SlideShare una empresa de Scribd logo
1 de 23
Descargar para leer sin conexión
Metacognition in ELEKTRA∗
                         Jean-Loup Castaigne
                 LabSET — IFRES — University of Liege
                                  January 24, 2007



1     Why certitude degrees in learning?
In an evaluation based only on identifying correct and incorrect answers there
is little information available for both teacher and learner other than right or
wrong. Adding certitude degree to evaluation brings a new dimension, allowing
more precise conclusions.
     For instance what conclusion should raise a teacher when 95 % of his students
succeed answering a question? What other conclusion if those 95 % successful
students only have a mean confidence of 10% in their correct answer? Maybe
the teacher will consider this task as not achieved by his students despite 95%
of correct answer.
     The way a test will be corrected will also be different if a majority of students
are failing a question with a mean certitude degree of 10% for that question or
with a mean certitude degree of 90%. In the first case doubt can be expressed
regarding the question itself. In the second case it appears students are confident
in their believe which is an incorrect information. This last situation may be
considered as dangerous as students will trust what they think they know.
     Learning does not move someone from total ignorance to perfect knowledge.
Often people will already have some knowledge or representation about what is
teached, even if these representation or knowledge might be erroneous. Evalua-
tion should not be limited to either knowledge or correct answer and ignorance
or incorrect answer. Information is what reduces doubt. “Partial information
exists. To detect it is necessary and feasible” (De Finetti, 1965)1 . certitude
degrees give a teacher a more detailed image of the knowledge of a student:
they reveal partial information.
   ∗ ELEKTRA : “Enhanced Learning Experience and Knowledge TRAnsfer” is an European

research project that aims at revolutionising technology-enhanced learning.
   1 De Finetti, B. (1965). Methods of discriminating levels of partial knowledge concerning

a test item. Bristish Journal of Math. & Statist. Psychol., 18, 87-123.




                                             1
2     What is metacognition?
2.1     Metacognition in general
Metacognition has been defined by Flavell (1976)2 : “Metacognition refers to
one’s knowledge concerning one’s own cognitive processes or anything related
to them, e.g. , the learning-relevant properties of information or data” . Many
interpretations were made from the original definition of metacognition but
metacognition is agreed to involve both
    • knowledge about one’s own knowledge and
    • knowledge about one’s own cognitive processes.
Metacognition has to do with the active monitoring and regulation of cognitive
processes. Metacognition is also relevant to work on cognitive styles and learning
strategies in so far as the individual has some awareness of their thinking or
learning processes.
    Within metacognition “knowledge about memory” is defined as metamem-
ory (Flavell & Wellman, 1977)3 . Metamemory itself is declined into declar-
ative metamemory (e.g. knowledge about strategy variables) and procedural
metamemory with its two components: the monitoring component and the con-
trol and self-regulated component.

      Metacognition
         • Metamemory
              1. Declarative metamemory
              2. Procedural metamemory
                  (a) monitoring component
                  (b) control and self-regulated component

   Schraw and Dennison (1994)4 separate the knowledge and the regulation of
cognition, each one being defined into different parts.

    1. The knowledge of cognition is composed of:
        (a) Declarative knowledge: knowledge about one’s skills, intellectual re-
            sources, and abilities as a learner.
       (b) Procedural knowledge: knowledge about how to implement learning
           procedures (e.g., strategies).
        (c) Conditional knowledge: knowledge about when and why to use learn-
            ing procedures.
    2. The regulation of cognition refers to:
   2 Flavell, J.H. (1976). Metacognitive aspects of problem solving. In Resnick (Ed.), The

nature of intelligence. (pp. 231-235). New Jersey : Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
   3 Flavell, J.H., & Wellman, H. (1977). Metamemory. In R. V. Kail Jr. & J. Hagen (Eds.),

Perspectives on the development of memory and cognition (pp. 3–33). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
   4 Schraw, Gregory, and Rayne Sperling Dennison, 1994. Assessing Metacognitive Aware-

ness? In Contemporary Educational Psychology 19, 460-475.



                                            2
(a) Planning: planning, goal setting, and allocating resources prior to
            learning.
        (b) Information management: skills and strategy sequences used on-line
            to process information more efficiently (e.g., organizing, elaborating,
            summarizing, selective focusing).
        (c) Monitoring: assessment of one’s learning or strategy use.
        (d) Debugging: strategies used to correct comprehension and perfor-
            mance errors.
        (e) Evaluation: analysis of performance and strategy effectiveness after
            a learning episode.
The EARLI 5 metacognition special interest group often refers to the main
components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive control that was
defined from the works of Nelson (1996) 6 and Nelson & Narens (1994) 7 – see
figure 1.




 Figure 1: Main components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive control defined
by Nelson (1996) and Nelson & Narens (1994)



    Leclercq & Poumay (2004) 8 propose an “operational definition” of metacog-
nition: “Observable (or not) judgments, analysis and /or regulations effectuated
   5 EARLI:  European Association for Research on Learning and Instruction
   6 Nelson, T. O. (1996). Gamma is a measure of the accuracy of predicting performance
on one item relative to another item, not of the absolute performance on an individual item.
Applied Cognitive Psychology, 10, 257–260.
   7 Nelson, T. O., & Narens, L. (1994). Why investigate metacognition? In J. Metcalfe &

A. Shimamura (Eds.), Metacognition: Knowing about knowing (pp. 1–25). Cambridge, MA:
Bradford Books.
   8 personal translation of “les jugements, analyses et/ou r´gulations observables effectu´s par
                                                             e                            e
l’apprenant sur ses propres performances (processus ou produits d’apprentissages), ceci dans
des situations de PRE, PER ou POST performance” from Leclercq, D. & Poumay, M. (2004).
Une d´finition op´rationnelle de la m´tacognition et ses mises en oeuvre. 21e Conf´rence
       e           e                    e                                                 e
internationale de l’AIPU, Morocco: Marrakech.


                                               3
by a learner on his/her own performances (learning processes or products), in
situations of pre, per or post performance (mainly testing or learning).”

2.2     Certitude degrees and metacognition
Ebel (1965)9 defined confidence weighting as “a special mode of responding to
objective test items, and special mode of scoring those responses. In general
terms, the examinee is asked to indicate not only what he believes to be the
correct answer to a question, but also how certain he is of the correctness of his
answer”. certitude degrees are confidence weighting. In Nelson & Narens’s main
components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive control certitude
degrees with testing take place in the monitoring side, retrieval of knowledge
category, in the Confidence in retrieved answers box. In Leclercq & Poumay’s
operational definition certitude degree with testing will be observable judgments
effectuated by a learner on his/her own performances (products), in situations
of per performance (testing).

2.3     Metacognition in the demonstrator
One can ask if metacognition is usable as such for teenagers 14 years old. In
brief, publications that were founded consider tested components of metacogni-
tive monitoring and control not significantly different between adults and as low
as 10 years old children. Below the age of 10, components significance evolves
with age. Flavell, Friedrichs & Hoyt (1970)10 have showed significant correla-
tion between predicted and actual memory span in children from the 4th grade
and no significant correlation was founded below that age, including at nursery
and kindergarden. Young children show unrealistic performances prediction.
Schneider (2006)11 offers three theoretical reasons: 1) insufficient metacognitive
knowledge (young children not monitoring their memory activities or lacking in
understanding about the interplay among relevant factors), 2) predominance of
wishful thinking over expectations thus predictions reflecting their desires) and
3) belief in the power of effort. Duell (1986)12 confirm that as children get older
they demonstrate more awareness of their thinking processes.
    In the Elektra demonstrator the use of certitude degrees so far is neither
relevant of a “judgment of learning” nor a confidence in retrieved answer. Judg-
ments of learning (jols), are defined as judgments that “occur during or after
acquisition and are predictions about future test performance on recently stud-
ied items” (Nelson & Narens, 1994).
   9 Ebel, R. (1965). Confidence weighting and test reliability. Journal of Educational Mea-

surement, pages 49–57.
  10 Flavell, J. H., Friedrichs, A., & Hoyt, J. (1970). Developmental changes in memorization

processes. Cognitive Psychology, 1, 324–340.
  11 Schneider 2006, The development of metacognition in childhood and adolescence, keyn-

note of the 2nd international biennial conference of the Metacognition Special Interest Group
(SIG 16) of the European Association of Research in Learning and Instruction (EARLI), July
2006, Cambridge
  12 Duell, O.K. (1986). Metacognitive skills. In G. Phye & T. Andre (Eds.), Cognitive

Classroom Learning. Orlando, FL: Academic Press.




                                             4
2.3.1    What is a JOL?
Imagine a learner studying pairs of linked words13 such as game–elektra.
The learner receives the instructions that each pair should be learned so that
subsequently when prompted with the cue (e.g., “game–?”), the learner would
recall the target (e.g., “elektra”). An interval of time elapses between the
termination of studying a given item and the onset of the jol for that item.
This interval could be

   • extremely brief (e.g., as in an immediate jol that occurs as close in time
     as possible to the offset of the studied item) or
   • could be delayed for a more lengthy amount of time (as in a delayed jol)
     filled with other activity and/or other to-be-learned items.

Then the first jol occurs, prompted by a cue that usually consisted of only
the cue from the studied item (e.g., “game–?”). The learner generates a jol
by choosing the predicted likelihood (e.g., on a Likert-type rating scale or on a
scale ranging from 0% to 100% in steps of 20%) of remembering the item on an
eventual criterion test that might occur later (e.g., 10–20 minutes later). Other
pairs of words are studied, and jols are made for each of them, until every
pair had been studied and had received a jol. Finally, following an interval
of perhaps 10–20 minutes (filled with other items) from the time of studying a
given item, the person received the eventual memory test on that item. The
memory test is self-paced, usually asking the person to recall the target when
prompted by the cue (e.g., when prompted by “game–?”, the person attempt
to recall “elektra”).
    With this example we demonstrate that what is asked in the demonstrator
is neither true jols nor confidence in retrieved answers.

2.3.2    JOL or confidence in retrieved answer
We suggest that metacognition in elektra is in a first time limited to the use
of certitude degrees with the objective of improving the learner metacognitive
self assessment. Kruger & Dunning (1999) 14 showed that “learners whose skills
or knowledge bases are weak in a particular area tend to overestimate their
ability in that area”. In other words, they don’t know enough to recognize
that they lack sufficient knowledge for accurate self-assessment. In contrast,
learners whose knowledge or skills are strong may underestimate their ability.
These high-ability learners don’t recognize the extent of their knowledge or skills.
Kruger and Dunning’s research also shows that “it is possible to teach learners at
all ability levels to assess their own performance more accurately”. It is in that
perspective that certitude degrees will be implemented in elektra. With the
use of certitude degree in elektra we can at least give the learner/player some
feedback about their cognitive strategies with the confidence in their retrieved
answers.
  13 adapted form Nelson, Narens & Dunlosky (2004). A Revised Methodology for Research on

Metamemory: Pre-judgment Recall And Monitoring (PRAM). Psychological Methods, Vol.
9, No. 1, 53–69.
  14 Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How difficulties in

recognizing one’s own incompetence lead to inflated self-assessment. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 77, 1121-1134.



