in the embryos they have 
produced. 
II. Ethical Issues and Policy Approaches 
PGD raises important concerns related to whether and when it should be used, its 
safety and effectiveness, costs and access, and what it would mean to live in a society 
where one’s genetics become more a matter of choice than chance. Current oversight of 
PGD’s safety, accuracy and effectiveness is extremely limited, as is the practice of IVF 
5 
8 Verlinsky et al. (2001) 3130-3133. 
9 Robertson (2003a) 468-470 
10 Verlinsky et al. (2002) 1018-1021. 
11 Sermon et al. 591-598. 
12 Rechitsky et al. 148-155.
generally. Limits based on ethical, moral or societal concerns are almost nonexistent. The 
question is whether additional oversight is needed and if so, what issues it should address 
and how it should be structured. These are complicated dilemmas about which there has 
been little discussion or opportunity to form agreement. 
Since PGD requires IVF, it is mainly used today by a relatively small number of 
women who are willing to undergo IVF to avoid a known serious or fatal genetic 
condition or who are unable to get pregnant without IVF because of infertility problems. 
For people who already turn to IVF to treat infertility, PGD may become a more common 
tool to screen for genetic variants ranging from the serious to what some might consider 
trivial. For the moment, one would expect very few prospective parents who do not need 
IVF to get pregnant and who do not seek to avoid a serious or fatal known genetic 
condition to utilize PGD. Nonetheless, as the number of genetic tests that can be 
employed successfully in PGD increases and IVF techniques improve, it is possible that 
more prospective parents may consider using IVF and PGD to “choose” their embryo. 
Hence, with the advent of new reproductive biotechnologies – of which PGD is 
exemplary – there is likely to be growing public interest in developing policies that 
address ethical, technical and social concerns raised by the genetic testing of embryos. 
Below, we summarize the range of concerns about PGD and outline the possible policy 
alternatives that could guide the future development and use of this technology. 
6
Is PGD “ethical”? 
The ethical and moral ramifications of PGD have attracted significant attention. 
Some categorically oppose PGD’s use under any circumstances,13 while others have 
focused on the circumstances under which it may and may not be acceptable.14 
As noted previously, PGD enables the selection of one or more embryos over 
others on the basis of genetic makeup. Embryos deemed genetically undesirable will 
likely be destroyed if they are not frozen indefinitely. Thus, PGD and the underlying IVF 
process involve the creation and, frequently, the destruction of human embryos. PGD is 
therefore objectionable to people who believe that a unique human being, deserving of 
the protections of a born person, is formed at the moment a sperm fertilizes an egg. From 
this perspective, no use of PGD is truly “therapeutic,” because the testing does not treat 
the condition it detects. Rather, it diagnoses a “patient” with the sole purpose of telling 
parents which “patient” to discard. People who hold that the sanctity of human life 
extends to conception therefore tend to oppose PGD.15 
There are some people who do not hold a firm position on the moral status of the 
early human embryo but who nonetheless oppose PGD because they view it as unnatural 
or as violating the ways of nature. Still others argue that we should be wary of PGD 
(even if it is not inherently wrong or offensive) because it places society atop a slippery 
slope that will lead to genetic enhancement and human control of reproduction.16 
13 Catholic Health Association 16. 
14 Robertson (2003b) 213-16; Adams, 489-94; Botkin 17-28. 
15 It should be noted that these questions first emerged with the advent of IVF, though they have often been 
subsumed by the perceived good of enabling otherwise-infertile couples to bear children. In both IVF and 
PGD embryos will be discarded or frozen indefinitely if they are unused; in PGD, however, embryos are 
affirmatively rejected if they are deemed “unacceptable” because of the presence of a particular mutation or 
the absence of a particular desirable trait. 
16 The President’s Council on Bioethics raises this concern in its book Beyond Therapy, in which the 
Council addresses PGD as part of a larger project on biotechnology (see especially pages 40-57). 
7
The range of possible oversight proposals parallels the range of ethical opinions 
on PGD. For those who categorically oppose PGD, a permanent ban may be the only 
satisfying approach. A federal or state ban on PGD would have the benefit of creating a 
clear rule for prospective parents, health care providers and society. However, an 
outright ban would impose a single moral or ethical viewpoint, raise Constitutional 
concerns, and could be difficult to enact and enforce. 
For those who are concerned about the societal implications of PGD for certain 
uses, a temporary ban – to be revisited after society has more carefully considered the 
implications of this technology – might alleviate these concerns. Other possibilities 
include greater federal, state, and/or professional oversight of PGD, both to ensure its 
safety and effectiveness and to limit its uses to those deemed societally acceptable. 
Questions About Specific Uses of PGD 
PGD is now used primarily to increase the chance of having a child free of a 
specific serious disease. But there are no legal limits on the use of genetic tests in PGD, 
and the technology can be applied to choose a child with certain traits, such as sex and 
HLA type. Although some providers believe that certain uses of PGD are unethical and 
refuse to do PGD under certain circumstances (for example, to select an embryo of a 
particular sex for non-health-related reasons), others advertise these services and believe 
that parents should have the freedom to decide what uses of PGD are appropriate to their 
particular needs. 
Some observers argue that parents always have tried to give their children every 
possible advantage, from vitamin supplements to private swimming lessons. PGD, they 
argue, should therefore be viewed as a technology that simply extends the boundaries of 
8
this natural tendency. Another view suggests that PGD is appropriate when used to avoid 
serious genetic disease, but is inappropriate when used to detect mild conditions or 
benign traits. On this logic, the use of PGD to avoid suffering outweighs the risks 
involved and concerns over the status of embryos. But the balance tips when PGD is 
applied to avoid a mild or treatable condition, or used to select embryos for particular 
traits deemed “desirable” but whose absence does not cause suffering. 
The discussion of appropriate uses is made more complex because the lines 
between a serious health problem, a mild or treatable disease and a trait unrelated to 
disease are diffuse and often semi-permeable. Two related questions emerge: Where is 
the line to be drawn between acceptable and unacceptable uses of PGD? And who should 
draw this line? As but one example, many people in the medical community would say 
that a genetic predisposition to hearing loss represents a serious medical condition. Yet 
many in the Deaf community consider deafness to be a culture, not a disability.17 Should 
physicians, parents, or the government be the gatekeepers of “appropriate use” of 
technology? Whose values should have priority – the physician who sees deafness as a 
disability, the government who (in theory) sets the parameters for use of technology, or 
the parents who want to avoid, or in some case select for, a deaf child? It is clear that 
PGD raises the question of who decides what a “good life” is, and how far we should go 
in its pursuit. 
Some people question the ethics of using PGD to screen embryos for diseases that 
will not affect a person until adulthood (such as Huntington disease). They reason that 
children born today with those mutations would enjoy several decades of normal health 
before any symptoms begin, during which time science may find a treatment or cure. The 
9 
17 Middleton et al. (1998) 1175.
same question holds for genetic mutations associated with a heightened risk (as opposed 
to a certainty) for developing a particular disease. Should embryos be tested for a genetic 
mutation linked to an elevated risk (but not certainty) of developing hereditary breast 
cancer? Should an embryo with that mutation be summarily discarded? 
Safety, Accuracy, and Effectiveness 
For people who have decided to use PGD, the questions turn from broad ethical 
quandaries to more immediate issues such as safety and effectiveness. There are three 
chief concerns. Is this procedure safe for the mother and the resulting child? Does it 
accurately detect the genetic mutation of interest? And is it effective in producing a child 
free of that disease? Exploring these matters requires a consideration of the technical 
challenges and risks inherent in the genetic test itself and in the IVF procedure that it 
entails. 
The data, however, are far from clear. There are incomplete and conflicting data 
concerning the risks IVF may present to mothers who undergo the procedure and the 
children conceived via this method. This situation makes it difficult to determine the 
extent to which adding PGD to the IVF process may introduce additional risks. In all 
IVF processes there are risks associated with the hormones used to stimulate ovulation, 
and there is the risk the procedure could result in an ectopic pregnancy (in which the fetus 
develops in the fallopian tubes of the mother, and not in the uterus). Because more than 
one embryo is usually transferred to the uterus simultaneously, there is a heightened risk 
that the mother will carry multiple fetuses, which can make for a higher risk pregnancy 
for both the mother and fetuses. In addition, as with IVF generally, there is no certainty 
10
that a pregnancy will occur after the embryo is transferred. One known risk specific to 
PGD is that the biopsy to remove one or two cells from the embryo for genetic testing 
may harm or destroy the embryo. 
As for the accuracy and effectiveness of genetic testing, currently there is no 
government review of the analytic or clinical validity of a genetic test before it is 
marketed. There have been a small number of cases in which PGD failed to detect the 
genetic abnormality it was intended to reveal. The targeted condition was later detected 
either during pregnancy or following the birth of the child. Because an error can be 
made when testing the embryo, it is often recommended that the PGD result be confirmed 
by subsequent prenatal tests, such as amniocentesis or chorionic villus sampling. Some 
recent data suggest that PGD may increase the success rate of IVF if it is used to test 
embryos for chromosomal aneuploidy, but opinions vary on whether and under what 
circumstances this is useful. 
III. Current Oversight and Policy Approaches 
There is currently very little oversight of PGD. In general, decisions about PGD 
are left to IVF and PGD providers, who, together with patients, determine if PGD is 
appropriate in particular situations. Though most existing oversight is indirect and 
enforced to varying degrees, there are several oversight entities that could potentially 
play larger roles in the future. 
Federal Agency Oversight 
PGD sits at the intersection of two technologies with ambiguous and complex 
regulatory status: assisted reproduction (IVF) and genetic testing. The federal 
government does not typically directly regulate the practice of medicine, leaving such 
11
oversight to the states. Nevertheless, there are a variety of mechanisms that governmental 
agencies can use to regulate or influence the safety and availability of health care services 
and medical products. Three federal agencies within the U.S. Department of Health and 
Human Services oversee areas related to PGD: the Centers for Disease Control and 
Prevention (CDC), the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) and the Center for 
Medicare and Medicaid Services (CMS, formerly known as the Health Care Financing 
Administration). Federally-funded research is also subject to federal regulations for the 
protection of human subjects of research. 
The CDC oversees the 1992 Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act 
(FCSRA).18 This law requires that IVF clinics report pregnancy success rates annually to 
the federal government. The FCSRA requires clinics to report a variety of data, and 
noncompliance results in the clinic being listed on the CDC’s website (other than this 
minimal chastisement, there are no penalties for failure to comply with the law). 
However, the FCSRA does not require IVF clinics to report the health status of babies 
born as a result of the procedure or the use of diagnostic tests such as PGD. 
The FDA, under the Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetics (FD&C) Act,19 regulates 
drugs and devices, including those used in IVF treatments.20 Depending on the type of 
product, the FDA may require submission of data from clinical studies (premarket 
review) and agency approval before the product may be sold. FDA does not regulate 
most genetic tests, although it does regulate certain components that laboratories use to 
18 P.L. 102-493, 106 Stat. 3146 (1992) (codified at 42 U.S.C. §§ 263a-1 et seq.) 
19 Chapter 675, 52 Stat. 1040 (1938) (as amended) (codified at 21 U.S.C. § 301 et seq.). 
20 For example, medicines used to stimulate ovulation are classified as “drugs” subject to the FD&C Act 
and therefore must be approved by FDA before they are marketed in the United States. Similarly, culture 
media used to grow human embryos in the laboratory prior to implantation are classified as "devices" 
subject to premarket approval or clearance. 
12
make those tests.21 Thus, for genetic tests in general, and those used in PGD, there is no 
uniform system to assure accuracy or validity before the tests are marketed. 
FDA also regulates facilities handling human tissues intended for transplantation 
in order to ensure the safety of the tissue supply. Recently, FDA has decided to extend 
this limited regulatory oversight to facilities handling reproductive tissues under certain 
circumstances.22 In addition, FDA regulates the safety and effectiveness of certain human 
tissue-based therapies, such as tissues that are manipulated extensively or are used in a 
manner different from their original function in the body.23 These “biological products” 
may be subject to premarket review and approval under the Public Health Service Act24 
and FD&C Act. However, FDA has not determined that reproductive tissues are 
biological products when used for IVF or PGD procedures, and it has not required 
premarket review or approval for these tissues. Whether FDA has the legal authority 
under current statutes to categorize reproductive tissues in this way or require premarket 
review, and whether FDA would choose to do so if legal authority were not an issue, is 
an open question. 
The Center for Medicare and Medicaid Services implements the Clinical 
Laboratory Improvement Amendments of 1988 (CLIA).25 CLIA includes requirements 
addressing laboratory personnel qualifications, documentation and validation of tests and 
procedures, quality control standards and proficiency testing to monitor laboratory 
21 Medical Devices; Classification/Reclassification; Restricted Devices; Analyte Specific Reagents, 62 Fed. 
Reg. 62243 (Nov. 21, 1997) (final rule) (codified at 21 C.F.R. §§ 809.10(e), 809.30, 864.4010(a), and 
864.4020). 
22 Human Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-Based Products; Establishment Registration and Listing, 
66 Fed. Reg. 5447 (Jan. 19, 2001) (final rule) (codified at 21 C.F.R. § 1271.1 et seq.). 
23 Food and Drug Administration (1997) 12-17. 
24 Chapter 373 (1944) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 201 et seq.). The biologics provisions of the Act are codified 
at 42 U.S.C. § 262. 
25 P.L. 100-578, 102 Stat. 2903 (1988)(codified at 42 U.S.C. § 263a et seq.). 
13
performance. CMS has not taken a position regarding whether laboratories engaged in 
IVF meet the statutory definition of “clinical laboratories.” CMS has similarly not taken 
a position regarding whether laboratories that engage in the genetic analysis component 
of PGD are subject to regulation as clinical laboratories. If CLIA were applied and 
enforced with respect to genetic analysis of preimplantation embryos, laboratories 
engaged in this activity would be required to demonstrate proficiency under CLIA’s 
general proficiency testing requirements for high complexity laboratories. However, 
CMS has not yet established specific proficiency testing requirements for molecular 
genetic testing. Thus, the responsibility to ensure testing proficiency for genetic tests 
rests squarely with the individual laboratory. 
Finally, research carried out at institutions supported with federal funds is subject 
to federal requirements for protecting human research subjects.26 These requirements 
also are mandatory for research to support an application to FDA for product approval.27 
As it now stands, any research on PGD techniques involving human subjects would 
probably fall outside federal requirements for protecting human research subjects. First, 
there is a law against providing federal funding for research in which embryos are created 