                                            5
Consolidated Research Report M1-6 specifies that metacognition within elek-
tra should:

    • support and facilitate the development of metacognitive abilities and strate-
      gies and
    • support the assessment of knowledge.
We recommend to be very cautious in identifying what is assessment of knowl-
edge and what is support to metacognition. Feedbacks should always be very
clear in regard to what they refer to, either cognition–knowledge or metacognition–
knowledge about knowledge. With elektra we can provide teachers a tool to
begin a reflection with their students about metacognition. The distinction
between cognitive and metacognitive strategies is important, partly because it
gives some indication of which strategies are the most crucial in determining
the effectiveness of learning. It seems that “metacognitive strategies, that allow
students to plan, control, and evaluate their learning, have the most central role
to play in this respect, rather than those that merely maximize interaction and
input . . . Thus the ability to choose and evaluate one’s strategies is of central
importance” (Graham, 1997) 15 . Learners who are metacognitively aware know
what to do when they don’t know what to do; that is, they have strategies for
finding out or figuring out what they need to do. “The use of metacognitive
strategies ignites one’s thinking and can lead to more profound learning and im-
proved performance, especially among learners who are struggling” (Anderson,
2002) 16 .


3     Metacognition in games
Prakash (1999) 17 reports that he heard on the radio a sixth grader explaining
what she was learning from playing the Stock Market Game. This game was an
activity designed to help children become familiar with how the stock market
functions. She said, “This game makes me think how to think”. What this
statement reveals is that this young learner was beginning to understand the
real key to learning; she was engaged in metacognition using a game.
    Salda˜a (2004) 18 reports using a Master Mind c modified (order was not
         n
important) to assess metacognitive processes use to solve the enigma. The
solution could be found independently or with three levels of assistance

    1. focusing on the metacognitive processes present in the task such as
         • planning aims / strategies,
         • supervision and control of aims / strategies,
         • revision of aims / strategies,
  15 Graham, S. (1997). Effective language learning. Clevedon, England: Multilingual Mat-

ters.
  16 Neil J. Anderson, The Role of Metacognition in Second Language Teaching and Learning,

Brigham Young University
  17 Prakash, S. (Reporter). (1999, March 19). Market games [Radio series episode]. All

things considered. Washington: National Public Radio.
  18 Salda˜ a, D. (2004) Dynamic Master Mind: interactive use of a game for testing metacog-
           n
nition. School Psychology International, Vol 25(4): 422-438.



                                             6
• meta knowledge of possibilities and limitations
         • meta knowledge of tasks / strategies;

    2. scaffolding each and every one of the selfregulatory steps included in the
       task;
    3. modelling of the task solution process
On top of working metacognitive process this experiment also showed diversifi-
cation in methods for adaptivity.
    Additional literature research is still under process. Please keep this docu-
ment for private use within elektra.


4     About the demonstrator, 2006 version
These comments only cover some metacognitive aspects of the demonstrator.

4.1     A surprise
When Galileo says that the most important thing is to first define what you
want to do, he is asking George to identify the objective. This is a metacognitive
activity and looks like what is described by Salda˜a (2004) as “planning aims”
                                                    n
in his Master Mind c experiment. It is a pleasant surprise to see that the
formulation of that question turned it into a metacognitive activity.




                Figure 2: Cut scene from the elektra demonstrator, 2006




                                          7
4.2     General comments
   1. The asked question should not have been ‘Are you sure?” but something
      like “With what you know and what you have learned, how confident are
      you that you will succeed opening the door in this try?” Asked the way it
      was, it was confusing as we mentioned as soon as we had the opportunity
      to look at the demonstrator. But it was too late to change as the validation
      in ORT Marseilles had already begun. UG document about metacognition
      19
         mentioned that “As shown for example in the first validation results,
      the current formulation of the confidence rating is not understood by most
      individuals of the target group”. We argue that
        (a) the formulation of the question, especially that lack of “sure of what?”
        (b) the fact that the question was neither a jol nor a confidence in
            retrieved answer,
        (c) the lack of explanations related to the metacognitive aims and the
            absence of tutorial explaining how to use certitude degree,
        (d) the lack of training of students in general regarding expression of
            their confidence,
        (e) the use of verbal expression e.g., “sure” is confusing by itself and
            should not be used when retrieving certitude (see Shuford, Albert &
            Massengill (1966)20 recommendations for the use of subjective prob-
            abilities instead of verbal expressions)
       are all explanations of the confusion. As mentioned here above, in collect-
       ing jol Nelson & Narens themselves are using a probabilistic scale from
       0% to 100% by steps of 20%. In the validation report21 ORT mentions
       that: “It seemed that most pupils didn’t really understand the meaning
       behind the confidence degree, or the questions that was asked.” We to-
       tally agree with their recommendation that suggest: “It seems that the
       question related to the confidence degree wasn’t very clear, it is therefore
       recommended to formulate the question in a clearer way (adapted to 13-14
       years old pupils)”. To avoid confusion we propose section 7 some sugges-
       tion about what to explain in the tutorial. Shuford (1966) and Leclercq
       (198322 , 198623 , 199324 ) defined 4 rules when using certitude degrees:
        (a) the use of probabilistic value instead of words;
        (b) if points are awarded tariff should respect the decision theory;
        (c) feedbacks concerning the good or not good use of certitude degree
            provided to students;
  19 Kickmeier-Rust, Albert & Linek (2007) A psychological perspective on metacognition and

the usage of confidence ratings. Draft for internal use of elektra consortium
  20 Shuford, E. H., Albert, A., and Massengill, H. E. (1966). Admissible probability mea-

surement procedures. Psychometrika, 31(2):125–45.
  21 Hirschberg, G. (2007) DELIVERABLE Name: Phase 1 – Validation Report
  22 Leclercq, D. (1983). Confidence marking, its use in testing. Postlethwaite, Choppin (eds)

Evaluation in Education, Oxford : Pergamon, 1982, vol. 6, 2, pp. 161-287.
  23 Leclercq, D. (1986). La conception des questions ` choix multiple, Bruxelles, Ed. Labor.
                                                         a
  24 Leclercq, D. (1993). Validity, reliability and acuity of self-assessment in educational test-

ing. In Leclercq, D. and Bruno, J., editors, Item Banking : Interactive Testing and Self-
Assessment, number F 112 in NATO ASI Series, pages 114–131. Berlin: Springer Verlag.


                                                8
(d) students must be trained to use certitude degrees.
      The respect of these rules is mandatory for anyone willing to use certitude
      degrees and avoid confusion or deception.
  2. Chosen certitude and chosen answer are not recorded into the game. Both
     teacher and learner should be able to view the results, success and failure,
     during tries and tasks. These data should influence the feedbacks. As
     such they can be part of micro-adaptivity.
  3. The feedback should be more precise. Galileo might say something like:



   When I asked you how confident you were about succeeding this task, you
   told me you were XX% confident succeeding it.
   If (FAILURE) then
       If (chosen certitude degree > 50%) then
            You did not succeed. But you were very confident you would
            succeed. So you’ve made a bad assumption. You should be more
            careful in your estimations. Try again and be more modest with
            your confidence.
       else
           You did not succeed. But you confidence in your ability to
           succeed was low. So your assumption was good: you have failed
           but you knew it was risky so you associated doubt with your
           try. I congratulate you for that. Give it another try.
       end If
   else
      If (chosen certitude degree ≤ 50%) then
           You’ve succeeded. Congratulations. But your confidence in
           your ability was too low. You should be more confident in your
           estimations.
      else
          You’ve succeeded. Congratulations. And your estimation was a
          good assumption: you were sure and you’ve succeeded. That’s
          great.
      end If
   end If



Notice how feedbacks about cognition and metacognition are in different sen-
tences as suggested in section 2.3.2, page 5. Knowledge feedbacks are clearly
different than support of metacognition. When a few tries have been made, the
feedback can even turn to be more precise. This will be described in the last
part of this document.

4.3    Experiment in world 2 and metacognition
We also suggest that, in world 2, the player should be able to turn on and off
the flashlight. He should only be allowed to move the blinds and the screen

                                       9
when the torch is turned off. After he has placed all the objects the way he
wants, he will have to turn the flashlight on to see the results.
    Even if the player does not find the correct solution he will see the result of
what he built when turning the flashlight on. He will see it in 3D and will also see
the associated top view. When the player turns on the flashlight Galileo might
also ask a question like “How sure are you that this construction will produce a
narrow beam of light?” When turning it off Galileo will give a feedback (see the
previous algorithm). Instead of Galileo always asking the same question about
confidence, we suggest that the switch of the light might be something like

                  off            on with certitude degree of
                          0%     20% 40% 60% 80% 100%

            Table 1: Flashlight on–off switch enhanced with certitude degree




4.4    The metal-wooden door and the blinds
Imagine that the player succeed placing the blinds and screen in LeS1.2a in
world 2 with a very good confidence. Then he/she fails in the real world with
the metal-wooden door. What kind of feedback can we give about what he/she
has learned in world 2? What kind of feedback can we give about his/her
confidence in succeeding the task based on what he/she has experimented in
world 2? We have no answer for these questions because the problem, from our
point of view, is that the metal-wooden door does not evaluate what might have
been learned with the blinds and screen in world2. This seems impossible to be
changed. So we recommend not to use certitude degrees at the moment with
the opening of the metal–wooden door situation.


5     Deeper with certitude degree
The demonstrator is working on one single expression of the player’s jol. It is
difficult for him to gain any metacognitive knowledge with a single measurement.
The only feedback we can actually give with the actual state of development of
the demonstrator is a goodbad performance associated with a confidentnon
confident jol as showed in table 2.

                                       good                     bad
                                   performance             performance
             confident                  Best                   Worst
                                 good knowledge         wrong knowledge
                                 good confidence           bad confidence
             non confident        good knowledge         lack of knowledge
                                        but                     but
                                lack of confidence        good confidence


    Table 2: Feedback class associated with the combination of true-false and confidence




                                           10
5.1     Theoretical background
The following is based on the works of Hunt (1993), Jans & Leclercq (1999) and
Leclercq (2003) and gives a much more detailed measure of knowledge with the
association of a confidence chosen out of a scale of 6 degrees of certitude (see
figures 3 to 5, pages 11 et 12). All figures are spectral distributions of knowledge.
On the left hand side are the incorrect answers. They are distributed by the
learner chosen confidence, ranking from left to right from 100% down to 0%. In
the middle is the grey area of not answered questions. On the right hand side
are the correct answer, also distributed by confidence but ranking from left to
right from 0% to 100%. Figure 3 showed Darwin Hunt (1993) 25 suggestion to
distinguish between three types of knowledge situations in which a person can
be in relation to a piece of content : “misinformed, uninformed, informed”.




       Figure 3: Spectral distributions of Hunt’s three situations of knowledge (1993)


    These situations were redefined –see figure 4– by Jans & Leclercq (1999) 26
as: “dangerous knowledge, unusable knowledge, usable knowledge”.
    Unhappy with the “unusable knowledge” unable to make the difference be-
tween a student making a mistake with a low confidence and a student hav-
ing a low confidence in a correct answer, Leclercq (2003) 27 divided it into
“unawareness” and “mid knowledge” as showed in figure 5. This is an impor-
tant distinction as mid knowledge needs working on metacognitive judgment, a
   25 Hunt, D. (1993). Human self-assessment : Theory and application to learning and testing.