or destroyed. Second, embryos are not generally thought to be “human subjects” within 
the meaning of federal regulations. Third, FDA does not currently require premarket 
approval for PGD. 
State Regulation 
No state has enacted laws that directly address PGD. Some states have passed 
laws related to assisted reproductive technology (ART), of which IVF is a major 
14 
26 45 C.F.R. Part 46. 
27 21 C.F.R. Parts 50,56.
component. These statutes are mainly concerned with defining parentage, ensuring that 
the transfer or donation of embryos is done with informed consent, or ensuring insurance 
coverage for fertility treatment. Some states prohibit the use of embryos for research 
purposes and one state, Louisiana, prohibits the intentional destruction of embryos 
created via IVF.28 For the most part, states have not assumed oversight responsibilities 
for fertility clinics. 
In terms of clinical laboratories, most states do not specifically oversee 
laboratories that conduct IVF or PGD as part of their administration of the CLIA 
program. However, New York is in the process of developing standards for laboratories 
that will include oversight of the genetic tests associated with PGD. 
Court Action and Legal Precedent 
Courts have addressed a variety of cases relating to assisted reproduction but only 
a few concerning PGD. In one case, the parents of a child born with cystic fibrosis (CF) 
following PGD sued those involved with the embryo screening for failing to detect the 
condition.29 The parents made the claim of “loss of consortium,” meaning the loss of the 
companionship they would otherwise have had with a healthy, non-CF-afflicted child. 
The court construed their claim as one for “wrongful birth” and rejected it, finding that 
the alleged harm was too speculative. The court similarly rejected the child’s claim of 
“wrongful life” (made by the parents on behalf of the child), which alleged that the 
defendants’ negligent failure to detect CF denied his parents an opportunity not to give 
birth to him. The court also found that the defective gene itself, not the physicians, had 
caused the defect. Most courts that have considered the issue have rejected wrongful life 
28 La. Rev. Stat. 9:129 (2004). 
29 Doolan v. IVF America, 12 Mass.L.Rep. 482 (MA Sup.Ct.2000). 
15
claims, such those arising from a flawed prenatal test. Part of the reason for the 
reluctance to accept wrongful life as a cause of action is the concern that to do so would 
give credence to the argument that there can be instances in which an impaired life is 
worse than no life at all. As more people take advantage of the new PGD technology, 
additional legal questions may be brought before the courts, leading to the development 
of a body of case law. Standards developed through case law frequently influence 
legislative action or become a de facto policy by themselves. 
Self-Regulation by Professional Organizations 
Medical and scientific professional organizations present another opportunity for 
oversight of PGD. These groups can educate their members about advances in the field, 
develop guidelines addressing appropriate conduct or practices and impose standards of 
adherence that are a prerequisite for membership. For the most part, however, such 
standards are voluntary: an individual can choose not to belong to the organization and 
therefore avoid the obligation to follow the standards. Professional organizations also 
typically do not have authority to sanction members for noncompliance. Unless the 
organization is specifically authorized by the federal government to act on the 
government’s behalf in administering and enforcing government standards, actions of the 
professional organization do not have the force of law.30 
For example, the American Society for Reproductive Medicine (ASRM) is a 
professional organization whose members are health professionals engaged in 
reproductive medicine. ASRM issues policy statements, guidelines and opinions 
regarding a variety of medical and ethical issues that reflect the thinking of the 
30 This issue becomes more acute when there is limited legislation, as is the current situation (as noted 
previously). 
16
organization’s various practice committees. In 2001 ASRM issued a practice committee 
opinion on PGD stating that it “appears to be a viable alternative to post-conception 
diagnosis and pregnancy termination.”31 It further states that while it is important for 
patients be aware of “potential diagnostic errors and the possibility of currently unknown 
long-term consequences on the fetus” from the biopsy procedure, “PGD should be 
regarded as an established technique with specific and expanding applications for 
standard clinical practice.” ASRM has also issued an ethics committee opinion 
cautioning against the use of PGD for sex selection in the absence of a serious sex-linked 
disease.32 
Two other professional organizations, the PGD International Society and the 
European Society for Human Reproduction and Embryology (ESHRE), are potentially in 
a position to play a larger oversight role for PGD. ESHRE recently issued “best practice” 
guidelines for PGD.33 These guidelines are an attempt to build consensus regarding PGD 
practice, while recognizing that different countries may adopt different practices because 
of country-specific requirements or circumstances. The ESHRE guidelines explicitly 
acknowledge that they are not intended as rules and not enforceable, but note that, in 
some countries, best practice guidelines may become “standard of care” and may be 
codified in law. 
Several professional organizations oversee clinical laboratories and could 
potentially extend their oversight to the laboratory component of PGD. For example, the 
College of American Pathologists has been empowered by the federal government to 
31 American Society for Reproductive Medicine 1-4. 
32 The Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. 
33 ESHRE PGD Consortium, Best Practice Guidelines for Clinical PGD/PGS testing. 
17
inspect laboratories seeking certification under the Clinical Laboratory Improvement 
Amendments, and the American College of Medical Genetics develops laboratory 
standards or clinical practice guidelines for genetic tests. However, neither group has 
developed guidelines and standards for PGD. 
IV. Possible Oversight Actions, Revisions and Considerations 
With this plethora of possible regulatory bodies in mind, we turn to the question 
of what entities might oversee PGD, and what objectives such entities might seek to 
accomplish. We consider oversight at the federal and state level, as well as oversight 
through the actions of professional organizations. In the absence of agreement, decisions 
about when and whether to use PGD will continue to be made largely by providers and 
patients. 
Policy Options 
There are a number of policy approaches that could be taken to restrict the use of 
PGD to those purposes deemed acceptable. Federal or state legislatures could enact a law 
clearly prohibiting PGD for uses it determines to be unacceptable (e.g. sex selection for 
non-health-related uses), an approach that has been used by a number of other 
countries.34 This approach would require that lawmakers list and define prohibited uses, 
but it also requires some degree of moral consensus among legislators and their 
constituencies. 
34 For example, under French law PGD is allowed only if the relevant hereditary predisposition has 
previously been demonstrated to exist in the parents or in one parent, and, only for the purpose of avoiding 
a severe genetic pathology. Loi no 94-654 du 29 juillet 1994 «relative au don et à l’utilisation des éléments 
et produits du corps humain, à l’assistance médicale à la procréation et au diagnostic prénatal». Similarly, 
in the U.K. access to PGD “is confined to individuals having a known family history of a serious genetic 
disorder.” Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, and Advisory Committee on Genetic Testing, 
Consultation document of PGD (2000). Finally, Canada recently enacted a law prohibiting PGD for sex 
selection in the absence of a sex-linked disease-causing mutation. See Bill C-6, “An Act Respecting 
Human Reproduction and Related Research” (Royal Assent received March 29, 2004). 
18
Alternatively, federal or state legislatures could pass legislation delegating to a 
new or existing federal agency the authority to oversee PGD, for which there is also 
precedent from other countries.35 For example, Congress could pass a law giving a new 
or existing federal agency the authority to oversee PGD. The agency would be 
empowered to deal with matters of safety, accuracy and effectiveness. Such an entity 
could be charged with:(1) Licensing and inspecting facilities that engage in PGD; (2) 
Approving new PGD tests and techniques; (3) Developing regulations concerning how 
PGD should be conducted, focusing on quality assurance and control; and (4) Collecting 
data on health outcomes of children born following PGD. 
One statute that could be broadened to explicitly cover PGD is CLIA, which 
currently provides limited reassurance to patients about the safety and accuracy of genetic 
tests in general and PGD in particular. CLIA could be applied and enforced with respect 
to genetic analysis of preimplantation embryos. Proficiency testing standards for this 
genetic analysis could be developed. Similarly, the government could authorize FDA to 
broaden its oversight to require that PGD providers demonstrate the safety and 
effectiveness of the genetic testing and embryo biopsy components of PGD. Those IVF-PGD 
clinics would be required to conduct controlled clinical trials and submit data from 
those trials to FDA. Finally, CDC’s reporting obligations for IVF clinics could be 
35 For example, in 1990 the U.K. enacted the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act, which established 
the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA). This Authority has the responsibility to 
license and monitor clinics that carry out in vitro fertilisation (IVF) and donor insemination, license and 
monitor research centres undertaking human embryo research, regulate the storage of gametes and 
embryos, produce a Code of Practice which gives guidelines to clinics about the proper conduct of licensed 
activities, maintain a formal register of information about donors, treatments and children born as a result 
of those treatments, provide relevant advice and information to patients, donors and clinics, review 
information about human embryos and any subsequent development of such embryos, and the provision of 
treatment services and activities governed by the HFE Act, and advise the Secretary of State on relevant 
developments in treatments and research. 
19
rigorously enforced and expanded to include health outcomes of children born as a result 
of PGD. 
At the state level, public health agencies could play a role in monitoring and 
improving the safety and accuracy of PGD. It is, however, difficult to create a uniform 
policy approach for state public health agencies because they take so many different 
statutory and bureaucratic forms. Nonetheless, each agency could take its basic charge to 
protect the public health and apply it to improving the safety and accuracy of PGD, as 
New York State, for example, is doing for laboratory standards (as mentioned 
previously). 
Professional organizations could provide significant oversight of PGD in ways 
that do not require the involvement of federal or state authorities. Non-governmental 
approaches to regulate PGD could involve the development of professional guidelines 
through a new or existing professional organization (such as the ASRM). While such 
guidelines are traditionally voluntary, they can nevertheless exert influence on medical 
practice – indeed, they are often viewed as evidence of the standard of care within a 
particular specialty. Since guidelines are more useful when some enforcement 
mechanism is contemplated, perhaps membership could be contingent upon adherence to 
the guidelines. In addition, the organization could encourage patients and those paying 
for PGD services (including employers and insurance companies) to use only the services 
of organization members, creating market forces in favor of compliance. The 
professional society could give this mechanism additional authority through a campaign 
educating the public and payors about the benefits of using providers who are members. 
Since a number of different types of professionals are involved in providing PGD 
20
services (physicians, geneticists, embryologists, technicians), collaboration among 
several existing professional organizations would be optimal. These complementary 
organizations could develop a comprehensive system to certify PGD providers in clinics 
and laboratories, and thereby ensure a minimum level of competency. Organizations that 
could collaborate to develop such a system include the American Board of Medical 
Genetics, the American Board of Obstetrics and Gynecology , the American Association 
of Bioanalysts, and the American College of Medical Genetics. 
A second non-governmental approach would be to employ education rather than 
regulation to discourage PGD for purposes deemed unacceptable. Patient groups, which 
typically are organized around particular diseases or conditions, could develop their own 
recommendations for appropriate use of PGD. In addition, patient groups could educate 
genetic counselors and other health care professionals by including the perspective of 
those living with the genetic disease or condition. Further, prospective parents could have 
the opportunity to meet with persons living with a particular condition or disability as 
well as their families. 
There are advantages and disadvantages to each of these approaches. 
Congressional intervention provides the strongest potential for national uniformity and 
adequate enforcement, but risks treading on the practice of medicine, a traditional 
province of state oversight. It can also be a blunt instrument for dealing with complex 
and rapidly changing technologies. Federal oversight can provide scientific expertise and 
greater assurance that questions concerning safety, accuracy, and effectiveness are being 
adequately addressed, but it also tends to limit the pace of scientific development, slows 
access to new technologies, and increases their cost. State oversight allows for more 
21
tailored approaches, but states may lack the resources for adequate oversight. Further, 
state-by-state approaches may lead to inconsistent practices, where availability of 
services is dependent on one’s geographic location. Finally, professional oversight 
allows those with the most direct expertise and knowledge about the practice to craft the 
approach, but such an approach may be hard to enforce within the profession. It is clear 
that deciding what limits are appropriate will be difficult for any entity. 
The Problem of Access to PGD Services 
PGD is expensive. It requires IVF, which costs upwards of $10,000-$12,000. The 
addition of PGD can add $2,500-$4,000, bringing the total cost to approximately 
$12,500-$16,000. Insurers may not cover PGD at all, or may pay only for the genetic 
testing, leaving prospective parents to pay for the IVF. Without coverage, PGD is 
available primarily to those who can pay significant out-of-pocket costs. Families who 
would face the greatest financial burden of caring for children born with conditions 
detectable via PGD may be the ones least able to afford it. Many insurers do not cover 
IVF for infertility treatment or offer only a limited benefit. Some fertility clinics offer 
ways to make IVF more affordable, and fifteen states have enacted some type of 
infertility insurance coverage law, but there are no federal laws in this area. 
Further, there has been no systematic investigation of insurance coverage 
practices for PGD. No federal or state law, either enacted or proposed, requires health 
insurers to cover PGD. To further complicate the matter, due to a quirk in Federal law, 
both Congress and state legislatures would have to act in order to require insurance 
coverage of all aspects of PGD. Anecdotal evidence suggests that when families are using 
PGD to avoid serious genetic disorders, insurance companies are more willing to 
22
consider the PGD medically necessary and cover the cost. At least one insurance 
company covers the genetic testing component of PGD for detection of inherited genetic 
disorders but not for aneuploidy. However, that company will not cover IVF if used only 
to perform PGD (i.e., if the IVF is not needed because of infertility)).36 
For insurers, the question of whether to cover any medical procedure or test 
primarily comes down to an analysis of the potential costs and benefits of coverage. A 
cost-benefit analysis of PGD would have to take into account the cost of the underlying 
IVF, the embryo biopsy and the genetic testing. It is not clear whether any health insurer 
in this country has undertaken a formal cost-benefit analysis of PGD for inherited genetic 
disorders. There could be pressure on insurers not to pay for PGD services given the 
moral issues involved. And from a health policy standpoint, there could be an argument 
made that there are many other health care needs that should be covered first. 
There are several alternatives to increase access to PGD without government 
mandates. Private employers could include PGD in their employee benefit plans. IVF 
clinics and PGD providers and laboratories could offer financial assistance directly to 
prospective parents seeking PGD. Due to the high cost associated with assisted 
reproductive technologies, some IVF programs offer IVF on a “shared-risk,” “warranty,” 
“refund” or “outcome” basis. These plans operate by refunding a portion of the fee paid 
for one or more IVF cycles in the event that they do not result in a pregnancy or live birth 
of a child. Typically, shared-risk patients pay a higher fee than other IVF patients and, in 
return, receive a refund of 70 to 100 percent of this fee if treatment fails. While this 
means that someone who does have a baby may pay more under the shared-risk plan than 
she would have under a traditional fee-for-service plan, this option helps ensure that non- 
36 Aetna, <http://www.aetna.com/cpb/data/CPBA0358.html>. 
23
pregnant couples will have the monetary resources to pursue other options for starting a 
family. 
Research and Data Collection 
While it is sometimes fashionable in science and policy to opine that “more 
research is needed,” in the case of PGD critical data are truly needed to develop effective, 
evidence-based policy. Research is warranted in two directions: the safety, accuracy, and 
effectiveness of PGD itself; and the informed public’s attitudes toward this technology. 
Many questions remain about the safety, accuracy and effectiveness of PGD. 
These include how often embryo biopsy damages or destroys embryos, how often PGD 
fails to detect a genetic mutation, and whether and for whom aneuploidy screening 
improves IVF results. In addition, more research is needed on the genetic tests used in 
PGD in order to improve test validity. There are incomplete and conflicting data on the 
long-term health effects of IVF for women and children, and no systematic studies on the 
health and developmental outcomes for children born following PGD. Thus, it is difficult 
to assess the baseline risk of IVF and any possible additional risk from the biopsy 
component of PGD. Longitudinal studies of women who have undergone IVF and 
children born following IVF and PGD would provide valuable information about the 
safety and risks of IVF and embryo biopsy. 
Funding for such research could come from a variety of sources, including 
industry, private foundations and the federal government. Federal funding would, 
however, be limited to research not involving the creation or destruction of human 
embryos unless Congress lifted the current funding ban. To obtain that information, the 
Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act (administered by CDC, together with 
24
the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technology or SART) could be expanded and 
enforced, requiring IVF clinics to report when PGD is used as part of an IVF procedure. 
Information required could include the purpose for which PGD was used (e.g., 
aneuploidy, cystic fibrosis), whether pregnancy occurred and the outcome of such 
pregnancy. Currently, clinics that fail to report information on IVF procedures face no 
penalties. Officials could consider monetary or other penalties for failure to report. In 
terms of insurance coverage, further research is needed to clarify current coverage 
policies for PGD, the extent to which price is a barrier to patient access to PGD and the 
costs and benefits for third-party payors (insurance companies and employers) of 
covering PGD. 
In addition, more empirical and theoretical research is needed on the potential 
societal impact of PGD. To address these questions, researchers could track changes in 
resources available for the disabled and in societal perceptions over time (the same could 
be applied to gender selection concerns). Longitudinal psychological studies of families 
who have used the procedure for a variety of reasons would provide data on the impact of 
PGD on families. And last but not least, surveys of national opinion and education about 
this topic will be essential in the formulation of any policy and oversight of PGD. 
V. PGD and Its Future Implications for Society 
Looking to the future, some observers view PGD, or any technology that allows 
parents the ability to choose the characteristics of their children, as having the potential to 
fundamentally alter the way we view human reproduction and our offspring as well. 
They fear that human reproduction could come to be seen as the province of technology, 
and children the end result of a series of meticulous, technology-driven choices. 
25
Some argue that widespread use of PGD eventually could change the current 
framework of social equality in many areas. The most dramatic possibilities involve 
babies who are born with genes selected to increase their chances of having good looks, 
musical talent, athletic ability, high SAT scores or whatever a parent who can afford PGD 
may desire. Meanwhile, such advantages would be unavailable to the less affluent. 
Such a scenario, while not possible now, is perhaps not totally implausible. 
Although PGD involves a diagnostic test and embryo selection, it is not genetic 
manipulation or “engineering” of the embryo itself. Over time the factors for which an 
embryo is tested could grow as science elucidates the links between individual genes and 
specific traits. Embryos might be selected or discarded based on genes correlated with 
intellectual, physical, or behavioral characteristics. 
Two sources of concern regarding PGD relate to its impact on the disabled and on 
women. First, some worry that, with the increasing number of genetic tests and ability 
for embryo selection, PGD could negatively impact the way society views the disabled. 
Some critics argue that some of the genetic conditions that PGD can now detect, such as 
those causing hereditary deafness, are merely human differences that do not limit an 
individual's ability to live a useful and satisfying life. To select against these human 
differences would be to create a problematic “norm” for human flourishing. Using 
technology to prevent such births, these groups argue, will lead to a society in which 
aesthetic concerns, convenience or mere prejudice supplant the inherent dignity due to 
every human being, regardless of how closely he or she conforms to some ideal of 
normality or perfection. They worry that societal norms will evolve such that parents who 
26
are at risk of having affected children will be pressured to use PGD, even if they find the 
procedure objectionable. 
Others have responded that for some time now parents have had the option of 
using amniocentesis and other types of prenatal diagnostic tests to probe for the same 
genetic abnormalities PGD can now detect. This information sometimes prompts parents 
to terminate a pregnancy to avoid having a child with a disability, yet many parents still 
choose to decline testing and to give birth to children with disabilities. Society continues 
to support families who make these choices. Nevertheless, anti-discrimination laws, 
public education, and social programs to aid the disabled would all help to limit negative 
perceptions of the disabled, and might also reduce the use of PGD by those who are 
concerned about the potential societal stigma of having a disabled child. 
Specific concerns also have been raised about the societal impact of using PGD 
for sex selection, based on parental preferences and not on sex-linked genetic disease. 
Historically, females in many societies have been subjected to discrimination based 
purely on gender, and some cultures still openly prefer male children to female. Given 
this situation, some observers see using PGD for sex selection as having the potential to 
devalue women. However, others argue that in many countries, including the U.S., one 
sex is not currently preferred over the other. When sex selection has occurred, these 
proponents claim, boys and girls have been equally selected. Providers have varied 
policies as well: Some refuse to conduct tests that would allow for gender selection 
unless it is related to a genetic condition; others actively advertise sex-selection services. 
Additional societal concerns have been raised about the potential for PGD to alter 
childhood and family dynamics, particularly when it comes to parental expectations and 
27
sibling relationships. For example, parents could end up being more critical and 
demanding of a child they view as having been carefully selected to possess certain 
attributes. Also, there could be tension among siblings when one is the product of PGD 
and the other is not, or when one has been selected via PGD to serve as an immunological 
match for another. In all cases of PGD, counseling guidelines could and should be 
developed that help prompt prospective parents to consider the breadth and implications 
of such matters. 
Conclusion 
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis raises many scientific questions and ethical 
quandaries. In this chapter we have reviewed the scientific, social, ethical and legal 
issues surrounding PGD and presented a range of policy alternatives that could be 
employed to address specific concerns. How then does one make policy in this complex 
and controversial area? A full consideration of all the policy alternatives and the benefits 
and burdens, and the range of persons or entities entrusted with making these decisions, 
must ensue. Only attentive and thorough debate over these topics will ensure that policy 
decisions in this arena are undertaken with a clear understanding of the potential impact 
of each alternative. An on-going effort to assess public attitudes about PGD and other 
reproductive genetic technologies will give stakeholders and policymakers a better feel 
for the diversity of opinion that surround these issues and, we hope, will enable 
individuals and society as a whole to use technology wisely and to flourish. 
28
29 
REFERENCES 
Books 
Kass, Leon. Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness. Regan 
Books, 2003. See also President’s Council on Bioethics, Beyond Therapy: 
Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness. Washington, D.C. (2003), available at 
http://www.bioethics.gov/reports/beyondtherapy/index.html 
Articles 
Adams Karen E. “Ethical Considerations of Applications of Preimplantation Genetic 
Diagnosis in the United States.” Medicine and Law. 22(3) (2003):489-94. 
American Society for Reproductive Medicine. “A Practice Committee Report: 
Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis." June 2001. 
Botkin, Jeffrey R. “Ethical Issues and Practical Problems in Preimplantation Genetic 
Diagnosis.” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics. 26(1) (1998): 17-28. 
Catholic Health Association of the United States, “Genetics, Science, and the Church: A 
Synopsis of Catholic Church Teachings on Science and Genetics.” 2003. 
<http://www.chausa.org/transform/genscience.pdf>. 
Delhanty, Joy A. “Preimplantation Diagnosis.” Prenatal Diagnosis. 14(13) (1994): 
1217-27. 
Ferraretti, A.P., Magli, M.C., Kopcow, L., Gianaroli, L. “Prognostic Role of 
Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for Aneuploidy in Assisted Reproductive Technology 
Outcome.” Human Reproduction. 19(3) (2004):694-9 
Grifo, J.A., Tang, Y.X., Munne, S., Alikani, M., Cohen, J., Rosenwaks, Z. Healthy 
Deliveries from Biopsied Human Embryos. Human Reproduction. 9(5) (1994):912-6 
Handyside, Alan H. and Delhanty, Joy D.A. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: 
Strategies and Surprises.” Trends in Genetics. 13(7) (1997):270-75. 
Handyside, A.H., Lesko, J.G., Tarin, J.J., Winston, R.M., Hughes, M.R.. “Birth of a 
Normal Girl After In Vitro Fertilization and Preimplantation Diagnostic Testing for 
Cystic Fibrosis.” New England Journal of Medicine. 327(13) (1992):905-9. 
Kuliev Anver and Verlinsky, Yuri. “Thirteen Years' Experience of Preimplantation 
Diagnosis: Report of the Fifth International Symposium on Preimplantation Genetics.” 
Reproductive BioMedicine Online. 8(2) (2004): 229-35.
Kuliev, Anver and Verlinsky, Yuri. “The Role of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis in 
Women of Advanced Reproductive Age.” Current Opinion in Obstetrics and 
Gynecology 15(3) (2003):233-8. 
Middleton, A., Hewison, J., Mueller, R.F. “Attitudes of Deaf Adults toward Genetic 
Testing for Hereditary Deafness.” American Journal of Human Genetics. 63 
(1998):1175-1180. 
Munne, Santiago. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis and Human Implantation--A 
Review.” Placenta. 24 (2003):S70-6 
Munne, Santiago, and Wells, Dagan. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Current 
Opinion in Obstetrics and Gynecology 14(3) (2002): 239-44. 
Rechitsky, S., Verlinsky, O., Chistokhina, A., Sharapova, T., Ozen, S., Masciangelo, C., 
Kuliev, A., Verlinsky, Y. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for Cancer 
Predisposition.” Reproductive Biomedicine Online. 5(2) (2002): 148-55. 
Robertson, John A. “Extending Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: The Ethical Debate. 
Ethical Issues in New Uses of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Human 
Reproduction. 18(3) (2003a):465-71. 
Robertson, John A. “Extending Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: Medical and Non- 
Medical Uses.” Journal of Medical Ethics. 29 (2003):213-216 
Sermon, K., De Rijcke, M., Lissens, W., De Vos, A., Platteau, P., Bonduelle, M., 
Devroey, P., Van Steirteghem, A., Liebaers, I. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for 
Huntington's Disease with Exclusion Testing.” European Journal of Human Genetics. 
10(10) (2002):591-8. 
The Ethics Committee of the American Society of Reproductive Medicine. “Sex 
Selection and Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Fertility and Sterility. 72(4) 
(1999):595-8. 
Verlinsky, Yuri and Kuliev, Anvir. “Current Status of Preimplantation Diagnosis for 
Single Gene Disorders.” Reproductive Biomedicine Online. 7(2): 2003:145-50. 
Verlinsky, Y., Rechitsky, S., Verlinsky, O., Masciangelo, C., Lederer, K., Kuliev, A. 
“Preimplantation Diagnosis for Early-Onset Alzheimer Disease Caused by 
V717L Mutation.” Journal of the American Medical Association. 287(8) (2002):1018-21 
Verlinsky, Y., Rechitsky, S., Schoolcraft, W., Strom, C., Kuliev, A. “Preimplantation 
Diagnosis for Fanconi Anemia Combined with HLA Matching.” Journal of the American 
Medical Association. 285(4) (2001):3130-3. 
30
Verlinsky, Yuri and Kuliev, Anver. “Preimplantation Polar Body Diagnosis.” 
Biochemical and Molecular Medicine. 58(1) (1996):13-17. 
Verlinsky, Y., Handyside, A., Simpson, J.L., Edwards, R., Kuliev, A., Muggleton-Harris, 
A., Readhead, C., Liebaers, I., Coonen, E., Plachot, M., et al. “Current Progress in 
Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics. 
10(5) (1993):353-60 
Verlinsky, Y., Rechitsky, S., Evsikov, S., White, M., Cieslak, J., Lifchez, A., Valle, J., 
Moise, J., Strom, C.M. “Preconception and Preimplantation Diagnosis for Cystic 
Fibrosis.” Prenatal Diagnosis. 12(2) (1992):103-10. 
Legal/Regulatory Materials 
Bill C-6, “An Act Respecting Human Reproduction and Related Research” (Royal 
Assent received March 29, 2004). 
Clinical Laboratory Improvement Amendments of 1988, P.L. 100-578, 102 Stat. 2903 
(1988) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 263a et seq.). 
Department of Health and Human Services, Regulations for the Protection of Human 
Subjects, 45 C.F.R. Part 46 (2004). 
Doolan v. IVF America, 12 Mass.L.Rep. 482 (MA Sup.Ct.2000). 
Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetics Act, Chapter 675, 52 Stat. 1040 (1938) (as amended), 
(codified at 21 U.S.C. § 301 et seq.). 
Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992, P.L. 102-493, 106 Stat. 3146 
(1992) (codified at 42 U.S.C. §§ 263a-1 et seq.). 
Food and Drug Administration. “Proposed Approach to Regulation of Cellular and 
Tissue-Based Products.” February 28, 1997. < 
http://www.fda.gov/cber/gdlns/celltissue.pdf>. 
Food and Drug Administration, Regulations for the Protection of Human Subjects, 21 
C.F.R. Part 50 and Part 56 (2004). 
Human Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-Based Products; Establishment 
Registration and Listing, 66 Fed. Reg. 5447 (Jan. 19, 2001) (final rule) (codified at 21 
C.F.R. § 1271.1 et seq.). 
Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act, 1990, ch. 37 (Eng.). 
Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, and Advisory Committee on Genetic 
Testing, Consultation document of PGD (2000). 
31
La. Rev. Stat. 9:129 (2004). 
Loi no 94-654 du 29 juillet 1994 «relative au don et à l’utilisation des éléments et 
produits du corps humain, à l’assistance médicale à la procréation et au diagnostic 
prénatal». 
Medical Devices; Classification/Reclassification; Restricted Devices; Analyte Specific 
Reagents, 62 Fed. Reg. 62243 (Nov. 21, 1997) (final rule) (codified at 21 C.F.R. §§ 
809.10(e), 809.30, 864.4010(a), and 864.4020). 
Public Health Service Act, Chapter 373 (1944) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 201 et seq.). 
Miscellaneous 
Aetna. “Clinical Policy Bulletin No. 0358, Prenatal Diagnosis of Genetic 
Diseases.”September 19, 2003. <http://www.aetna.com/cpb/data/CPBA0358.html>. 
GeneTests. 26 March 2004. < http://www.genetests.org/>. 
European Society for Human Reproduction and Embryology. ESHRE PGD Consortium, 
“Best Practice Guidelines for Clinical PGD/PGS testing.” 
<http://www.eshre.com/ecm/main.asp?lan=46&typ=122&fld=3603>. 
32