In Leclercq, D. and Bruno, J., editors, Item Banking : Interactive Testing and Self-Assessment,
volume F 112 of NATO ASI Series, pages 177–189. Berlin: Springer Verlag
   26 Jans, V. and Leclercq, D. (1999) Mesurer l’effet de l’apprentissage ` l’aide de l’analyse
                                                                           a
spectrale des performances.      In Depover, C. and No¨l, B., editors, L’´valuation des
                                                            e                   e
comp´tences et des processus cognitifs. Mod`les pratiques et contextes, pages 303-317. Brux-
       e                                      e
elles : De Boeck Universit´e
   27 Leclercq, D. (2003). Un diagnostic cognitif et m´tacognitif au seuil de l’universit´. Le
                                                        e                                 e
projet MOHICAN men´ par les 9 universit´s de la Communaut´ Fran¸aise Wallonie Bruxelles.
                        e                   e                   e      c
Li`ge : Editions de l’Universit´ de Li`ge.
   e                           e       e



                                              11
Figure 4: Spectral distribution of knowledge kinds by Jans & Leclercq (1999) based on Hunt’s
three situation of knowledge


metacognitive part, and unawareness needs to first work on knowledge, a cogni-
tive part. Again, as mentioned in section2.3.2 page 5, do not confuse assessment
of knowledge and support of metacognition with certitude degrees. It is already




Figure 5: Leclercq’s (2003) spectral splitting of Jans & Leclercq’s (1999) unusable knowledge


much better than a simple correct or not correct feedback. But certitude degrees
allows to give much more refined feedbacks.




                                             12
5.2    Application in the game
Certitude degrees will add a dimension in storytelling as we define a new “socio-
affective” goal to the game: George is to gain the trust of Galileo Galilei to
become the new trustfully leader of the Galileans. Galileo’s trust in George will
be based on his good use on certitude degrees, mainly based on confidence in
retrieved answers. The point is to give a general feedback on how the player is
using certitude degree. Not only immediatly after after a single judgment as it
is in the actual demonstrator but with enough measure to pin tendencies like
over– and under–estimation, see section 2.3, page 4.

5.3    Technical implementation
So on top of what was suggested here above, the program should compute
two values and communicate with the player about confidence (mcdca) and
imprudence (mcdia) as defined by Leclercq & Poumay (2004):
  1. mcdca is the mean certitude degree when the tries are successful or

                                                    n (n · pn )
                        Conf idencce = CDcA =                                (1)
                                                    NCDcA

      where
        • CDcA stands for mean certitude degree for correct answers;
        • n is a certitude degree (0%, 20%, 40%, 60%, 80% or 100%)
        • pn is the number of use of the n certitude degree associated with
          correct answers;
        • NCDcA is the number of use of the certitude degrees in correct an-
          swers;
  2. mcdia is the mean certitude degree when the tries are unsuccessful or

                                                    n (n   · qn )
                         Imprudence = CDiA =                                 (2)
                                                    NCDiA

        • CDiA stands for mean certitude degree for incorrect answers;
        • n is a certitude degree (0%, 20%, 40%, 60%, 80% or 100%)
        • qn is the number of use of the n certitude degree associated with
          incorrect answers;
        • NCDiA is the number of use of the certitude degrees in incorrect
          answers.

Exemple : Out of a test of 7 questions a student has 5 correct answers and
2 incorrect answers. All 7 answers were associated with a certitude degree as
showed in table 3 page 14.
    To compute confidence we focus on the correct answers only: first we count
the number of use of certitude degree 0% (only for correct answer!). So n is 0%.
In our exemple, there is 1 use of certitude degree 0% with a correct answer. So
p0 = 1. We multiply those two numbers by each other: n · pn giving 0 · 1 = 0.


                                       13
Question     Answer       Certitude degree
                          1           C                 80
                          2           C                 20
                          3           C                 100
                          4           C                  0
                          5           C                 80
                          6           I                 60
                          7           I                  0


 Table 3: Exemple for the computation of confidence and imprudence (C for correct answer
and I for Incorrect answer).



Then we do the same for n = 20% which means that we count the number of
use of certitude degree 20%, only for correct answer! In our exemple there is 1
use of certitude 20% within all correct answers: p20 = 1. We multiply those two
numbers by each other: n · pn giving 20 · 1 = 20. Same thing for n = 40% which
means that we count the number of use of certitude degree 40%, remember only
for correct answer! In our exemple there is no use of certitude 40% within all
correct answers: p40 = 0. We multiply those two numbers by each other: n · pn
giving 40·0 = 0. Same thing for each certitude degree (60%, 80%) until we reach
certitude of 100% (n = 100%) with one use of certitude 100% making p100 = 1.
We multiply those two numbers by each other: n · pn giving 100 · 1 = 100. We
sum all n · pn into [(0 · 1) + (20 · 1) + (40 · 0) + (60 · 0) + (80 · 2) + (100 · 1)]
and divide by NCDcA or the number of use of certitude degree associated with
correct answers, in our case 5. Final equation being [0+20+0+0+160+100] = 56
                                                                     5
    To compute Imprudence, it is the same process but focusing only on incorrect
answers. So we finish with [(0 · 1) + (20 · 0) + (40 · 0) + (60 · 1) + (80 · 0) + (100 · 0)]
and divide by NCDcA or the number of use of certitude degree associated with
incorrect answers, in our case 2. Final equation being [0+0+0+60+0+0] = 30. So
                                                                     2
in our exemple confidence is 56% and imprudence 30%.
    It is in the computation of those mean values that the use of a scale with
6 levels makes sense. First Miller’s (1956) 28 works demonstrated that people
are able to work with 7 plus or minus two certitude degrees to choose from.
And the 6 levels are very easy to remember as they are from 0% to 100% step
of 20%. Shuford et al.(1966)29 demonstrated the necessity of using subjective
probabilities instead of verbal expressions. Finally it is after a number of answers
that mean values are computed taking into account every choice made by the
student. In the case of elektra, after collecting certitude degrees during the
student’s experimentations it is expected that the mean certitude of correct
answers (mcdca) –that is to say for the successful tries, should above 50%.
Mixing well the use of all 6 levels of the certitude degree scale, students should
learn to weight their certitude in a correct way when they are about to succeed.
A student will be considered as confident when his confidence is above 50%.
On the other side the mean certitude of incorrect answers (mcdia) –that is to
  28 Miller, G. (1956). The magical number seven, plus or minus two: Some limits on our

capacity for processing information. Psychological Review, (63):81–97
  29 Shuford, E. H., Albert, A., and Massengill, H. E. (1966). Admissible probability mea-

surement procedures. Psychometrika, 31(2):125–45



                                            14
say for the unsuccessful tries, should be below 50%. Students should learn to
be modest in confidence using low value on the 6 level scale. An accident may
always occur like using a high certitude degree and failing but the tendency
should be that when about to fail student learn to be prudent. An imprudent
student will be a student with an imprudence above 50%. The best performance
is
   • a confidence of 100% or a mean certitude degree for the successful answers
     of 100% and
   • an imprudence of 0% or a mean certitude degree for the unsuccessful
     answers of 0%
For gaming reasons, LMR asked that instead of trying to reach 100% on one
scale and 0% on another scale the student should always try to maximize his
score (like gaining points) or to minimize his level (like note losing live points
when fighting). To comply we suggest to use prudence instead of imprudence

                            prudence = 100 − imprudence                       (3)

Imprudence or mean certitude degree of incorrect answer should ideally be as
low as possible. Over 50% is the limit when the student becomes imprudent.
With the inversion presented in equation (3) goals are exactly the opposite.
Prudence should ideally be as close to 100% as possible. A student will be
qualified as prudent if his prudence is over 50%.

5.4    Graphic interface
Prudence and confidence will be the indicators of Galileo’s trust gained by the
player. We suggest to represent prudence and confidence to use the certimeter
that was invented by Galileo and suggested by Frederic Pourbaix. There will
be 2 certimeters, one for the confidence (mean certitude of correct answers) and
one for prudence (100 − mean certitude of incorrect answers), see figure 6. Both
certimeter will be graduated from 0% to 100%. Suggested colors might be from
red to light red between 0% and 50% and from light green to green from 50%
to 100%.
    Including prudence and confidence we offer a possible answer to ORT rec-
ommendation30 : “The idea of confidence degree [. . . ] and may have the form
of points in the game, which will bring the pupils to think further about their
answer and will bring additional anticipation.” The aim of the player will be to
reach green level score on both certimeter meaning that Galileo can trust him
when he says that he is confident or when he says that he doubt. Of course to
make the “eclipse machine” work the player will have to gain knowledge and
comprehension of optic physics and astronomy. But the player should also pay
attention to some metacognitive aspects: confidence and prudence. If the player
fails to gain Galileo’s trust but manage to get the “eclipse machine” working
he will gain access to the Galilean’s secret headquarters and to the book. But
maybe Galileo will be a bit reluctant to help the player using the book. . . and
give him a feedback in that way, unless the player starts the game all over again
and tries to improve his score on both certimeter. Success in the game could
 30 Hirschberg,   G. (2007) DELIVERABLE Name: Phase 1 – Validation Report


                                          15
Figure 6: Rough design of a possible way to communicate to the player the level of Galileo’s
         trust gained: the cursor on each certimeter takes the color of the position in the color grada-
         tion. Both cursor must be at least light green to gain Galileo’s trust.




         then be achieved by reaching the Galilean’s HQ. But another level of success
         will be to reach HQ and to gain Galileo’s trust.

         5.5     Realistic use of certitude degrees
         The feedbacks could take the form described in this algorithm here after. The
         limit values of 50% used in this alogrithm should be variables. Four limits are
         to be created and defined at a default level of 50
conf-lim-ccd the limit to judge a single judgement with a correct answer or the limit
             to be declared confident in a single judgment
prud-lim-ccd the limit to judge a single judgment with an incorrect answer or the limit
             to be declared prudent in a single judgment

  mcdca-lim the limit to judge the mean certitude degree for correct answer as good or
            not or when is the player confident or not in the game so far
   mcdia-lim the limit to judge the mean certitude degree for incorrect answer as good
             or not or when is the player prudent or not in the game so far
             Every situation is symbolized by a group in between brackets (e.g., F + -).

             • First with a letter
                  F for failure in case of an unsuccessful try
                   S for success in case of a successful try


                                                       16
• a plus (+) or (-) sign
    + if the chosen confidence degree is above 50%
     - if the chosen confidence degree is below 50%
• a plus (+) or (-) sign
    + if the mean confidence degree is above 50%
     - if the mean confidence degree is below 50%



ccd (chosen certitude degree) : matrix;
mcdca (mean certitude degree of correct answers) : integer;
mcdia (mean certitude degree of incorrect answers) : integer;

print When I asked you how confident you were about succeeding
this task, you told me you were {ccd}% confident succeeding it.
If (FAILURE) then
     If (ccd > 50) then
          If (mcdia > 50) then
               print Situation A (F + +)
          else
              print Situation B (F + -)
          end If
     else
         If (mcdia ≤ 50) then
              print Situation C (F - -)
         else
             print Situation D (F - +)
         end If
     end If
else
    If (ccd ≤ 50) then
         If (mcdca > 50) then
              print Situation E (S - +)
         else
             print Situation F (S - -)
         end If
    else
        If (mcdca ≤ 50) then
             print Situation G (S + -)
        else
            print Situation H (S + +)
        end If
    end If
end If




                                  17
5.5.1   Situation A (F + +)
Situation: Test unsuccessful, confident in answer, tend to be overconfident
when wrong.
Feedback: You did not succeed. And you were very confident you would
succeed. So you’ve made a bad assumption. You should be more careful in your
estimations. When you failed you tend to choose a too high certitude degree.
So when you fail your average prudence is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that
it should be over {mcdia-lim}%. You should try to be less confident when
you choose a certitude degree. You should learn to be a bit more modest and
humble. You tend to believe you know when you’re still learning. So give it
another try. A try to be more modest if you doubt, even a little.