Más contenido relacionado

La actualidad más candente

Infertility Stem Cell 1
Infertility  Stem  Cell  1Infertility  Stem  Cell  1
Infertility Stem Cell 1
guest9dc181
 
The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...
The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...
The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...
鋒博 蔡
 
CJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copy
CJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copyCJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copy
CJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copy
Jane Langille
 
Ricardo International Innovations article
Ricardo International Innovations articleRicardo International Innovations article
Ricardo International Innovations article
Sharon Ricardo
 

La actualidad más candente (17)

Prevalence of Congenital Malformations in Newborns Delivered in a Rural Medic...
Prevalence of Congenital Malformations in Newborns Delivered in a Rural Medic...Prevalence of Congenital Malformations in Newborns Delivered in a Rural Medic...
Prevalence of Congenital Malformations in Newborns Delivered in a Rural Medic...
 
Genetic Engineered Babies
Genetic Engineered BabiesGenetic Engineered Babies
Genetic Engineered Babies
 
The Potential Impact of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis on Discrimination o...
The Potential Impact of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis on Discrimination o...The Potential Impact of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis on Discrimination o...
The Potential Impact of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis on Discrimination o...
 
Infertility Stem Cell 1
Infertility  Stem  Cell  1Infertility  Stem  Cell  1
Infertility Stem Cell 1
 
The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...
The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...
The use of time lapse photography in an in vitro fertilization programme for ...
 
Fulltext
FulltextFulltext
Fulltext
 
In Vitro Fertilisation
In Vitro FertilisationIn Vitro Fertilisation
In Vitro Fertilisation
 
INNOVATIONS IN ART
INNOVATIONS IN ARTINNOVATIONS IN ART
INNOVATIONS IN ART
 
CJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copy
CJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copyCJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copy
CJMLS_Summer2016_ENG_article only copy
 
Joseph Genetic project
Joseph Genetic projectJoseph Genetic project
Joseph Genetic project
 
IMSI
IMSIIMSI
IMSI
 
Time lapse observations
Time lapse observations Time lapse observations
Time lapse observations
 
Ricardo International Innovations article
Ricardo International Innovations articleRicardo International Innovations article
Ricardo International Innovations article
 
Current Regulatory Requirements in Developmental and Reproductive Toxicity As...
Current Regulatory Requirements in Developmental and Reproductive Toxicity As...Current Regulatory Requirements in Developmental and Reproductive Toxicity As...
Current Regulatory Requirements in Developmental and Reproductive Toxicity As...
 
Genetics research
Genetics researchGenetics research
Genetics research
 
Genetics research
Genetics researchGenetics research
Genetics research
 
Baby designing
Baby designingBaby designing
Baby designing
 

Destacado

The "Discovery" of Machu Picchu
The "Discovery" of Machu PicchuThe "Discovery" of Machu Picchu
The "Discovery" of Machu Picchu
smacedo372
 
Management Vs Leadership
Management Vs LeadershipManagement Vs Leadership
Management Vs Leadership
exportpat
 
Unidad 9
Unidad 9Unidad 9
Unidad 9
melmomi
 
PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...
PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...
PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...
Marcelo Weihmayr
 
John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09
John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09
John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09
John Landry
 
Tic educativo
Tic educativoTic educativo
Tic educativo
Negra91
 

Destacado (20)

NoSql Database
NoSql DatabaseNoSql Database
NoSql Database
 
Ejercicio 114
Ejercicio 114Ejercicio 114
Ejercicio 114
 
16.fusiones bonet
16.fusiones bonet16.fusiones bonet
16.fusiones bonet
 
Entornos
EntornosEntornos
Entornos
 
Ejercicio 1 2
Ejercicio 1 2Ejercicio 1 2
Ejercicio 1 2
 
Volume ii web
Volume ii webVolume ii web
Volume ii web
 
Proyecto sena.
Proyecto sena.Proyecto sena.
Proyecto sena.
 
The "Discovery" of Machu Picchu
The "Discovery" of Machu PicchuThe "Discovery" of Machu Picchu
The "Discovery" of Machu Picchu
 
Management Vs Leadership
Management Vs LeadershipManagement Vs Leadership
Management Vs Leadership
 
Manual de Usuario S I A G I E 2.0
Manual de Usuario S I A G I E  2.0Manual de Usuario S I A G I E  2.0
Manual de Usuario S I A G I E 2.0
 
guía de seguridad en el laboratorio 1
guía de seguridad en el laboratorio 1guía de seguridad en el laboratorio 1
guía de seguridad en el laboratorio 1
 
Deontologica del derecho
Deontologica del derechoDeontologica del derecho
Deontologica del derecho
 
Unidad 9
Unidad 9Unidad 9
Unidad 9
 
PETIC SEAD/SE 2.0
PETIC SEAD/SE 2.0PETIC SEAD/SE 2.0
PETIC SEAD/SE 2.0
 
October 25
October 25October 25
October 25
 
PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...
PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...
PARANÁ CENTRO ON-LINE: UM SISTEMA INFORMATIZADO NO AUXÍLIO DE GESTÃO DE NOTÍC...
 
John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09
John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09
John Landry at Mass TLC Feb09
 
Franklin Public Schools - PROgram
Franklin Public Schools - PROgramFranklin Public Schools - PROgram
Franklin Public Schools - PROgram
 
Tic educativo
Tic educativoTic educativo
Tic educativo
 
Chapter 1 CSC118
Chapter 1 CSC118 Chapter 1 CSC118
Chapter 1 CSC118
 

Similar a Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt2

Assisted Reproductive Technology
Assisted Reproductive TechnologyAssisted Reproductive Technology
Assisted Reproductive Technology
Reem Al-Hada
 
Pgd issue brief
Pgd issue briefPgd issue brief
Pgd issue brief
t7260678
 
Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439
Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439
Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439
鋒博 蔡
 
Genetics preimplantation
Genetics preimplantationGenetics preimplantation
Genetics preimplantation
t7260678
 
Post pn-445
Post pn-445Post pn-445
Post pn-445
t7260678
 
Post pn-445 (1)
Post pn-445 (1)Post pn-445 (1)
Post pn-445 (1)
t7260678
 
Post pn-445 (2)
Post pn-445 (2)Post pn-445 (2)
Post pn-445 (2)
t7260678
 
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     pptPreimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
鋒博 蔡
 
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     pptPreimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
鋒博 蔡
 
2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1 2001 by The MIT P.docx
2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1  2001 by The MIT P.docx2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1  2001 by The MIT P.docx
2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1 2001 by The MIT P.docx
vickeryr87
 
Current controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasive
Current controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasiveCurrent controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasive
Current controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasive
Luis Carlos Murillo Valencia
 
Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01
Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01
Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01
t7260678
 
Ques-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdf
Ques-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdfQues-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdf
Ques-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdf
apleathers
 

Similar a Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt2 (20)

Assisted Reproductive Technology
Assisted Reproductive TechnologyAssisted Reproductive Technology
Assisted Reproductive Technology
 
Pgd issue brief
Pgd issue briefPgd issue brief
Pgd issue brief
 
Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439
Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439
Preimplantation genetic-diagnosisdoc3439
 
designer babies
designer babiesdesigner babies
designer babies
 
Genetics preimplantation
Genetics preimplantationGenetics preimplantation
Genetics preimplantation
 
Global Medical Cures™ | Genetic Testing Handbook
Global Medical Cures™ | Genetic Testing HandbookGlobal Medical Cures™ | Genetic Testing Handbook
Global Medical Cures™ | Genetic Testing Handbook
 
Post pn-445
Post pn-445Post pn-445
Post pn-445
 
Post pn-445
Post pn-445Post pn-445
Post pn-445
 
Post pn-445
Post pn-445Post pn-445
Post pn-445
 
Post pn-445 (1)
Post pn-445 (1)Post pn-445 (1)
Post pn-445 (1)
 
Post pn-445 (2)
Post pn-445 (2)Post pn-445 (2)
Post pn-445 (2)
 
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     pptPreimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
 
35170
3517035170
35170
 
35170
3517035170
35170
 
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     pptPreimplantation genetic screening (pgs)  current     ppt
Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt
 
35170
3517035170
35170
 
2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1 2001 by The MIT P.docx
2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1  2001 by The MIT P.docx2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1  2001 by The MIT P.docx
2 ajob Winter 2001, Volume 1, Number 1 2001 by The MIT P.docx
 
Current controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasive
Current controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasiveCurrent controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasive
Current controversies in prenatal diagnosis 1 should noninvasive
 
Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01
Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01
Bettingergeneticspaperapril2009edited 090630144414-phpapp01
 
Ques-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdf
Ques-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdfQues-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdf
Ques-1 Prenatal diagnosis has both positive and potentially negativ.pdf
 

Más de 鋒博 蔡

1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main
1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main
1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main
鋒博 蔡
 
1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main
鋒博 蔡
 
Fetal fraction nipt pnd
Fetal fraction nipt pndFetal fraction nipt pnd
Fetal fraction nipt pnd
鋒博 蔡
 
Fetal quant cuhk bioinformatics
Fetal quant cuhk bioinformaticsFetal quant cuhk bioinformatics
Fetal quant cuhk bioinformatics
鋒博 蔡
 
Gb 2011-12-9-228
Gb 2011-12-9-228Gb 2011-12-9-228
Gb 2011-12-9-228
鋒博 蔡
 
Mat weight ga fetal frac nipt pnd
Mat weight ga fetal frac nipt pndMat weight ga fetal frac nipt pnd
Mat weight ga fetal frac nipt pnd
鋒博 蔡
 
Nihms379831 stephen quake
Nihms379831 stephen quakeNihms379831 stephen quake
Nihms379831 stephen quake
鋒博 蔡
 
Twin zygosity nipt
Twin zygosity niptTwin zygosity nipt
Twin zygosity nipt
鋒博 蔡
 
1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main
鋒博 蔡
 
1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main
1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main
1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main
鋒博 蔡
 
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4
鋒博 蔡
 
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)
鋒博 蔡
 
1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main
鋒博 蔡
 
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3
鋒博 蔡
 
1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main
鋒博 蔡
 

Más de 鋒博 蔡 (20)

Shapiro
ShapiroShapiro
Shapiro
 
Fresh or frozen embryos – which are better
Fresh or frozen embryos – which are betterFresh or frozen embryos – which are better
Fresh or frozen embryos – which are better
 
1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main
1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main
1 s2.0-s0929664613000958-main
 
1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006354-main
 
Fetal fraction nipt pnd
Fetal fraction nipt pndFetal fraction nipt pnd
Fetal fraction nipt pnd
 
Fetal quant cuhk bioinformatics
Fetal quant cuhk bioinformaticsFetal quant cuhk bioinformatics
Fetal quant cuhk bioinformatics
 
Gb 2011-12-9-228
Gb 2011-12-9-228Gb 2011-12-9-228
Gb 2011-12-9-228
 
Pone.0034901
Pone.0034901Pone.0034901
Pone.0034901
 
Mat weight ga fetal frac nipt pnd
Mat weight ga fetal frac nipt pndMat weight ga fetal frac nipt pnd
Mat weight ga fetal frac nipt pnd
 
Snp nipt pnd
Snp nipt pndSnp nipt pnd
Snp nipt pnd
 
Nihms379831 stephen quake
Nihms379831 stephen quakeNihms379831 stephen quake
Nihms379831 stephen quake
 
Twin zygosity nipt
Twin zygosity niptTwin zygosity nipt
Twin zygosity nipt
 
1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main
1 s2.0-s1472648313006366-main
 
1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main
1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main
1 s2.0-s0015028213027441-main
 
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4
 
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0355-4 (1)
 
Ecas1 1410
Ecas1 1410Ecas1 1410
Ecas1 1410
 
1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214020809-main
 
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3
Art%3 a10.1007%2fs10815 014-0230-3
 
1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main
1 s2.0-s0015028214018603-main
 