5.5.2   Situation B (F + -)
Situation: Test unsuccessful, confident in answer, tend to be prudent when
wrong.
Feedback: You did not succeed. You were very confident you would succeed.
So you made a bad assumption but I consider this assumption as an accident.
Usually you seem prudent in your own estimations. Every time you’ve failed
you’ve chosen before a low certitude degree. So when you fail your prudence
is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that it should be over {mcdia-lim}% so I trust
your judgement. Keep going like that when you choose a certitude degree and
maybe go back to the table for some more experimentation.

5.5.3   Situation C (F - -)
Situation: Test unsuccessful, prudent in answer, tend to be prudent when
wrong.
Feedback: You did not succeed. But you certitude in your ability to succeed
was low: you were prudent. So your assumption was good: you have failed but
you knew it was risky so you associated doubt with your try. I congratulate
you for that. It is important for me to know if I can trust you. In case case of
course you’ve failed but before failing you told me that you were not sure. And
as usual when you say that you’re not sure you do not succeed. So this failure
is not important at all. It seems you’re quite good at being prudent: usually
when you’ve failed you’ve chosen before a low certitude degree. So when you
fail your overall prudence is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that it should be over
{mcdia-lim}%. That is a good performance. Continue to do so and I will keep
my trust in your judgments. But you still need to succeed this task: give it
another try.

5.5.4   Situation D (F - +)
Situation: Test unsuccessful, prudent in answer, tend to be overconfident when
wrong.
Feedback: You did not succeed. But this time your assumption was good: you
have failed but you knew it was risky so you associated doubt with your try. I
congratulate you for that. You should continue to behave like that because it
does not appear you’re very skilled at this on the long run. For instance, when
you fail your average prudence is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that it should be


                                      18
over {mcdia-lim}%. That is why I said you’re not very skilled. With such a
value I will wait for you to improve before fully trusting your judgement. Maybe
you should go back to the table for some more experimentation before giving it
another try. And do not forget to keep going like you just did in giving your
confidence.

5.5.5    Situation E (S - +)
Situation: Test successful, prudent in answer, tend to be confident when right.
Feedback: To be completed

5.5.6    Situation F (S - -)
Situation: Test successful, prudent in answer, tend to be under confident when
right.
Feedback: To be completed

5.5.7    Situation G (S + -)
Situation: Test successful, confident in answer, tend to be under confident
when right.
Feedback: To be completed

5.5.8    Situation H (S + +)
Situation: Test successful, confident in answer, tend to be confident when
right.
Feedback: To be completed

5.6     Even more complex feedbacks
It will really be enjoying for the player to hear the same long feedback. We
suggest that all these information should be delivered not at once but over a
number of tries. Counter of try and counters of times being in the same situation
(e.g., F + - or S + +) should be implemented into the if–then–else loops. So the
first time the player is in situation A he will received a more simple feedback
but the second time he will receive a different feedback. It will be only after
number of correct or incorrect answers that the computed mean values will have
any meaning and so can be given to the player. Prudence and confidence can
already have significant values computed on 55 value of certitude chosen by the
player if we had the suggested game situation into the tutorial.


6       Certitude degrees in LU1.2b
The Labset proposition for Elektra learning situation 1.2b (the slope) is similar
to what we propose for learning situation 1.2a (the blinds) : every time George
wants to release a marble he is asked his confidence in reaching the target on a
scale from 0% to 100% by step of 20%. We suggest that beneath to the cursors
for the magnet and the fan a third cursor with “confidence to reach the target”
record the confidence associated with each try. Feedbacks will be less systematic


                                       19
as the player/learner should be more aware of his confidence score showed in the
certimeter. When the player successfully dropped all 3 balls in the basket Galileo
will ask him a transfer question. The player will have to chose out of a number
a drawings the one that will represent the trajectory of light when turned on.
He will also be asked about his confidence. Imagine they are only 4 drawing to
choose from and the player knows that if he fails he can immediately try again.
Without confidence degrees the player may try any of the 4 propositions until
he finds the right one. But with confidence degrees he knows that if he chooses
a wrong one and is confident in his guessing he will loose some of Galileo’s trust.
So he might know the right solution, be confident and then will answer with
a high confidence degree. He also may guess the right solution but then the
chosen certitude should be lower. If guessing all proposition until he finds the
correct one, all confidence will be low31 . So teacher will have information on
how did the student reached transfer.


7     The tutorial for certitude degrees
ORT recommended32 that “The idea of confidence degree should be explained in
the beginning of the game (tutorial)”. The player will receive some explications
about the Galileans. It is at that moment that certitude degrees should be ex-
plained. We propose a theoretical information based on transmission–reception
and a gaming situation similar to experimentation–reactivity.
    The tutorial should include
    1. the player should gain the trust of Galileo Galilei
    2. Galileo’s trust is based on the fact the when someone says “I know” he
       can trust that knowledge. And when someone doubt that person is right
       to doubt.
    3. To gain Galileo trust everytime the player will experiment to solve an
       enigma he will be asked how confident he his that he will succeed resolving
       the enigma at this exact moment, on this precise try.
    4. To indicate his self-confidence the player will chose one certitude degree
       between 0%, 20%, 40%, 60%, 80% and 100%. Points will be gained and
       lost based on
           • if what the player just tried is successful and
                – if he has chosen a high certitude degree he will gain confidence
                  points
                – if he has chosen a low confidence degree he will loose confidence
                  points
           • else if what the player just tried is unsuccessful and
                – if he has chosen a high certitude degree he will loose prudence
                  points
                – if he has chosen a low confidence degree he will gain prudence
                  points
 31 with   the limitation that certitude will go up as the number of possible answers goes down.
 32 Hirschberg,   G. (2007) DELIVERABLE Name: Phase 1 – Validation Report


                                               20
5. In other word if the player bet 100% on a try and if that try is
          • successful then he will gain a lot of confidence points
          • unsuccessful then he will loose a lot of prudence points
   6. On the other hand if the player bet 0% on a try and if that try is
          • successful then he will loose a lot of confidence points
          • unsuccessful then he will gain a lot of prudence points

We suggest that this “theoretical” explanation is to be followed with a Gaming
Situation based on betting certitude degrees. This might be something like the
Shannon Guessing Game (1951)33 or another gaming situation that UL will
provide.

7.1     Shannon’s guessing game
“The new method of estimating entropy exploits the fact that anyone speaking
a language possesses, implicitly, an enormous knowledge of the statistics of the
language. Familiarity with the words, idioms, cliches and grammar enables
him to fill in missing or incorrect letters in proof-reading, or to complete an
unfinished phrase in conversation. An experimental demonstration of the extent
to which English is predictable can be given as follows; Select a short passage
unfamiliar to the person who is to do the predicting, He is then asked to guess
the first letter in the passage. If the guess is correct he is so informed, and
proceeds to guess the second letter. If not, he is told the correct first letter
and proceeds to his next guess. This is continued through the text. As the
experiment progresses, the subject writes down the correct text up to the current
point for use in predicting future letters.” Gilles & Leclercq (1994) 34 have
adapted this game to train student to use certitude degrees: each time a letter
is chosen a certitude for it being the right next letter in the sentence is asked.
Metacognitive indices like realism are computed and a graphical representation
of the confidence in retrieved answer is drawn. The student tries to find the
text and to score well in metacognitive judgment.
    In elektra the passage might be a simple phrase like The secret book of
the Galileans is in the third drawer of the desk. The player will face an empty
parchment that will be filled with letters written by a 3D feather when the
player types a letter and a certitude degree. If the letter is incorrect it will
burn, disappear and be replaced by the correct letter. Prudence and confidence
will be computed and a metacognitive feedback will be generated. Then the
player is to guess the next letter and so on.

7.2     Tutorial for teacher
We also suggest that informations about metacognition and certitude degrees
should be available for teachers. These informations should cover a wide domain,
from objectives in the elektra game to proposition of reflection path about
  33 Shannon, C. E. (1951) Prediction and entropy in printed English, Bell Syst. Tech. J., 30,

1951, 50-64
  34 Leclercq, D. & Gilles, J.-L. (1994). GUESS, un logiciel pour entraˆ
                                                                       ıner ` l’auto-estimation
                                                                            a
de sa comp´tence cognitive. Actes du colloque QCM et questionnaires ferm´s, Paris: ISIEE
            e                                                                 e


                                              21
metacognition in classroom and support to further metacognitive activities for
the students.


8     Conclusion
Knowing how to learn, and knowing which strategies work best, are valuable
skills that differentiate expert learners from novice learners. Metacognition, or
awareness of the process of learning, is a critical ingredient to successful learning.
“Metacognition is an important concept in cognitive theory. It consists of two
basic processes occurring simultaneously: monitoring your progress as you learn,
and making changes and adapting your strategies if you perceive you are not
doing so well” (Winn, W. & Snyder, D., 1998).35




Contents
1 Why certitude degrees in learning?                                                                                     1

2 What is metacognition?                                                                                                 2
  2.1 Metacognition in general . . . . . . . . . . . .                      .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    2
  2.2 Certitude degrees and metacognition . . . . .                         .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    4
  2.3 Metacognition in the demonstrator . . . . . .                         .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    4
      2.3.1 What is a JOL? . . . . . . . . . . . .                          .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    5
      2.3.2 JOL or confidence in retrieved answer                            .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    5

3 Metacognition in games                                                                                                 6

4 About the demonstrator, 2006 version                                                                                   7
  4.1 A surprise . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .                .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    7
  4.2 General comments . . . . . . . . . . . . .                    .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    8
  4.3 Experiment in world 2 and metacognition                       .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .    9
  4.4 The metal-wooden door and the blinds . .                      .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   10

5 Deeper with certitude degree                                                                                          10
  5.1 Theoretical background . . . . .          .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   11
  5.2 Application in the game . . . . .         .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   13
  5.3 Technical implementation . . . .          .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   13
  5.4 Graphic interface . . . . . . . . .       .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   15
  5.5 Realistic use of certitude degrees        .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   16
      5.5.1 Situation A (F + +) . . .           .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   18
  35 Winn, W. & Snyder D. (1996). Cognitive perspectives in pyschology. In D.H. Jonassen,

ed. Handbook of research for educational communications and technology, 112-142. New
York: Simon & Schuster Macmillan



                                           22
5.5.2 Situation B (F + -) .      .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   18
         5.5.3 Situation C (F - -) . .    .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   18
         5.5.4 Situation D (F - +) .      .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   18
         5.5.5 Situation E (S - +) . .    .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   19
         5.5.6 Situation F (S - -) . .    .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   19
         5.5.7 Situation G (S + -) .      .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   19
         5.5.8 Situation H (S + +) .      .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   19
   5.6   Even more complex feedbacks      .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   .   19

6 Certitude degrees in LU1.2b                                                                                             19

7 The tutorial for certitude degrees                                           20
  7.1 Shannon’s guessing game . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
  7.2 Tutorial for teacher . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21

8 Conclusion                                                                                                              22


List of Tables
   1     Flashlight on–off switch enhanced with certitude degree . . . .                                                  10
   2     Feedback class associated with the combination of true-false and
         confidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .                                          10
   3     Exemple for the computation of confidence and imprudence (C
         for correct answer and I for Incorrect answer). . . . . . . . . . . .                                            14


List of Figures
   1     Main components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive
         control defined by Nelson (1996) and Nelson & Narens (1994) . .                                                    3
   2     Cut scene from the elektra demonstrator, 2006 . . . . . . . . .                                                   7
   3     Spectral distributions of Hunt’s three situations of knowledge (1993)                                            11
   4     Spectral distribution of knowledge kinds by Jans & Leclercq (1999)
         based on Hunt’s three situation of knowledge . . . . . . . . . . .                                               12
   5     Leclercq’s (2003) spectral splitting of Jans & Leclercq’s (1999)
         unusable knowledge . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .                                             12
   6     Rough design of a possible way to communicate to the player the
         level of Galileo’s trust gained: the cursor on each certimeter takes
         the color of the position in the color gradation. Both cursor must
         be at least light green to gain Galileo’s trust. . . . . . . . . . . .                                           16




                                         23

Más contenido relacionado

Destacado

Presentation1
Presentation1Presentation1
Presentation1
cwihhs
 
Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)
Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)
Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)
Lene Krogh Jeppesen
 
Presentation1
Presentation1Presentation1
Presentation1
cwihhs
 
Horse Slaughter
Horse SlaughterHorse Slaughter
Horse Slaughter
cwihhs
 
Apocalypse
ApocalypseApocalypse
Apocalypse
cwihhs
 
Current issues and challenges in education
Current issues and challenges in educationCurrent issues and challenges in education
Current issues and challenges in education
thenetworkcampus
 
Aims and Purposes in Education
Aims and Purposes in EducationAims and Purposes in Education
Aims and Purposes in Education
Joey Miñano
 
the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)
the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)
the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)
Lorein May Pabilona
 
Current Issues in Education PowerPoint
Current Issues in Education PowerPointCurrent Issues in Education PowerPoint
Current Issues in Education PowerPoint
Kayla
 
Philippine education presentation
Philippine education presentationPhilippine education presentation
Philippine education presentation
Carlo Magno
 

Destacado (20)

Clvsllc
ClvsllcClvsllc
Clvsllc
 
Presentation1
Presentation1Presentation1
Presentation1
 
Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)
Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)
Skattefar: En myndighed på Twitter (September 2013)
 
Developing Countries Pursuing Nuclear Technology
Developing Countries Pursuing Nuclear TechnologyDeveloping Countries Pursuing Nuclear Technology
Developing Countries Pursuing Nuclear Technology
 
Presentation1
Presentation1Presentation1
Presentation1
 
Horse Slaughter
Horse SlaughterHorse Slaughter
Horse Slaughter
 
An experience using degrees of certitude
An experience using degrees of certitudeAn experience using degrees of certitude
An experience using degrees of certitude
 
Is it Spring Yet?
Is it Spring Yet?Is it Spring Yet?
Is it Spring Yet?
 
Pptpodcast2
Pptpodcast2Pptpodcast2
Pptpodcast2
 
Rehearsal Ppt
Rehearsal PptRehearsal Ppt
Rehearsal Ppt
 
Apocalypse
ApocalypseApocalypse
Apocalypse
 
Stress Management Presentation
Stress Management PresentationStress Management Presentation
Stress Management Presentation
 
Teaching Architecture, incl. Studio: Education's Sciences POV
Teaching Architecture, incl. Studio: Education's Sciences POVTeaching Architecture, incl. Studio: Education's Sciences POV
Teaching Architecture, incl. Studio: Education's Sciences POV
 
AIM,OBJECTIVE AND PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION
AIM,OBJECTIVE AND PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATIONAIM,OBJECTIVE AND PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION
AIM,OBJECTIVE AND PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION
 
Current issues and challenges in education
Current issues and challenges in educationCurrent issues and challenges in education
Current issues and challenges in education
 
Aims and Purposes in Education
Aims and Purposes in EducationAims and Purposes in Education
Aims and Purposes in Education
 
Historical Perspective Of The Philippine Educational System
Historical Perspective Of The Philippine Educational SystemHistorical Perspective Of The Philippine Educational System
Historical Perspective Of The Philippine Educational System
 
the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)
the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)
the history of the Philippines education (teaching profession)
 
Current Issues in Education PowerPoint
Current Issues in Education PowerPointCurrent Issues in Education PowerPoint
Current Issues in Education PowerPoint
 
Philippine education presentation
Philippine education presentationPhilippine education presentation
Philippine education presentation
 

Similar a Metacognition in ELEKTRA

1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main
1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main
1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main
Anne de Hulster
 
7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing ...
7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing  ...7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing  ...
7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing ...
AhL'Dn Daliva
 
kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008
Joel Zucker
 
kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008
Joel Zucker
 
Describe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docx
Describe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docxDescribe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docx
Describe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docx
theodorelove43763
 
Metacogntion seminar
Metacogntion seminarMetacogntion seminar
Metacogntion seminar
Carlo Magno
 
Assessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/Product
Assessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/ProductAssessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/Product
Assessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/Product
Carlo Magno
 
งาน จานนัท 2
งาน จานนัท 2งาน จานนัท 2
งาน จานนัท 2
Yuwaporn Nuamtian
 
Cognitive development on high school learners
Cognitive development on high school learnersCognitive development on high school learners
Cognitive development on high school learners
elockin24
 
20121020121032 knowing and doing
20121020121032 knowing and doing20121020121032 knowing and doing
20121020121032 knowing and doing
Ge Chua
 

Similar a Metacognition in ELEKTRA (20)

1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main
1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main
1 s2.0-s1877042812000092-main
 
Achievement In Problem Solving And Metacognitive Thinking Strategies Among Un...
Achievement In Problem Solving And Metacognitive Thinking Strategies Among Un...Achievement In Problem Solving And Metacognitive Thinking Strategies Among Un...
Achievement In Problem Solving And Metacognitive Thinking Strategies Among Un...
 
7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing ...
7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing  ...7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing  ...
7. the role of metacognitive knowledge in learning, teaching, and assessing ...
 
kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008
 
kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008kellman_et_al_2008
kellman_et_al_2008
 
Relationship Between Metacognition, Attitude And Academic Achievement Of Seco...
Relationship Between Metacognition, Attitude And Academic Achievement Of Seco...Relationship Between Metacognition, Attitude And Academic Achievement Of Seco...
Relationship Between Metacognition, Attitude And Academic Achievement Of Seco...
 
Describe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docx
Describe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docxDescribe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docx
Describe how you would identify bottlenecks in your value stream .docx
 
Bornali poster final
Bornali poster finalBornali poster final
Bornali poster final
 
Metacogntion seminar
Metacogntion seminarMetacogntion seminar
Metacogntion seminar
 
Metacognition
MetacognitionMetacognition
Metacognition
 
Ed teach (my report)
Ed teach (my report)Ed teach (my report)
Ed teach (my report)
 
Assessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/Product
Assessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/ProductAssessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/Product
Assessing Knowledge, Process, Understanding, Performance/Product
 
Metacognition
MetacognitionMetacognition
Metacognition
 
งาน จานนัท 2
งาน จานนัท 2งาน จานนัท 2
งาน จานนัท 2
 
Cognitive development on high school learners
Cognitive development on high school learnersCognitive development on high school learners
Cognitive development on high school learners
 
Flanagan Webinar For Wiley 3 22 10
Flanagan Webinar For Wiley 3 22 10Flanagan Webinar For Wiley 3 22 10
Flanagan Webinar For Wiley 3 22 10
 
1 s2.0-s0273229716300132-main
1 s2.0-s0273229716300132-main1 s2.0-s0273229716300132-main
1 s2.0-s0273229716300132-main
 
Intelligence, Cognitive Styles, Methods of control
Intelligence, Cognitive Styles, Methods of controlIntelligence, Cognitive Styles, Methods of control
Intelligence, Cognitive Styles, Methods of control
 
Chapters 9/10 Presentation
Chapters 9/10 Presentation Chapters 9/10 Presentation
Chapters 9/10 Presentation
 
20121020121032 knowing and doing
20121020121032 knowing and doing20121020121032 knowing and doing
20121020121032 knowing and doing
 

Más de Jean-Loup Castaigne

Más de Jean-Loup Castaigne (20)

Formation des doctorants à l'enseignement
Formation des doctorants à l'enseignementFormation des doctorants à l'enseignement
Formation des doctorants à l'enseignement
 
Formation des nouveaux Enseignants-Chercheurs, IMT-A 2018
Formation des nouveaux Enseignants-Chercheurs, IMT-A 2018Formation des nouveaux Enseignants-Chercheurs, IMT-A 2018
Formation des nouveaux Enseignants-Chercheurs, IMT-A 2018
 
Comment améliorer la qualité des apprentissages à l’aide de l’évaluation des ...
Comment améliorer la qualité des apprentissages à l’aide de l’évaluation des ...Comment améliorer la qualité des apprentissages à l’aide de l’évaluation des ...
Comment améliorer la qualité des apprentissages à l’aide de l’évaluation des ...
 
Enseigner et Apprendre en enseignement supérieur
Enseigner et Apprendre en enseignement supérieurEnseigner et Apprendre en enseignement supérieur
Enseigner et Apprendre en enseignement supérieur
 
Experiential Learning in Architecture Education
Experiential Learning in Architecture EducationExperiential Learning in Architecture Education
Experiential Learning in Architecture Education
 
Année de césure : un truc de branleur ?
Année de césure : un truc de branleur ?Année de césure : un truc de branleur ?
Année de césure : un truc de branleur ?
 
Faire participer les étudiants avec les boîtiers de vote
Faire participer les étudiants avec les boîtiers de voteFaire participer les étudiants avec les boîtiers de vote
Faire participer les étudiants avec les boîtiers de vote
 
Quels outils pour évaluer quels apprentissages ?
Quels outils pour évaluer quels apprentissages ?Quels outils pour évaluer quels apprentissages ?
Quels outils pour évaluer quels apprentissages ?
 