Preimplantation genetic screening (pgs) current ppt2

  • 1. GENETIC TESTING OF HUMAN EMBRYOS: ETHICAL CHALLENGES AND POLICY CHOICES Kathy Hudson, Ph.D., Susannah Baruch, J.D., Gail Javitt, J.D., M.P.H. The Genetics and Public Policy Center Berman Bioethics Institute Johns Hopkins University* Introduction Today, there are some one million people for whom the journey toward personhood began when a fertility specialist, peering through a microscope, carefully added sperm to egg in a glass petri dish – a process known as in vitro fertilization. There have also been dramatic advances in our scientific understanding of the human genome during this time period, which has led to the ability to test for genetic alterations associated with diseases and other inherited characteristics. Currently there are tests for over 1000 genetic diseases available or under development, and the number is steadily growing.1 The independent fields of IVF and genetic testing each present a host of issues that are technically, legally and ethically complicated. But now, the worlds of genetic testing and assisted reproduction have converged, most notably in preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD)—technology that allows parents to choose which embryos to implant in a woman’s womb based on genetic test results. The arrival of PGD has engendered a host of new scientific, social, ethical and political quandaries. Many people have begun to consider not just the implications of this new genetic diagnostic tool but whether core ethical and practical concerns surrounding IVF are really all that settled. * This chapter was written with the generous support of the Pew Charitable Trusts. The opinions expressed are those of the authors. 1 <http://www.genetests.org/>.
  • 2. Adding genetic testing to the IVF process means that medical providers and scientists can now be deeply involved in the molecular mechanics of the most profound and mysterious of human activities: creating life. This intercession of technology into human reproduction evokes a range of responses. For some, it is a deeply offensive act in which science literally subsumes the role of God. For others, it allows science to alleviate the anguish of genetic disease and infertility. These dueling opinions reveal both PGD’s potential benefits and its possible risks. As with much modern scientific research, there is a basic tension between concerns about the adverse consequences of unregulated research and fears that we may fail to develop important technologies if we apply too much restraint. Regardless of how one feels about it, PGD is a powerful tool, for it allows parents to identify and select the genetic characteristics of their children. As a society, we must ask whether and under what conditions PGD should be used. In this chapter, we provide an overview of PGD and an analysis of the ethical, legal and social issues that surround it. We then present an array of policy options that could be employed to govern PGD’s development and use. This essay surveys the situation of PGD in order to encourage discussion and facilitate policymaking; it does not endorse one course of action over another. The challenge with new biomedical technology is for the public and policymakers to keep informed despite the rapid pace of change. We believe that new genetic technologies that alter how we have babies, and indeed what babies we have, are so important that the public and its representatives must be engaged in the discussion and formulation of policies. 2
  • 3. I. What is Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis? PGD is a process in which embryos developed outside of the womb are tested for particular genetic characteristics, usually genetic abnormalities that cause serious disease, before being transferred to a woman’s uterus.2 It is always performed within the context of in vitro fertilization (IVF), for reasons that will be developed below. PGD derives from recent advances in both reproductive medicine and genetics. In 1978, scientists achieved the first viable human pregnancy from an egg fertilized outside the womb. Around this time, geneticists’ understanding of the basis of inherited disorders increased. Genetic researchers developed a number of tests to detect specific disorders. Eventually clinicians were able to apply these tests to a small amount of genetic material taken from an egg or embryo. The use of these tests in a human embryo (in vitro) or fetus (in utero) enabled prenatal detection of genetic abnormalities. PGD is a multi-step process involving egg extraction, in vitro fertilization, cell biopsy, genetic analysis and embryo transfer. Eggs removed from the mother (after she has been given drugs to stimulate egg production) are fertilized in the laboratory. Once the egg is fertilized in vitro, it develops into an embryo. Most commonly, genetic tests are performed on one or two cells taken from an embryo two to four days after fertilization.3 The sample may be analyzed two ways: by chromosomal analysis to assess the number or structure of chromosomes present in the cells; or by DNA analysis to detect specific gene mutations. Regardless of the methods, the results of preimplantation genetic diagnosis are used to inform the selection of embryos for transfer to a woman’s uterus. 2 Munne, Wells 239. 3 Handyside, Delhanty 271. Alternatively, genetic tests can be performed on polar body cells, which are cast off by the egg as it matures and is fertilized. Verlinsky, Kuliev (1996) 13. 3
  • 4. PGD enables two types of reproductive decisions. First, it permits doctors and prospective parents to select embryos for implantation that do not have a genetic abnormality associated with a specific disease, such as cystic fibrosis. Second, it enables doctors and parents to select embryos that possess a desired genetic trait, such as a tissue type that matches that of an ailing sibling. Since PGD was first made available to facilitate embryo selection, more than 1,000 babies have been born worldwide following a preimplantation genetic test.4 PGD was initially developed to detect serious single gene disorders5 and not to alleviate infertility. More recently, however, PGD has been used as an adjunct to standard IVF to detect abnormalities in chromosome number, called aneuploidy, that arise during egg or embryo development. Some IVF providers recommend PGD for patients over 35 or those with repeated IVF failure.6 Since over 1% of all U.S. newborns are IVF babies, and since more than half of IVF patients are of advanced reproductive age,7 aneuploidy screening likely accounts for the biggest growth area in the use of PGD. There is no required tracking of the number of PGD procedures performed or of the purpose for which they are performed, however, so a definitive breakdown of how many PGD procedures are performed to detect single gene mutations versus aneuploidy is not available. Virtually any of the hundreds of genetic tests now commercially available (and the many more in development) could be used in PGD. The more tests available, the more options there are for embryonic selection. Possible (but controversial) applications 4 Kuliev, Verlinsky (2004) 229. 5 The first PGD cases were performed to determine embryo sex, in order to avoid X-linked disease. Munne, Wells 239. Other early uses included detection of genes causing cystic fibrosis, Tay Sachs disease, and Lesch-Nyhan syndrome. Verlinsky et al. (1992) 103-110; Delhanty 1217-1227. 6 Ferraretti et al. 694-699; Munne (2003) S70-S76. 7 Kuliev, Verlinsky (2003) 233. 4
  • 5. of PGD include its use to select an embryo that is an immunological match for a sick sibling;8 to select the sex of an embryo in the absence of a sex-linked disease risk;9 to test embryos for gene mutations associated with diseases such as early-onset Alzheimer disease10 or Huntington disease11 that do not appear until later in life; or to test for mutations that indicate a heightened but uncertain risk of developing a particular disease such as cancer.12 There are inherent limits to the use of PGD to avoid disease or select for certain traits. First, not all diseases have a clearly diagnosable genetic component. Many diseases and traits are the result of a complex interaction between multiple genetic and environmental factors. Second, if PGD is used to detect genes that indicate a heightened risk for a particular disease, such as hereditary breast cancer, the fact that such a gene is detected in the embryo does not mean that a person who developed from that embryo would definitely develop the disease. Finally, it is important to remember that PGD cannot create new genetic characteristics that neither parent has. PGD can allow parents to select only among the genetic combinations present in the embryos they have produced. II. Ethical Issues and Policy Approaches PGD raises important concerns related to whether and when it should be used, its safety and effectiveness, costs and access, and what it would mean to live in a society where one’s genetics become more a matter of choice than chance. Current oversight of PGD’s safety, accuracy and effectiveness is extremely limited, as is the practice of IVF 5 8 Verlinsky et al. (2001) 3130-3133. 9 Robertson (2003a) 468-470 10 Verlinsky et al. (2002) 1018-1021. 11 Sermon et al. 591-598. 12 Rechitsky et al. 148-155.
  • 6. generally. Limits based on ethical, moral or societal concerns are almost nonexistent. The question is whether additional oversight is needed and if so, what issues it should address and how it should be structured. These are complicated dilemmas about which there has been little discussion or opportunity to form agreement. Since PGD requires IVF, it is mainly used today by a relatively small number of women who are willing to undergo IVF to avoid a known serious or fatal genetic condition or who are unable to get pregnant without IVF because of infertility problems. For people who already turn to IVF to treat infertility, PGD may become a more common tool to screen for genetic variants ranging from the serious to what some might consider trivial. For the moment, one would expect very few prospective parents who do not need IVF to get pregnant and who do not seek to avoid a serious or fatal known genetic condition to utilize PGD. Nonetheless, as the number of genetic tests that can be employed successfully in PGD increases and IVF techniques improve, it is possible that more prospective parents may consider using IVF and PGD to “choose” their embryo. Hence, with the advent of new reproductive biotechnologies – of which PGD is exemplary – there is likely to be growing public interest in developing policies that address ethical, technical and social concerns raised by the genetic testing of embryos. Below, we summarize the range of concerns about PGD and outline the possible policy alternatives that could guide the future development and use of this technology. 6
  • 7. Is PGD “ethical”? The ethical and moral ramifications of PGD have attracted significant attention. Some categorically oppose PGD’s use under any circumstances,13 while others have focused on the circumstances under which it may and may not be acceptable.14 As noted previously, PGD enables the selection of one or more embryos over others on the basis of genetic makeup. Embryos deemed genetically undesirable will likely be destroyed if they are not frozen indefinitely. Thus, PGD and the underlying IVF process involve the creation and, frequently, the destruction of human embryos. PGD is therefore objectionable to people who believe that a unique human being, deserving of the protections of a born person, is formed at the moment a sperm fertilizes an egg. From this perspective, no use of PGD is truly “therapeutic,” because the testing does not treat the condition it detects. Rather, it diagnoses a “patient” with the sole purpose of telling parents which “patient” to discard. People who hold that the sanctity of human life extends to conception therefore tend to oppose PGD.15 There are some people who do not hold a firm position on the moral status of the early human embryo but who nonetheless oppose PGD because they view it as unnatural or as violating the ways of nature. Still others argue that we should be wary of PGD (even if it is not inherently wrong or offensive) because it places society atop a slippery slope that will lead to genetic enhancement and human control of reproduction.16 13 Catholic Health Association 16. 14 Robertson (2003b) 213-16; Adams, 489-94; Botkin 17-28. 15 It should be noted that these questions first emerged with the advent of IVF, though they have often been subsumed by the perceived good of enabling otherwise-infertile couples to bear children. In both IVF and PGD embryos will be discarded or frozen indefinitely if they are unused; in PGD, however, embryos are affirmatively rejected if they are deemed “unacceptable” because of the presence of a particular mutation or the absence of a particular desirable trait. 16 The President’s Council on Bioethics raises this concern in its book Beyond Therapy, in which the Council addresses PGD as part of a larger project on biotechnology (see especially pages 40-57). 7
  • 8. The range of possible oversight proposals parallels the range of ethical opinions on PGD. For those who categorically oppose PGD, a permanent ban may be the only satisfying approach. A federal or state ban on PGD would have the benefit of creating a clear rule for prospective parents, health care providers and society. However, an outright ban would impose a single moral or ethical viewpoint, raise Constitutional concerns, and could be difficult to enact and enforce. For those who are concerned about the societal implications of PGD for certain uses, a temporary ban – to be revisited after society has more carefully considered the implications of this technology – might alleviate these concerns. Other possibilities include greater federal, state, and/or professional oversight of PGD, both to ensure its safety and effectiveness and to limit its uses to those deemed societally acceptable. Questions About Specific Uses of PGD PGD is now used primarily to increase the chance of having a child free of a specific serious disease. But there are no legal limits on the use of genetic tests in PGD, and the technology can be applied to choose a child with certain traits, such as sex and HLA type. Although some providers believe that certain uses of PGD are unethical and refuse to do PGD under certain circumstances (for example, to select an embryo of a particular sex for non-health-related reasons), others advertise these services and believe that parents should have the freedom to decide what uses of PGD are appropriate to their particular needs. Some observers argue that parents always have tried to give their children every possible advantage, from vitamin supplements to private swimming lessons. PGD, they argue, should therefore be viewed as a technology that simply extends the boundaries of 8
  • 9. this natural tendency. Another view suggests that PGD is appropriate when used to avoid serious genetic disease, but is inappropriate when used to detect mild conditions or benign traits. On this logic, the use of PGD to avoid suffering outweighs the risks involved and concerns over the status of embryos. But the balance tips when PGD is applied to avoid a mild or treatable condition, or used to select embryos for particular traits deemed “desirable” but whose absence does not cause suffering. The discussion of appropriate uses is made more complex because the lines between a serious health problem, a mild or treatable disease and a trait unrelated to disease are diffuse and often semi-permeable. Two related questions emerge: Where is the line to be drawn between acceptable and unacceptable uses of PGD? And who should draw this line? As but one example, many people in the medical community would say that a genetic predisposition to hearing loss represents a serious medical condition. Yet many in the Deaf community consider deafness to be a culture, not a disability.17 Should physicians, parents, or the government be the gatekeepers of “appropriate use” of technology? Whose values should have priority – the physician who sees deafness as a disability, the government who (in theory) sets the parameters for use of technology, or the parents who want to avoid, or in some case select for, a deaf child? It is clear that PGD raises the question of who decides what a “good life” is, and how far we should go in its pursuit. Some people question the ethics of using PGD to screen embryos for diseases that will not affect a person until adulthood (such as Huntington disease). They reason that children born today with those mutations would enjoy several decades of normal health before any symptoms begin, during which time science may find a treatment or cure. The 9 17 Middleton et al. (1998) 1175.
  • 10. same question holds for genetic mutations associated with a heightened risk (as opposed to a certainty) for developing a particular disease. Should embryos be tested for a genetic mutation linked to an elevated risk (but not certainty) of developing hereditary breast cancer? Should an embryo with that mutation be summarily discarded? Safety, Accuracy, and Effectiveness For people who have decided to use PGD, the questions turn from broad ethical quandaries to more immediate issues such as safety and effectiveness. There are three chief concerns. Is this procedure safe for the mother and the resulting child? Does it accurately detect the genetic mutation of interest? And is it effective in producing a child free of that disease? Exploring these matters requires a consideration of the technical challenges and risks inherent in the genetic test itself and in the IVF procedure that it entails. The data, however, are far from clear. There are incomplete and conflicting data concerning the risks IVF may present to mothers who undergo the procedure and the children conceived via this method. This situation makes it difficult to determine the extent to which adding PGD to the IVF process may introduce additional risks. In all IVF processes there are risks associated with the hormones used to stimulate ovulation, and there is the risk the procedure could result in an ectopic pregnancy (in which the fetus develops in the fallopian tubes of the mother, and not in the uterus). Because more than one embryo is usually transferred to the uterus simultaneously, there is a heightened risk that the mother will carry multiple fetuses, which can make for a higher risk pregnancy for both the mother and fetuses. In addition, as with IVF generally, there is no certainty 10
  • 11. that a pregnancy will occur after the embryo is transferred. One known risk specific to PGD is that the biopsy to remove one or two cells from the embryo for genetic testing may harm or destroy the embryo. As for the accuracy and effectiveness of genetic testing, currently there is no government review of the analytic or clinical validity of a genetic test before it is marketed. There have been a small number of cases in which PGD failed to detect the genetic abnormality it was intended to reveal. The targeted condition was later detected either during pregnancy or following the birth of the child. Because an error can be made when testing the embryo, it is often recommended that the PGD result be confirmed by subsequent prenatal tests, such as amniocentesis or chorionic villus sampling. Some recent data suggest that PGD may increase the success rate of IVF if it is used to test embryos for chromosomal aneuploidy, but opinions vary on whether and under what circumstances this is useful. III. Current Oversight and Policy Approaches There is currently very little oversight of PGD. In general, decisions about PGD are left to IVF and PGD providers, who, together with patients, determine if PGD is appropriate in particular situations. Though most existing oversight is indirect and enforced to varying degrees, there are several oversight entities that could potentially play larger roles in the future. Federal Agency Oversight PGD sits at the intersection of two technologies with ambiguous and complex regulatory status: assisted reproduction (IVF) and genetic testing. The federal government does not typically directly regulate the practice of medicine, leaving such 11