Evaluer les acquis des étudiants
Evaluer les acquis des étudiantsEvaluer les acquis des étudiants
Evaluer les acquis des étudiants
 
Apprentissage par problème APP — PBL
Apprentissage par problème APP — PBLApprentissage par problème APP — PBL
Apprentissage par problème APP — PBL
 
Accompagner mémoires et rapports d'étude en école d'architecture
Accompagner mémoires et rapports d'étude en école d'architectureAccompagner mémoires et rapports d'étude en école d'architecture
Accompagner mémoires et rapports d'étude en école d'architecture
 
Aller plus loin avec les QCM grâce aux degrés de certitude
Aller plus loin avec les QCM grâce aux degrés de certitudeAller plus loin avec les QCM grâce aux degrés de certitude
Aller plus loin avec les QCM grâce aux degrés de certitude
 
Accompagner mémoires et rapports d'étude
Accompagner mémoires et rapports d'étudeAccompagner mémoires et rapports d'étude
Accompagner mémoires et rapports d'étude
 
Classes inversées… avant l’invention du terme
Classes inversées… avant l’invention du termeClasses inversées… avant l’invention du terme
Classes inversées… avant l’invention du terme
 
La pédagogie du projet par le projet pour soutenir la créativité
La pédagogie du projet par le projet pour soutenir la créativitéLa pédagogie du projet par le projet pour soutenir la créativité
La pédagogie du projet par le projet pour soutenir la créativité
 
Séminaire de rentrée des étudiants de L1
Séminaire de rentrée des étudiants de L1Séminaire de rentrée des étudiants de L1
Séminaire de rentrée des étudiants de L1
 
Enseigner et apprendre
Enseigner et apprendreEnseigner et apprendre
Enseigner et apprendre
 
Murène ou Alien ?
Murène ou Alien ?Murène ou Alien ?
Murène ou Alien ?
 
Qui est cette carpe ?
Qui est cette carpe ?Qui est cette carpe ?
Qui est cette carpe ?
 
Quelques indices pour différencier blennies et gobies
Quelques indices pour différencier blennies et gobiesQuelques indices pour différencier blennies et gobies
Quelques indices pour différencier blennies et gobies
 

Último

Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
PECB
 
Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.
Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.
Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.
MateoGardella
 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
QucHHunhnh
 

Último (20)

Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptxUnit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
 
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot GraphZ Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
Z Score,T Score, Percential Rank and Box Plot Graph
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
 
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
 
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
 
Application orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.pptApplication orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.ppt
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
 
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
Código Creativo y Arte de Software | Unidad 1
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
 
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
Advanced Views - Calendar View in Odoo 17
 
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17 How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17  How to Extend Models Using Mixin ClassesMixin Classes in Odoo 17  How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17 How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
 
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
Nutritional Needs Presentation - HLTH 104
 
Ecological Succession. ( ECOSYSTEM, B. Pharmacy, 1st Year, Sem-II, Environmen...
Ecological Succession. ( ECOSYSTEM, B. Pharmacy, 1st Year, Sem-II, Environmen...Ecological Succession. ( ECOSYSTEM, B. Pharmacy, 1st Year, Sem-II, Environmen...
Ecological Succession. ( ECOSYSTEM, B. Pharmacy, 1st Year, Sem-II, Environmen...
 
Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.
Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.
Gardella_Mateo_IntellectualProperty.pdf.
 
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
 
Measures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SD
Measures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SDMeasures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SD
Measures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SD
 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
 
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
 
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdfKey note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
 