  • 12. oversight to the states. Nevertheless, there are a variety of mechanisms that governmental agencies can use to regulate or influence the safety and availability of health care services and medical products. Three federal agencies within the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services oversee areas related to PGD: the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC), the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) and the Center for Medicare and Medicaid Services (CMS, formerly known as the Health Care Financing Administration). Federally-funded research is also subject to federal regulations for the protection of human subjects of research. The CDC oversees the 1992 Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act (FCSRA).18 This law requires that IVF clinics report pregnancy success rates annually to the federal government. The FCSRA requires clinics to report a variety of data, and noncompliance results in the clinic being listed on the CDC’s website (other than this minimal chastisement, there are no penalties for failure to comply with the law). However, the FCSRA does not require IVF clinics to report the health status of babies born as a result of the procedure or the use of diagnostic tests such as PGD. The FDA, under the Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetics (FD&C) Act,19 regulates drugs and devices, including those used in IVF treatments.20 Depending on the type of product, the FDA may require submission of data from clinical studies (premarket review) and agency approval before the product may be sold. FDA does not regulate most genetic tests, although it does regulate certain components that laboratories use to 18 P.L. 102-493, 106 Stat. 3146 (1992) (codified at 42 U.S.C. §§ 263a-1 et seq.) 19 Chapter 675, 52 Stat. 1040 (1938) (as amended) (codified at 21 U.S.C. § 301 et seq.). 20 For example, medicines used to stimulate ovulation are classified as “drugs” subject to the FD&C Act and therefore must be approved by FDA before they are marketed in the United States. Similarly, culture media used to grow human embryos in the laboratory prior to implantation are classified as "devices" subject to premarket approval or clearance. 12
  • 13. make those tests.21 Thus, for genetic tests in general, and those used in PGD, there is no uniform system to assure accuracy or validity before the tests are marketed. FDA also regulates facilities handling human tissues intended for transplantation in order to ensure the safety of the tissue supply. Recently, FDA has decided to extend this limited regulatory oversight to facilities handling reproductive tissues under certain circumstances.22 In addition, FDA regulates the safety and effectiveness of certain human tissue-based therapies, such as tissues that are manipulated extensively or are used in a manner different from their original function in the body.23 These “biological products” may be subject to premarket review and approval under the Public Health Service Act24 and FD&C Act. However, FDA has not determined that reproductive tissues are biological products when used for IVF or PGD procedures, and it has not required premarket review or approval for these tissues. Whether FDA has the legal authority under current statutes to categorize reproductive tissues in this way or require premarket review, and whether FDA would choose to do so if legal authority were not an issue, is an open question. The Center for Medicare and Medicaid Services implements the Clinical Laboratory Improvement Amendments of 1988 (CLIA).25 CLIA includes requirements addressing laboratory personnel qualifications, documentation and validation of tests and procedures, quality control standards and proficiency testing to monitor laboratory 21 Medical Devices; Classification/Reclassification; Restricted Devices; Analyte Specific Reagents, 62 Fed. Reg. 62243 (Nov. 21, 1997) (final rule) (codified at 21 C.F.R. §§ 809.10(e), 809.30, 864.4010(a), and 864.4020). 22 Human Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-Based Products; Establishment Registration and Listing, 66 Fed. Reg. 5447 (Jan. 19, 2001) (final rule) (codified at 21 C.F.R. § 1271.1 et seq.). 23 Food and Drug Administration (1997) 12-17. 24 Chapter 373 (1944) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 201 et seq.). The biologics provisions of the Act are codified at 42 U.S.C. § 262. 25 P.L. 100-578, 102 Stat. 2903 (1988)(codified at 42 U.S.C. § 263a et seq.). 13
  • 14. performance. CMS has not taken a position regarding whether laboratories engaged in IVF meet the statutory definition of “clinical laboratories.” CMS has similarly not taken a position regarding whether laboratories that engage in the genetic analysis component of PGD are subject to regulation as clinical laboratories. If CLIA were applied and enforced with respect to genetic analysis of preimplantation embryos, laboratories engaged in this activity would be required to demonstrate proficiency under CLIA’s general proficiency testing requirements for high complexity laboratories. However, CMS has not yet established specific proficiency testing requirements for molecular genetic testing. Thus, the responsibility to ensure testing proficiency for genetic tests rests squarely with the individual laboratory. Finally, research carried out at institutions supported with federal funds is subject to federal requirements for protecting human research subjects.26 These requirements also are mandatory for research to support an application to FDA for product approval.27 As it now stands, any research on PGD techniques involving human subjects would probably fall outside federal requirements for protecting human research subjects. First, there is a law against providing federal funding for research in which embryos are created or destroyed. Second, embryos are not generally thought to be “human subjects” within the meaning of federal regulations. Third, FDA does not currently require premarket approval for PGD. State Regulation No state has enacted laws that directly address PGD. Some states have passed laws related to assisted reproductive technology (ART), of which IVF is a major 14 26 45 C.F.R. Part 46. 27 21 C.F.R. Parts 50,56.
  • 15. component. These statutes are mainly concerned with defining parentage, ensuring that the transfer or donation of embryos is done with informed consent, or ensuring insurance coverage for fertility treatment. Some states prohibit the use of embryos for research purposes and one state, Louisiana, prohibits the intentional destruction of embryos created via IVF.28 For the most part, states have not assumed oversight responsibilities for fertility clinics. In terms of clinical laboratories, most states do not specifically oversee laboratories that conduct IVF or PGD as part of their administration of the CLIA program. However, New York is in the process of developing standards for laboratories that will include oversight of the genetic tests associated with PGD. Court Action and Legal Precedent Courts have addressed a variety of cases relating to assisted reproduction but only a few concerning PGD. In one case, the parents of a child born with cystic fibrosis (CF) following PGD sued those involved with the embryo screening for failing to detect the condition.29 The parents made the claim of “loss of consortium,” meaning the loss of the companionship they would otherwise have had with a healthy, non-CF-afflicted child. The court construed their claim as one for “wrongful birth” and rejected it, finding that the alleged harm was too speculative. The court similarly rejected the child’s claim of “wrongful life” (made by the parents on behalf of the child), which alleged that the defendants’ negligent failure to detect CF denied his parents an opportunity not to give birth to him. The court also found that the defective gene itself, not the physicians, had caused the defect. Most courts that have considered the issue have rejected wrongful life 28 La. Rev. Stat. 9:129 (2004). 29 Doolan v. IVF America, 12 Mass.L.Rep. 482 (MA Sup.Ct.2000). 15
  • 16. claims, such those arising from a flawed prenatal test. Part of the reason for the reluctance to accept wrongful life as a cause of action is the concern that to do so would give credence to the argument that there can be instances in which an impaired life is worse than no life at all. As more people take advantage of the new PGD technology, additional legal questions may be brought before the courts, leading to the development of a body of case law. Standards developed through case law frequently influence legislative action or become a de facto policy by themselves. Self-Regulation by Professional Organizations Medical and scientific professional organizations present another opportunity for oversight of PGD. These groups can educate their members about advances in the field, develop guidelines addressing appropriate conduct or practices and impose standards of adherence that are a prerequisite for membership. For the most part, however, such standards are voluntary: an individual can choose not to belong to the organization and therefore avoid the obligation to follow the standards. Professional organizations also typically do not have authority to sanction members for noncompliance. Unless the organization is specifically authorized by the federal government to act on the government’s behalf in administering and enforcing government standards, actions of the professional organization do not have the force of law.30 For example, the American Society for Reproductive Medicine (ASRM) is a professional organization whose members are health professionals engaged in reproductive medicine. ASRM issues policy statements, guidelines and opinions regarding a variety of medical and ethical issues that reflect the thinking of the 30 This issue becomes more acute when there is limited legislation, as is the current situation (as noted previously). 16
  • 17. organization’s various practice committees. In 2001 ASRM issued a practice committee opinion on PGD stating that it “appears to be a viable alternative to post-conception diagnosis and pregnancy termination.”31 It further states that while it is important for patients be aware of “potential diagnostic errors and the possibility of currently unknown long-term consequences on the fetus” from the biopsy procedure, “PGD should be regarded as an established technique with specific and expanding applications for standard clinical practice.” ASRM has also issued an ethics committee opinion cautioning against the use of PGD for sex selection in the absence of a serious sex-linked disease.32 Two other professional organizations, the PGD International Society and the European Society for Human Reproduction and Embryology (ESHRE), are potentially in a position to play a larger oversight role for PGD. ESHRE recently issued “best practice” guidelines for PGD.33 These guidelines are an attempt to build consensus regarding PGD practice, while recognizing that different countries may adopt different practices because of country-specific requirements or circumstances. The ESHRE guidelines explicitly acknowledge that they are not intended as rules and not enforceable, but note that, in some countries, best practice guidelines may become “standard of care” and may be codified in law. Several professional organizations oversee clinical laboratories and could potentially extend their oversight to the laboratory component of PGD. For example, the College of American Pathologists has been empowered by the federal government to 31 American Society for Reproductive Medicine 1-4. 32 The Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. 33 ESHRE PGD Consortium, Best Practice Guidelines for Clinical PGD/PGS testing. 17
  • 18. inspect laboratories seeking certification under the Clinical Laboratory Improvement Amendments, and the American College of Medical Genetics develops laboratory standards or clinical practice guidelines for genetic tests. However, neither group has developed guidelines and standards for PGD. IV. Possible Oversight Actions, Revisions and Considerations With this plethora of possible regulatory bodies in mind, we turn to the question of what entities might oversee PGD, and what objectives such entities might seek to accomplish. We consider oversight at the federal and state level, as well as oversight through the actions of professional organizations. In the absence of agreement, decisions about when and whether to use PGD will continue to be made largely by providers and patients. Policy Options There are a number of policy approaches that could be taken to restrict the use of PGD to those purposes deemed acceptable. Federal or state legislatures could enact a law clearly prohibiting PGD for uses it determines to be unacceptable (e.g. sex selection for non-health-related uses), an approach that has been used by a number of other countries.34 This approach would require that lawmakers list and define prohibited uses, but it also requires some degree of moral consensus among legislators and their constituencies. 34 For example, under French law PGD is allowed only if the relevant hereditary predisposition has previously been demonstrated to exist in the parents or in one parent, and, only for the purpose of avoiding a severe genetic pathology. Loi no 94-654 du 29 juillet 1994 «relative au don et à l’utilisation des éléments et produits du corps humain, à l’assistance médicale à la procréation et au diagnostic prénatal». Similarly, in the U.K. access to PGD “is confined to individuals having a known family history of a serious genetic disorder.” Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, and Advisory Committee on Genetic Testing, Consultation document of PGD (2000). Finally, Canada recently enacted a law prohibiting PGD for sex selection in the absence of a sex-linked disease-causing mutation. See Bill C-6, “An Act Respecting Human Reproduction and Related Research” (Royal Assent received March 29, 2004). 18
  • 19. Alternatively, federal or state legislatures could pass legislation delegating to a new or existing federal agency the authority to oversee PGD, for which there is also precedent from other countries.35 For example, Congress could pass a law giving a new or existing federal agency the authority to oversee PGD. The agency would be empowered to deal with matters of safety, accuracy and effectiveness. Such an entity could be charged with:(1) Licensing and inspecting facilities that engage in PGD; (2) Approving new PGD tests and techniques; (3) Developing regulations concerning how PGD should be conducted, focusing on quality assurance and control; and (4) Collecting data on health outcomes of children born following PGD. One statute that could be broadened to explicitly cover PGD is CLIA, which currently provides limited reassurance to patients about the safety and accuracy of genetic tests in general and PGD in particular. CLIA could be applied and enforced with respect to genetic analysis of preimplantation embryos. Proficiency testing standards for this genetic analysis could be developed. Similarly, the government could authorize FDA to broaden its oversight to require that PGD providers demonstrate the safety and effectiveness of the genetic testing and embryo biopsy components of PGD. Those IVF-PGD clinics would be required to conduct controlled clinical trials and submit data from those trials to FDA. Finally, CDC’s reporting obligations for IVF clinics could be 35 For example, in 1990 the U.K. enacted the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act, which established the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA). This Authority has the responsibility to license and monitor clinics that carry out in vitro fertilisation (IVF) and donor insemination, license and monitor research centres undertaking human embryo research, regulate the storage of gametes and embryos, produce a Code of Practice which gives guidelines to clinics about the proper conduct of licensed activities, maintain a formal register of information about donors, treatments and children born as a result of those treatments, provide relevant advice and information to patients, donors and clinics, review information about human embryos and any subsequent development of such embryos, and the provision of treatment services and activities governed by the HFE Act, and advise the Secretary of State on relevant developments in treatments and research. 19
  • 20. rigorously enforced and expanded to include health outcomes of children born as a result of PGD. At the state level, public health agencies could play a role in monitoring and improving the safety and accuracy of PGD. It is, however, difficult to create a uniform policy approach for state public health agencies because they take so many different statutory and bureaucratic forms. Nonetheless, each agency could take its basic charge to protect the public health and apply it to improving the safety and accuracy of PGD, as New York State, for example, is doing for laboratory standards (as mentioned previously). Professional organizations could provide significant oversight of PGD in ways that do not require the involvement of federal or state authorities. Non-governmental approaches to regulate PGD could involve the development of professional guidelines through a new or existing professional organization (such as the ASRM). While such guidelines are traditionally voluntary, they can nevertheless exert influence on medical practice – indeed, they are often viewed as evidence of the standard of care within a particular specialty. Since guidelines are more useful when some enforcement mechanism is contemplated, perhaps membership could be contingent upon adherence to the guidelines. In addition, the organization could encourage patients and those paying for PGD services (including employers and insurance companies) to use only the services of organization members, creating market forces in favor of compliance. The professional society could give this mechanism additional authority through a campaign educating the public and payors about the benefits of using providers who are members. Since a number of different types of professionals are involved in providing PGD 20
  • 21. services (physicians, geneticists, embryologists, technicians), collaboration among several existing professional organizations would be optimal. These complementary organizations could develop a comprehensive system to certify PGD providers in clinics and laboratories, and thereby ensure a minimum level of competency. Organizations that could collaborate to develop such a system include the American Board of Medical Genetics, the American Board of Obstetrics and Gynecology , the American Association of Bioanalysts, and the American College of Medical Genetics. A second non-governmental approach would be to employ education rather than regulation to discourage PGD for purposes deemed unacceptable. Patient groups, which typically are organized around particular diseases or conditions, could develop their own recommendations for appropriate use of PGD. In addition, patient groups could educate genetic counselors and other health care professionals by including the perspective of those living with the genetic disease or condition. Further, prospective parents could have the opportunity to meet with persons living with a particular condition or disability as well as their families. There are advantages and disadvantages to each of these approaches. Congressional intervention provides the strongest potential for national uniformity and adequate enforcement, but risks treading on the practice of medicine, a traditional province of state oversight. It can also be a blunt instrument for dealing with complex and rapidly changing technologies. Federal oversight can provide scientific expertise and greater assurance that questions concerning safety, accuracy, and effectiveness are being adequately addressed, but it also tends to limit the pace of scientific development, slows access to new technologies, and increases their cost. State oversight allows for more 21