Metacognition in ELEKTRA

  • 1. Metacognition in ELEKTRA∗ Jean-Loup Castaigne LabSET — IFRES — University of Liege January 24, 2007 1 Why certitude degrees in learning? In an evaluation based only on identifying correct and incorrect answers there is little information available for both teacher and learner other than right or wrong. Adding certitude degree to evaluation brings a new dimension, allowing more precise conclusions. For instance what conclusion should raise a teacher when 95 % of his students succeed answering a question? What other conclusion if those 95 % successful students only have a mean confidence of 10% in their correct answer? Maybe the teacher will consider this task as not achieved by his students despite 95% of correct answer. The way a test will be corrected will also be different if a majority of students are failing a question with a mean certitude degree of 10% for that question or with a mean certitude degree of 90%. In the first case doubt can be expressed regarding the question itself. In the second case it appears students are confident in their believe which is an incorrect information. This last situation may be considered as dangerous as students will trust what they think they know. Learning does not move someone from total ignorance to perfect knowledge. Often people will already have some knowledge or representation about what is teached, even if these representation or knowledge might be erroneous. Evalua- tion should not be limited to either knowledge or correct answer and ignorance or incorrect answer. Information is what reduces doubt. “Partial information exists. To detect it is necessary and feasible” (De Finetti, 1965)1 . certitude degrees give a teacher a more detailed image of the knowledge of a student: they reveal partial information. ∗ ELEKTRA : “Enhanced Learning Experience and Knowledge TRAnsfer” is an European research project that aims at revolutionising technology-enhanced learning. 1 De Finetti, B. (1965). Methods of discriminating levels of partial knowledge concerning a test item. Bristish Journal of Math. & Statist. Psychol., 18, 87-123. 1
  • 2. 2 What is metacognition? 2.1 Metacognition in general Metacognition has been defined by Flavell (1976)2 : “Metacognition refers to one’s knowledge concerning one’s own cognitive processes or anything related to them, e.g. , the learning-relevant properties of information or data” . Many interpretations were made from the original definition of metacognition but metacognition is agreed to involve both • knowledge about one’s own knowledge and • knowledge about one’s own cognitive processes. Metacognition has to do with the active monitoring and regulation of cognitive processes. Metacognition is also relevant to work on cognitive styles and learning strategies in so far as the individual has some awareness of their thinking or learning processes. Within metacognition “knowledge about memory” is defined as metamem- ory (Flavell & Wellman, 1977)3 . Metamemory itself is declined into declar- ative metamemory (e.g. knowledge about strategy variables) and procedural metamemory with its two components: the monitoring component and the con- trol and self-regulated component. Metacognition • Metamemory 1. Declarative metamemory 2. Procedural metamemory (a) monitoring component (b) control and self-regulated component Schraw and Dennison (1994)4 separate the knowledge and the regulation of cognition, each one being defined into different parts. 1. The knowledge of cognition is composed of: (a) Declarative knowledge: knowledge about one’s skills, intellectual re- sources, and abilities as a learner. (b) Procedural knowledge: knowledge about how to implement learning procedures (e.g., strategies). (c) Conditional knowledge: knowledge about when and why to use learn- ing procedures. 2. The regulation of cognition refers to: 2 Flavell, J.H. (1976). Metacognitive aspects of problem solving. In Resnick (Ed.), The nature of intelligence. (pp. 231-235). New Jersey : Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. 3 Flavell, J.H., & Wellman, H. (1977). Metamemory. In R. V. Kail Jr. & J. Hagen (Eds.), Perspectives on the development of memory and cognition (pp. 3–33). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum 4 Schraw, Gregory, and Rayne Sperling Dennison, 1994. Assessing Metacognitive Aware- ness? In Contemporary Educational Psychology 19, 460-475. 2
  • 3. (a) Planning: planning, goal setting, and allocating resources prior to learning. (b) Information management: skills and strategy sequences used on-line to process information more efficiently (e.g., organizing, elaborating, summarizing, selective focusing). (c) Monitoring: assessment of one’s learning or strategy use. (d) Debugging: strategies used to correct comprehension and perfor- mance errors. (e) Evaluation: analysis of performance and strategy effectiveness after a learning episode. The EARLI 5 metacognition special interest group often refers to the main components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive control that was defined from the works of Nelson (1996) 6 and Nelson & Narens (1994) 7 – see figure 1. Figure 1: Main components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive control defined by Nelson (1996) and Nelson & Narens (1994) Leclercq & Poumay (2004) 8 propose an “operational definition” of metacog- nition: “Observable (or not) judgments, analysis and /or regulations effectuated 5 EARLI: European Association for Research on Learning and Instruction 6 Nelson, T. O. (1996). Gamma is a measure of the accuracy of predicting performance on one item relative to another item, not of the absolute performance on an individual item. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 10, 257–260. 7 Nelson, T. O., & Narens, L. (1994). Why investigate metacognition? In J. Metcalfe & A. Shimamura (Eds.), Metacognition: Knowing about knowing (pp. 1–25). Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books. 8 personal translation of “les jugements, analyses et/ou r´gulations observables effectu´s par e e l’apprenant sur ses propres performances (processus ou produits d’apprentissages), ceci dans des situations de PRE, PER ou POST performance” from Leclercq, D. & Poumay, M. (2004). Une d´finition op´rationnelle de la m´tacognition et ses mises en oeuvre. 21e Conf´rence e e e e internationale de l’AIPU, Morocco: Marrakech. 3
  • 4. by a learner on his/her own performances (learning processes or products), in situations of pre, per or post performance (mainly testing or learning).” 2.2 Certitude degrees and metacognition Ebel (1965)9 defined confidence weighting as “a special mode of responding to objective test items, and special mode of scoring those responses. In general terms, the examinee is asked to indicate not only what he believes to be the correct answer to a question, but also how certain he is of the correctness of his answer”. certitude degrees are confidence weighting. In Nelson & Narens’s main components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive control certitude degrees with testing take place in the monitoring side, retrieval of knowledge category, in the Confidence in retrieved answers box. In Leclercq & Poumay’s operational definition certitude degree with testing will be observable judgments effectuated by a learner on his/her own performances (products), in situations of per performance (testing). 2.3 Metacognition in the demonstrator One can ask if metacognition is usable as such for teenagers 14 years old. In brief, publications that were founded consider tested components of metacogni- tive monitoring and control not significantly different between adults and as low as 10 years old children. Below the age of 10, components significance evolves with age. Flavell, Friedrichs & Hoyt (1970)10 have showed significant correla- tion between predicted and actual memory span in children from the 4th grade and no significant correlation was founded below that age, including at nursery and kindergarden. Young children show unrealistic performances prediction. Schneider (2006)11 offers three theoretical reasons: 1) insufficient metacognitive knowledge (young children not monitoring their memory activities or lacking in understanding about the interplay among relevant factors), 2) predominance of wishful thinking over expectations thus predictions reflecting their desires) and 3) belief in the power of effort. Duell (1986)12 confirm that as children get older they demonstrate more awareness of their thinking processes. In the Elektra demonstrator the use of certitude degrees so far is neither relevant of a “judgment of learning” nor a confidence in retrieved answer. Judg- ments of learning (jols), are defined as judgments that “occur during or after acquisition and are predictions about future test performance on recently stud- ied items” (Nelson & Narens, 1994). 9 Ebel, R. (1965). Confidence weighting and test reliability. Journal of Educational Mea- surement, pages 49–57. 10 Flavell, J. H., Friedrichs, A., & Hoyt, J. (1970). Developmental changes in memorization processes. Cognitive Psychology, 1, 324–340. 11 Schneider 2006, The development of metacognition in childhood and adolescence, keyn- note of the 2nd international biennial conference of the Metacognition Special Interest Group (SIG 16) of the European Association of Research in Learning and Instruction (EARLI), July 2006, Cambridge 12 Duell, O.K. (1986). Metacognitive skills. In G. Phye & T. Andre (Eds.), Cognitive Classroom Learning. Orlando, FL: Academic Press. 4
  • 5. 2.3.1 What is a JOL? Imagine a learner studying pairs of linked words13 such as game–elektra. The learner receives the instructions that each pair should be learned so that subsequently when prompted with the cue (e.g., “game–?”), the learner would recall the target (e.g., “elektra”). An interval of time elapses between the termination of studying a given item and the onset of the jol for that item. This interval could be • extremely brief (e.g., as in an immediate jol that occurs as close in time as possible to the offset of the studied item) or • could be delayed for a more lengthy amount of time (as in a delayed jol) filled with other activity and/or other to-be-learned items. Then the first jol occurs, prompted by a cue that usually consisted of only the cue from the studied item (e.g., “game–?”). The learner generates a jol by choosing the predicted likelihood (e.g., on a Likert-type rating scale or on a scale ranging from 0% to 100% in steps of 20%) of remembering the item on an eventual criterion test that might occur later (e.g., 10–20 minutes later). Other pairs of words are studied, and jols are made for each of them, until every pair had been studied and had received a jol. Finally, following an interval of perhaps 10–20 minutes (filled with other items) from the time of studying a given item, the person received the eventual memory test on that item. The memory test is self-paced, usually asking the person to recall the target when prompted by the cue (e.g., when prompted by “game–?”, the person attempt to recall “elektra”). With this example we demonstrate that what is asked in the demonstrator is neither true jols nor confidence in retrieved answers. 2.3.2 JOL or confidence in retrieved answer We suggest that metacognition in elektra is in a first time limited to the use of certitude degrees with the objective of improving the learner metacognitive self assessment. Kruger & Dunning (1999) 14 showed that “learners whose skills or knowledge bases are weak in a particular area tend to overestimate their ability in that area”. In other words, they don’t know enough to recognize that they lack sufficient knowledge for accurate self-assessment. In contrast, learners whose knowledge or skills are strong may underestimate their ability. These high-ability learners don’t recognize the extent of their knowledge or skills. Kruger and Dunning’s research also shows that “it is possible to teach learners at all ability levels to assess their own performance more accurately”. It is in that perspective that certitude degrees will be implemented in elektra. With the use of certitude degree in elektra we can at least give the learner/player some feedback about their cognitive strategies with the confidence in their retrieved answers. 13 adapted form Nelson, Narens & Dunlosky (2004). A Revised Methodology for Research on Metamemory: Pre-judgment Recall And Monitoring (PRAM). Psychological Methods, Vol. 9, No. 1, 53–69. 14 Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How difficulties in recognizing one’s own incompetence lead to inflated self-assessment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77, 1121-1134. 5
  • 6. Consolidated Research Report M1-6 specifies that metacognition within elek- tra should: • support and facilitate the development of metacognitive abilities and strate- gies and • support the assessment of knowledge. We recommend to be very cautious in identifying what is assessment of knowl- edge and what is support to metacognition. Feedbacks should always be very clear in regard to what they refer to, either cognition–knowledge or metacognition– knowledge about knowledge. With elektra we can provide teachers a tool to begin a reflection with their students about metacognition. The distinction between cognitive and metacognitive strategies is important, partly because it gives some indication of which strategies are the most crucial in determining the effectiveness of learning. It seems that “metacognitive strategies, that allow students to plan, control, and evaluate their learning, have the most central role to play in this respect, rather than those that merely maximize interaction and input . . . Thus the ability to choose and evaluate one’s strategies is of central importance” (Graham, 1997) 15 . Learners who are metacognitively aware know what to do when they don’t know what to do; that is, they have strategies for finding out or figuring out what they need to do. “The use of metacognitive strategies ignites one’s thinking and can lead to more profound learning and im- proved performance, especially among learners who are struggling” (Anderson, 2002) 16 . 3 Metacognition in games Prakash (1999) 17 reports that he heard on the radio a sixth grader explaining what she was learning from playing the Stock Market Game. This game was an activity designed to help children become familiar with how the stock market functions. She said, “This game makes me think how to think”. What this statement reveals is that this young learner was beginning to understand the real key to learning; she was engaged in metacognition using a game. Salda˜a (2004) 18 reports using a Master Mind c modified (order was not n important) to assess metacognitive processes use to solve the enigma. The solution could be found independently or with three levels of assistance 1. focusing on the metacognitive processes present in the task such as • planning aims / strategies, • supervision and control of aims / strategies, • revision of aims / strategies, 15 Graham, S. (1997). Effective language learning. Clevedon, England: Multilingual Mat- ters. 16 Neil J. Anderson, The Role of Metacognition in Second Language Teaching and Learning, Brigham Young University 17 Prakash, S. (Reporter). (1999, March 19). Market games [Radio series episode]. All things considered. Washington: National Public Radio. 18 Salda˜ a, D. (2004) Dynamic Master Mind: interactive use of a game for testing metacog- n nition. School Psychology International, Vol 25(4): 422-438. 6
  • 7. • meta knowledge of possibilities and limitations • meta knowledge of tasks / strategies; 2. scaffolding each and every one of the selfregulatory steps included in the task; 3. modelling of the task solution process On top of working metacognitive process this experiment also showed diversifi- cation in methods for adaptivity. Additional literature research is still under process. Please keep this docu- ment for private use within elektra. 4 About the demonstrator, 2006 version These comments only cover some metacognitive aspects of the demonstrator. 4.1 A surprise When Galileo says that the most important thing is to first define what you want to do, he is asking George to identify the objective. This is a metacognitive activity and looks like what is described by Salda˜a (2004) as “planning aims” n in his Master Mind c experiment. It is a pleasant surprise to see that the formulation of that question turned it into a metacognitive activity. Figure 2: Cut scene from the elektra demonstrator, 2006 7
  • 8. 4.2 General comments 1. The asked question should not have been ‘Are you sure?” but something like “With what you know and what you have learned, how confident are you that you will succeed opening the door in this try?” Asked the way it was, it was confusing as we mentioned as soon as we had the opportunity to look at the demonstrator. But it was too late to change as the validation in ORT Marseilles had already begun. UG document about metacognition 19 mentioned that “As shown for example in the first validation results, the current formulation of the confidence rating is not understood by most individuals of the target group”. We argue that (a) the formulation of the question, especially that lack of “sure of what?” (b) the fact that the question was neither a jol nor a confidence in retrieved answer, (c) the lack of explanations related to the metacognitive aims and the absence of tutorial explaining how to use certitude degree, (d) the lack of training of students in general regarding expression of their confidence, (e) the use of verbal expression e.g., “sure” is confusing by itself and should not be used when retrieving certitude (see Shuford, Albert & Massengill (1966)20 recommendations for the use of subjective prob- abilities instead of verbal expressions) are all explanations of the confusion. As mentioned here above, in collect- ing jol Nelson & Narens themselves are using a probabilistic scale from 0% to 100% by steps of 20%. In the validation report21 ORT mentions that: “It seemed that most pupils didn’t really understand the meaning behind the confidence degree, or the questions that was asked.” We to- tally agree with their recommendation that suggest: “It seems that the question related to the confidence degree wasn’t very clear, it is therefore recommended to formulate the question in a clearer way (adapted to 13-14 years old pupils)”. To avoid confusion we propose section 7 some sugges- tion about what to explain in the tutorial. Shuford (1966) and Leclercq (198322 , 198623 , 199324 ) defined 4 rules when using certitude degrees: (a) the use of probabilistic value instead of words; (b) if points are awarded tariff should respect the decision theory; (c) feedbacks concerning the good or not good use of certitude degree provided to students; 19 Kickmeier-Rust, Albert & Linek (2007) A psychological perspective on metacognition and the usage of confidence ratings. Draft for internal use of elektra consortium 20 Shuford, E. H., Albert, A., and Massengill, H. E. (1966). Admissible probability mea- surement procedures. Psychometrika, 31(2):125–45. 21 Hirschberg, G. (2007) DELIVERABLE Name: Phase 1 – Validation Report 22 Leclercq, D. (1983). Confidence marking, its use in testing. Postlethwaite, Choppin (eds) Evaluation in Education, Oxford : Pergamon, 1982, vol. 6, 2, pp. 161-287. 23 Leclercq, D. (1986). La conception des questions ` choix multiple, Bruxelles, Ed. Labor. a 24 Leclercq, D. (1993). Validity, reliability and acuity of self-assessment in educational test- ing. In Leclercq, D. and Bruno, J., editors, Item Banking : Interactive Testing and Self- Assessment, number F 112 in NATO ASI Series, pages 114–131. Berlin: Springer Verlag. 8