  • 22. tailored approaches, but states may lack the resources for adequate oversight. Further, state-by-state approaches may lead to inconsistent practices, where availability of services is dependent on one’s geographic location. Finally, professional oversight allows those with the most direct expertise and knowledge about the practice to craft the approach, but such an approach may be hard to enforce within the profession. It is clear that deciding what limits are appropriate will be difficult for any entity. The Problem of Access to PGD Services PGD is expensive. It requires IVF, which costs upwards of $10,000-$12,000. The addition of PGD can add $2,500-$4,000, bringing the total cost to approximately $12,500-$16,000. Insurers may not cover PGD at all, or may pay only for the genetic testing, leaving prospective parents to pay for the IVF. Without coverage, PGD is available primarily to those who can pay significant out-of-pocket costs. Families who would face the greatest financial burden of caring for children born with conditions detectable via PGD may be the ones least able to afford it. Many insurers do not cover IVF for infertility treatment or offer only a limited benefit. Some fertility clinics offer ways to make IVF more affordable, and fifteen states have enacted some type of infertility insurance coverage law, but there are no federal laws in this area. Further, there has been no systematic investigation of insurance coverage practices for PGD. No federal or state law, either enacted or proposed, requires health insurers to cover PGD. To further complicate the matter, due to a quirk in Federal law, both Congress and state legislatures would have to act in order to require insurance coverage of all aspects of PGD. Anecdotal evidence suggests that when families are using PGD to avoid serious genetic disorders, insurance companies are more willing to 22
  • 23. consider the PGD medically necessary and cover the cost. At least one insurance company covers the genetic testing component of PGD for detection of inherited genetic disorders but not for aneuploidy. However, that company will not cover IVF if used only to perform PGD (i.e., if the IVF is not needed because of infertility)).36 For insurers, the question of whether to cover any medical procedure or test primarily comes down to an analysis of the potential costs and benefits of coverage. A cost-benefit analysis of PGD would have to take into account the cost of the underlying IVF, the embryo biopsy and the genetic testing. It is not clear whether any health insurer in this country has undertaken a formal cost-benefit analysis of PGD for inherited genetic disorders. There could be pressure on insurers not to pay for PGD services given the moral issues involved. And from a health policy standpoint, there could be an argument made that there are many other health care needs that should be covered first. There are several alternatives to increase access to PGD without government mandates. Private employers could include PGD in their employee benefit plans. IVF clinics and PGD providers and laboratories could offer financial assistance directly to prospective parents seeking PGD. Due to the high cost associated with assisted reproductive technologies, some IVF programs offer IVF on a “shared-risk,” “warranty,” “refund” or “outcome” basis. These plans operate by refunding a portion of the fee paid for one or more IVF cycles in the event that they do not result in a pregnancy or live birth of a child. Typically, shared-risk patients pay a higher fee than other IVF patients and, in return, receive a refund of 70 to 100 percent of this fee if treatment fails. While this means that someone who does have a baby may pay more under the shared-risk plan than she would have under a traditional fee-for-service plan, this option helps ensure that non- 36 Aetna, <http://www.aetna.com/cpb/data/CPBA0358.html>. 23
  • 24. pregnant couples will have the monetary resources to pursue other options for starting a family. Research and Data Collection While it is sometimes fashionable in science and policy to opine that “more research is needed,” in the case of PGD critical data are truly needed to develop effective, evidence-based policy. Research is warranted in two directions: the safety, accuracy, and effectiveness of PGD itself; and the informed public’s attitudes toward this technology. Many questions remain about the safety, accuracy and effectiveness of PGD. These include how often embryo biopsy damages or destroys embryos, how often PGD fails to detect a genetic mutation, and whether and for whom aneuploidy screening improves IVF results. In addition, more research is needed on the genetic tests used in PGD in order to improve test validity. There are incomplete and conflicting data on the long-term health effects of IVF for women and children, and no systematic studies on the health and developmental outcomes for children born following PGD. Thus, it is difficult to assess the baseline risk of IVF and any possible additional risk from the biopsy component of PGD. Longitudinal studies of women who have undergone IVF and children born following IVF and PGD would provide valuable information about the safety and risks of IVF and embryo biopsy. Funding for such research could come from a variety of sources, including industry, private foundations and the federal government. Federal funding would, however, be limited to research not involving the creation or destruction of human embryos unless Congress lifted the current funding ban. To obtain that information, the Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act (administered by CDC, together with 24
  • 25. the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technology or SART) could be expanded and enforced, requiring IVF clinics to report when PGD is used as part of an IVF procedure. Information required could include the purpose for which PGD was used (e.g., aneuploidy, cystic fibrosis), whether pregnancy occurred and the outcome of such pregnancy. Currently, clinics that fail to report information on IVF procedures face no penalties. Officials could consider monetary or other penalties for failure to report. In terms of insurance coverage, further research is needed to clarify current coverage policies for PGD, the extent to which price is a barrier to patient access to PGD and the costs and benefits for third-party payors (insurance companies and employers) of covering PGD. In addition, more empirical and theoretical research is needed on the potential societal impact of PGD. To address these questions, researchers could track changes in resources available for the disabled and in societal perceptions over time (the same could be applied to gender selection concerns). Longitudinal psychological studies of families who have used the procedure for a variety of reasons would provide data on the impact of PGD on families. And last but not least, surveys of national opinion and education about this topic will be essential in the formulation of any policy and oversight of PGD. V. PGD and Its Future Implications for Society Looking to the future, some observers view PGD, or any technology that allows parents the ability to choose the characteristics of their children, as having the potential to fundamentally alter the way we view human reproduction and our offspring as well. They fear that human reproduction could come to be seen as the province of technology, and children the end result of a series of meticulous, technology-driven choices. 25
  • 26. Some argue that widespread use of PGD eventually could change the current framework of social equality in many areas. The most dramatic possibilities involve babies who are born with genes selected to increase their chances of having good looks, musical talent, athletic ability, high SAT scores or whatever a parent who can afford PGD may desire. Meanwhile, such advantages would be unavailable to the less affluent. Such a scenario, while not possible now, is perhaps not totally implausible. Although PGD involves a diagnostic test and embryo selection, it is not genetic manipulation or “engineering” of the embryo itself. Over time the factors for which an embryo is tested could grow as science elucidates the links between individual genes and specific traits. Embryos might be selected or discarded based on genes correlated with intellectual, physical, or behavioral characteristics. Two sources of concern regarding PGD relate to its impact on the disabled and on women. First, some worry that, with the increasing number of genetic tests and ability for embryo selection, PGD could negatively impact the way society views the disabled. Some critics argue that some of the genetic conditions that PGD can now detect, such as those causing hereditary deafness, are merely human differences that do not limit an individual's ability to live a useful and satisfying life. To select against these human differences would be to create a problematic “norm” for human flourishing. Using technology to prevent such births, these groups argue, will lead to a society in which aesthetic concerns, convenience or mere prejudice supplant the inherent dignity due to every human being, regardless of how closely he or she conforms to some ideal of normality or perfection. They worry that societal norms will evolve such that parents who 26
  • 27. are at risk of having affected children will be pressured to use PGD, even if they find the procedure objectionable. Others have responded that for some time now parents have had the option of using amniocentesis and other types of prenatal diagnostic tests to probe for the same genetic abnormalities PGD can now detect. This information sometimes prompts parents to terminate a pregnancy to avoid having a child with a disability, yet many parents still choose to decline testing and to give birth to children with disabilities. Society continues to support families who make these choices. Nevertheless, anti-discrimination laws, public education, and social programs to aid the disabled would all help to limit negative perceptions of the disabled, and might also reduce the use of PGD by those who are concerned about the potential societal stigma of having a disabled child. Specific concerns also have been raised about the societal impact of using PGD for sex selection, based on parental preferences and not on sex-linked genetic disease. Historically, females in many societies have been subjected to discrimination based purely on gender, and some cultures still openly prefer male children to female. Given this situation, some observers see using PGD for sex selection as having the potential to devalue women. However, others argue that in many countries, including the U.S., one sex is not currently preferred over the other. When sex selection has occurred, these proponents claim, boys and girls have been equally selected. Providers have varied policies as well: Some refuse to conduct tests that would allow for gender selection unless it is related to a genetic condition; others actively advertise sex-selection services. Additional societal concerns have been raised about the potential for PGD to alter childhood and family dynamics, particularly when it comes to parental expectations and 27
  • 28. sibling relationships. For example, parents could end up being more critical and demanding of a child they view as having been carefully selected to possess certain attributes. Also, there could be tension among siblings when one is the product of PGD and the other is not, or when one has been selected via PGD to serve as an immunological match for another. In all cases of PGD, counseling guidelines could and should be developed that help prompt prospective parents to consider the breadth and implications of such matters. Conclusion Preimplantation genetic diagnosis raises many scientific questions and ethical quandaries. In this chapter we have reviewed the scientific, social, ethical and legal issues surrounding PGD and presented a range of policy alternatives that could be employed to address specific concerns. How then does one make policy in this complex and controversial area? A full consideration of all the policy alternatives and the benefits and burdens, and the range of persons or entities entrusted with making these decisions, must ensue. Only attentive and thorough debate over these topics will ensure that policy decisions in this arena are undertaken with a clear understanding of the potential impact of each alternative. An on-going effort to assess public attitudes about PGD and other reproductive genetic technologies will give stakeholders and policymakers a better feel for the diversity of opinion that surround these issues and, we hope, will enable individuals and society as a whole to use technology wisely and to flourish. 28
  • 29. 29 REFERENCES Books Kass, Leon. Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness. Regan Books, 2003. See also President’s Council on Bioethics, Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness. Washington, D.C. (2003), available at http://www.bioethics.gov/reports/beyondtherapy/index.html Articles Adams Karen E. “Ethical Considerations of Applications of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis in the United States.” Medicine and Law. 22(3) (2003):489-94. American Society for Reproductive Medicine. “A Practice Committee Report: Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis." June 2001. Botkin, Jeffrey R. “Ethical Issues and Practical Problems in Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics. 26(1) (1998): 17-28. Catholic Health Association of the United States, “Genetics, Science, and the Church: A Synopsis of Catholic Church Teachings on Science and Genetics.” 2003. <http://www.chausa.org/transform/genscience.pdf>. Delhanty, Joy A. “Preimplantation Diagnosis.” Prenatal Diagnosis. 14(13) (1994): 1217-27. Ferraretti, A.P., Magli, M.C., Kopcow, L., Gianaroli, L. “Prognostic Role of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for Aneuploidy in Assisted Reproductive Technology Outcome.” Human Reproduction. 19(3) (2004):694-9 Grifo, J.A., Tang, Y.X., Munne, S., Alikani, M., Cohen, J., Rosenwaks, Z. Healthy Deliveries from Biopsied Human Embryos. Human Reproduction. 9(5) (1994):912-6 Handyside, Alan H. and Delhanty, Joy D.A. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: Strategies and Surprises.” Trends in Genetics. 13(7) (1997):270-75. Handyside, A.H., Lesko, J.G., Tarin, J.J., Winston, R.M., Hughes, M.R.. “Birth of a Normal Girl After In Vitro Fertilization and Preimplantation Diagnostic Testing for Cystic Fibrosis.” New England Journal of Medicine. 327(13) (1992):905-9. Kuliev Anver and Verlinsky, Yuri. “Thirteen Years' Experience of Preimplantation Diagnosis: Report of the Fifth International Symposium on Preimplantation Genetics.” Reproductive BioMedicine Online. 8(2) (2004): 229-35.
  • 30. Kuliev, Anver and Verlinsky, Yuri. “The Role of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis in Women of Advanced Reproductive Age.” Current Opinion in Obstetrics and Gynecology 15(3) (2003):233-8. Middleton, A., Hewison, J., Mueller, R.F. “Attitudes of Deaf Adults toward Genetic Testing for Hereditary Deafness.” American Journal of Human Genetics. 63 (1998):1175-1180. Munne, Santiago. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis and Human Implantation--A Review.” Placenta. 24 (2003):S70-6 Munne, Santiago, and Wells, Dagan. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Current Opinion in Obstetrics and Gynecology 14(3) (2002): 239-44. Rechitsky, S., Verlinsky, O., Chistokhina, A., Sharapova, T., Ozen, S., Masciangelo, C., Kuliev, A., Verlinsky, Y. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for Cancer Predisposition.” Reproductive Biomedicine Online. 5(2) (2002): 148-55. Robertson, John A. “Extending Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: The Ethical Debate. Ethical Issues in New Uses of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Human Reproduction. 18(3) (2003a):465-71. Robertson, John A. “Extending Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: Medical and Non- Medical Uses.” Journal of Medical Ethics. 29 (2003):213-216 Sermon, K., De Rijcke, M., Lissens, W., De Vos, A., Platteau, P., Bonduelle, M., Devroey, P., Van Steirteghem, A., Liebaers, I. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for Huntington's Disease with Exclusion Testing.” European Journal of Human Genetics. 10(10) (2002):591-8. The Ethics Committee of the American Society of Reproductive Medicine. “Sex Selection and Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Fertility and Sterility. 72(4) (1999):595-8. Verlinsky, Yuri and Kuliev, Anvir. “Current Status of Preimplantation Diagnosis for Single Gene Disorders.” Reproductive Biomedicine Online. 7(2): 2003:145-50. Verlinsky, Y., Rechitsky, S., Verlinsky, O., Masciangelo, C., Lederer, K., Kuliev, A. “Preimplantation Diagnosis for Early-Onset Alzheimer Disease Caused by V717L Mutation.” Journal of the American Medical Association. 287(8) (2002):1018-21 Verlinsky, Y., Rechitsky, S., Schoolcraft, W., Strom, C., Kuliev, A. “Preimplantation Diagnosis for Fanconi Anemia Combined with HLA Matching.” Journal of the American Medical Association. 285(4) (2001):3130-3. 30
  • 31. Verlinsky, Yuri and Kuliev, Anver. “Preimplantation Polar Body Diagnosis.” Biochemical and Molecular Medicine. 58(1) (1996):13-17. Verlinsky, Y., Handyside, A., Simpson, J.L., Edwards, R., Kuliev, A., Muggleton-Harris, A., Readhead, C., Liebaers, I., Coonen, E., Plachot, M., et al. “Current Progress in Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis.” Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics. 10(5) (1993):353-60 Verlinsky, Y., Rechitsky, S., Evsikov, S., White, M., Cieslak, J., Lifchez, A., Valle, J., Moise, J., Strom, C.M. “Preconception and Preimplantation Diagnosis for Cystic Fibrosis.” Prenatal Diagnosis. 12(2) (1992):103-10. Legal/Regulatory Materials Bill C-6, “An Act Respecting Human Reproduction and Related Research” (Royal Assent received March 29, 2004). Clinical Laboratory Improvement Amendments of 1988, P.L. 100-578, 102 Stat. 2903 (1988) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 263a et seq.). Department of Health and Human Services, Regulations for the Protection of Human Subjects, 45 C.F.R. Part 46 (2004). Doolan v. IVF America, 12 Mass.L.Rep. 482 (MA Sup.Ct.2000). Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetics Act, Chapter 675, 52 Stat. 1040 (1938) (as amended), (codified at 21 U.S.C. § 301 et seq.). Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992, P.L. 102-493, 106 Stat. 3146 (1992) (codified at 42 U.S.C. §§ 263a-1 et seq.). Food and Drug Administration. “Proposed Approach to Regulation of Cellular and Tissue-Based Products.” February 28, 1997. < http://www.fda.gov/cber/gdlns/celltissue.pdf>. Food and Drug Administration, Regulations for the Protection of Human Subjects, 21 C.F.R. Part 50 and Part 56 (2004). Human Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-Based Products; Establishment Registration and Listing, 66 Fed. Reg. 5447 (Jan. 19, 2001) (final rule) (codified at 21 C.F.R. § 1271.1 et seq.). Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act, 1990, ch. 37 (Eng.). Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority, and Advisory Committee on Genetic Testing, Consultation document of PGD (2000). 31
  • 32. La. Rev. Stat. 9:129 (2004). Loi no 94-654 du 29 juillet 1994 «relative au don et à l’utilisation des éléments et produits du corps humain, à l’assistance médicale à la procréation et au diagnostic prénatal». Medical Devices; Classification/Reclassification; Restricted Devices; Analyte Specific Reagents, 62 Fed. Reg. 62243 (Nov. 21, 1997) (final rule) (codified at 21 C.F.R. §§ 809.10(e), 809.30, 864.4010(a), and 864.4020). Public Health Service Act, Chapter 373 (1944) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 201 et seq.). Miscellaneous Aetna. “Clinical Policy Bulletin No. 0358, Prenatal Diagnosis of Genetic Diseases.”September 19, 2003. <http://www.aetna.com/cpb/data/CPBA0358.html>. GeneTests. 26 March 2004. < http://www.genetests.org/>. European Society for Human Reproduction and Embryology. ESHRE PGD Consortium, “Best Practice Guidelines for Clinical PGD/PGS testing.” <http://www.eshre.com/ecm/main.asp?lan=46&typ=122&fld=3603>. 32