  • 9. (d) students must be trained to use certitude degrees. The respect of these rules is mandatory for anyone willing to use certitude degrees and avoid confusion or deception. 2. Chosen certitude and chosen answer are not recorded into the game. Both teacher and learner should be able to view the results, success and failure, during tries and tasks. These data should influence the feedbacks. As such they can be part of micro-adaptivity. 3. The feedback should be more precise. Galileo might say something like: When I asked you how confident you were about succeeding this task, you told me you were XX% confident succeeding it. If (FAILURE) then If (chosen certitude degree > 50%) then You did not succeed. But you were very confident you would succeed. So you’ve made a bad assumption. You should be more careful in your estimations. Try again and be more modest with your confidence. else You did not succeed. But you confidence in your ability to succeed was low. So your assumption was good: you have failed but you knew it was risky so you associated doubt with your try. I congratulate you for that. Give it another try. end If else If (chosen certitude degree ≤ 50%) then You’ve succeeded. Congratulations. But your confidence in your ability was too low. You should be more confident in your estimations. else You’ve succeeded. Congratulations. And your estimation was a good assumption: you were sure and you’ve succeeded. That’s great. end If end If Notice how feedbacks about cognition and metacognition are in different sen- tences as suggested in section 2.3.2, page 5. Knowledge feedbacks are clearly different than support of metacognition. When a few tries have been made, the feedback can even turn to be more precise. This will be described in the last part of this document. 4.3 Experiment in world 2 and metacognition We also suggest that, in world 2, the player should be able to turn on and off the flashlight. He should only be allowed to move the blinds and the screen 9
  • 10. when the torch is turned off. After he has placed all the objects the way he wants, he will have to turn the flashlight on to see the results. Even if the player does not find the correct solution he will see the result of what he built when turning the flashlight on. He will see it in 3D and will also see the associated top view. When the player turns on the flashlight Galileo might also ask a question like “How sure are you that this construction will produce a narrow beam of light?” When turning it off Galileo will give a feedback (see the previous algorithm). Instead of Galileo always asking the same question about confidence, we suggest that the switch of the light might be something like off on with certitude degree of 0% 20% 40% 60% 80% 100% Table 1: Flashlight on–off switch enhanced with certitude degree 4.4 The metal-wooden door and the blinds Imagine that the player succeed placing the blinds and screen in LeS1.2a in world 2 with a very good confidence. Then he/she fails in the real world with the metal-wooden door. What kind of feedback can we give about what he/she has learned in world 2? What kind of feedback can we give about his/her confidence in succeeding the task based on what he/she has experimented in world 2? We have no answer for these questions because the problem, from our point of view, is that the metal-wooden door does not evaluate what might have been learned with the blinds and screen in world2. This seems impossible to be changed. So we recommend not to use certitude degrees at the moment with the opening of the metal–wooden door situation. 5 Deeper with certitude degree The demonstrator is working on one single expression of the player’s jol. It is difficult for him to gain any metacognitive knowledge with a single measurement. The only feedback we can actually give with the actual state of development of the demonstrator is a goodbad performance associated with a confidentnon confident jol as showed in table 2. good bad performance performance confident Best Worst good knowledge wrong knowledge good confidence bad confidence non confident good knowledge lack of knowledge but but lack of confidence good confidence Table 2: Feedback class associated with the combination of true-false and confidence 10
  • 11. 5.1 Theoretical background The following is based on the works of Hunt (1993), Jans & Leclercq (1999) and Leclercq (2003) and gives a much more detailed measure of knowledge with the association of a confidence chosen out of a scale of 6 degrees of certitude (see figures 3 to 5, pages 11 et 12). All figures are spectral distributions of knowledge. On the left hand side are the incorrect answers. They are distributed by the learner chosen confidence, ranking from left to right from 100% down to 0%. In the middle is the grey area of not answered questions. On the right hand side are the correct answer, also distributed by confidence but ranking from left to right from 0% to 100%. Figure 3 showed Darwin Hunt (1993) 25 suggestion to distinguish between three types of knowledge situations in which a person can be in relation to a piece of content : “misinformed, uninformed, informed”. Figure 3: Spectral distributions of Hunt’s three situations of knowledge (1993) These situations were redefined –see figure 4– by Jans & Leclercq (1999) 26 as: “dangerous knowledge, unusable knowledge, usable knowledge”. Unhappy with the “unusable knowledge” unable to make the difference be- tween a student making a mistake with a low confidence and a student hav- ing a low confidence in a correct answer, Leclercq (2003) 27 divided it into “unawareness” and “mid knowledge” as showed in figure 5. This is an impor- tant distinction as mid knowledge needs working on metacognitive judgment, a 25 Hunt, D. (1993). Human self-assessment : Theory and application to learning and testing. In Leclercq, D. and Bruno, J., editors, Item Banking : Interactive Testing and Self-Assessment, volume F 112 of NATO ASI Series, pages 177–189. Berlin: Springer Verlag 26 Jans, V. and Leclercq, D. (1999) Mesurer l’effet de l’apprentissage ` l’aide de l’analyse a spectrale des performances. In Depover, C. and No¨l, B., editors, L’´valuation des e e comp´tences et des processus cognitifs. Mod`les pratiques et contextes, pages 303-317. Brux- e e elles : De Boeck Universit´e 27 Leclercq, D. (2003). Un diagnostic cognitif et m´tacognitif au seuil de l’universit´. Le e e projet MOHICAN men´ par les 9 universit´s de la Communaut´ Fran¸aise Wallonie Bruxelles. e e e c Li`ge : Editions de l’Universit´ de Li`ge. e e e 11
  • 12. Figure 4: Spectral distribution of knowledge kinds by Jans & Leclercq (1999) based on Hunt’s three situation of knowledge metacognitive part, and unawareness needs to first work on knowledge, a cogni- tive part. Again, as mentioned in section2.3.2 page 5, do not confuse assessment of knowledge and support of metacognition with certitude degrees. It is already Figure 5: Leclercq’s (2003) spectral splitting of Jans & Leclercq’s (1999) unusable knowledge much better than a simple correct or not correct feedback. But certitude degrees allows to give much more refined feedbacks. 12
  • 13. 5.2 Application in the game Certitude degrees will add a dimension in storytelling as we define a new “socio- affective” goal to the game: George is to gain the trust of Galileo Galilei to become the new trustfully leader of the Galileans. Galileo’s trust in George will be based on his good use on certitude degrees, mainly based on confidence in retrieved answers. The point is to give a general feedback on how the player is using certitude degree. Not only immediatly after after a single judgment as it is in the actual demonstrator but with enough measure to pin tendencies like over– and under–estimation, see section 2.3, page 4. 5.3 Technical implementation So on top of what was suggested here above, the program should compute two values and communicate with the player about confidence (mcdca) and imprudence (mcdia) as defined by Leclercq & Poumay (2004): 1. mcdca is the mean certitude degree when the tries are successful or n (n · pn ) Conf idencce = CDcA = (1) NCDcA where • CDcA stands for mean certitude degree for correct answers; • n is a certitude degree (0%, 20%, 40%, 60%, 80% or 100%) • pn is the number of use of the n certitude degree associated with correct answers; • NCDcA is the number of use of the certitude degrees in correct an- swers; 2. mcdia is the mean certitude degree when the tries are unsuccessful or n (n · qn ) Imprudence = CDiA = (2) NCDiA • CDiA stands for mean certitude degree for incorrect answers; • n is a certitude degree (0%, 20%, 40%, 60%, 80% or 100%) • qn is the number of use of the n certitude degree associated with incorrect answers; • NCDiA is the number of use of the certitude degrees in incorrect answers. Exemple : Out of a test of 7 questions a student has 5 correct answers and 2 incorrect answers. All 7 answers were associated with a certitude degree as showed in table 3 page 14. To compute confidence we focus on the correct answers only: first we count the number of use of certitude degree 0% (only for correct answer!). So n is 0%. In our exemple, there is 1 use of certitude degree 0% with a correct answer. So p0 = 1. We multiply those two numbers by each other: n · pn giving 0 · 1 = 0. 13
  • 14. Question Answer Certitude degree 1 C 80 2 C 20 3 C 100 4 C 0 5 C 80 6 I 60 7 I 0 Table 3: Exemple for the computation of confidence and imprudence (C for correct answer and I for Incorrect answer). Then we do the same for n = 20% which means that we count the number of use of certitude degree 20%, only for correct answer! In our exemple there is 1 use of certitude 20% within all correct answers: p20 = 1. We multiply those two numbers by each other: n · pn giving 20 · 1 = 20. Same thing for n = 40% which means that we count the number of use of certitude degree 40%, remember only for correct answer! In our exemple there is no use of certitude 40% within all correct answers: p40 = 0. We multiply those two numbers by each other: n · pn giving 40·0 = 0. Same thing for each certitude degree (60%, 80%) until we reach certitude of 100% (n = 100%) with one use of certitude 100% making p100 = 1. We multiply those two numbers by each other: n · pn giving 100 · 1 = 100. We sum all n · pn into [(0 · 1) + (20 · 1) + (40 · 0) + (60 · 0) + (80 · 2) + (100 · 1)] and divide by NCDcA or the number of use of certitude degree associated with correct answers, in our case 5. Final equation being [0+20+0+0+160+100] = 56 5 To compute Imprudence, it is the same process but focusing only on incorrect answers. So we finish with [(0 · 1) + (20 · 0) + (40 · 0) + (60 · 1) + (80 · 0) + (100 · 0)] and divide by NCDcA or the number of use of certitude degree associated with incorrect answers, in our case 2. Final equation being [0+0+0+60+0+0] = 30. So 2 in our exemple confidence is 56% and imprudence 30%. It is in the computation of those mean values that the use of a scale with 6 levels makes sense. First Miller’s (1956) 28 works demonstrated that people are able to work with 7 plus or minus two certitude degrees to choose from. And the 6 levels are very easy to remember as they are from 0% to 100% step of 20%. Shuford et al.(1966)29 demonstrated the necessity of using subjective probabilities instead of verbal expressions. Finally it is after a number of answers that mean values are computed taking into account every choice made by the student. In the case of elektra, after collecting certitude degrees during the student’s experimentations it is expected that the mean certitude of correct answers (mcdca) –that is to say for the successful tries, should above 50%. Mixing well the use of all 6 levels of the certitude degree scale, students should learn to weight their certitude in a correct way when they are about to succeed. A student will be considered as confident when his confidence is above 50%. On the other side the mean certitude of incorrect answers (mcdia) –that is to 28 Miller, G. (1956). The magical number seven, plus or minus two: Some limits on our capacity for processing information. Psychological Review, (63):81–97 29 Shuford, E. H., Albert, A., and Massengill, H. E. (1966). Admissible probability mea- surement procedures. Psychometrika, 31(2):125–45 14
  • 15. say for the unsuccessful tries, should be below 50%. Students should learn to be modest in confidence using low value on the 6 level scale. An accident may always occur like using a high certitude degree and failing but the tendency should be that when about to fail student learn to be prudent. An imprudent student will be a student with an imprudence above 50%. The best performance is • a confidence of 100% or a mean certitude degree for the successful answers of 100% and • an imprudence of 0% or a mean certitude degree for the unsuccessful answers of 0% For gaming reasons, LMR asked that instead of trying to reach 100% on one scale and 0% on another scale the student should always try to maximize his score (like gaining points) or to minimize his level (like note losing live points when fighting). To comply we suggest to use prudence instead of imprudence prudence = 100 − imprudence (3) Imprudence or mean certitude degree of incorrect answer should ideally be as low as possible. Over 50% is the limit when the student becomes imprudent. With the inversion presented in equation (3) goals are exactly the opposite. Prudence should ideally be as close to 100% as possible. A student will be qualified as prudent if his prudence is over 50%. 5.4 Graphic interface Prudence and confidence will be the indicators of Galileo’s trust gained by the player. We suggest to represent prudence and confidence to use the certimeter that was invented by Galileo and suggested by Frederic Pourbaix. There will be 2 certimeters, one for the confidence (mean certitude of correct answers) and one for prudence (100 − mean certitude of incorrect answers), see figure 6. Both certimeter will be graduated from 0% to 100%. Suggested colors might be from red to light red between 0% and 50% and from light green to green from 50% to 100%. Including prudence and confidence we offer a possible answer to ORT rec- ommendation30 : “The idea of confidence degree [. . . ] and may have the form of points in the game, which will bring the pupils to think further about their answer and will bring additional anticipation.” The aim of the player will be to reach green level score on both certimeter meaning that Galileo can trust him when he says that he is confident or when he says that he doubt. Of course to make the “eclipse machine” work the player will have to gain knowledge and comprehension of optic physics and astronomy. But the player should also pay attention to some metacognitive aspects: confidence and prudence. If the player fails to gain Galileo’s trust but manage to get the “eclipse machine” working he will gain access to the Galilean’s secret headquarters and to the book. But maybe Galileo will be a bit reluctant to help the player using the book. . . and give him a feedback in that way, unless the player starts the game all over again and tries to improve his score on both certimeter. Success in the game could 30 Hirschberg, G. (2007) DELIVERABLE Name: Phase 1 – Validation Report 15
  • 16. Figure 6: Rough design of a possible way to communicate to the player the level of Galileo’s trust gained: the cursor on each certimeter takes the color of the position in the color grada- tion. Both cursor must be at least light green to gain Galileo’s trust. then be achieved by reaching the Galilean’s HQ. But another level of success will be to reach HQ and to gain Galileo’s trust. 5.5 Realistic use of certitude degrees The feedbacks could take the form described in this algorithm here after. The limit values of 50% used in this alogrithm should be variables. Four limits are to be created and defined at a default level of 50 conf-lim-ccd the limit to judge a single judgement with a correct answer or the limit to be declared confident in a single judgment prud-lim-ccd the limit to judge a single judgment with an incorrect answer or the limit to be declared prudent in a single judgment mcdca-lim the limit to judge the mean certitude degree for correct answer as good or not or when is the player confident or not in the game so far mcdia-lim the limit to judge the mean certitude degree for incorrect answer as good or not or when is the player prudent or not in the game so far Every situation is symbolized by a group in between brackets (e.g., F + -). • First with a letter F for failure in case of an unsuccessful try S for success in case of a successful try 16
  • 17. • a plus (+) or (-) sign + if the chosen confidence degree is above 50% - if the chosen confidence degree is below 50% • a plus (+) or (-) sign + if the mean confidence degree is above 50% - if the mean confidence degree is below 50% ccd (chosen certitude degree) : matrix; mcdca (mean certitude degree of correct answers) : integer; mcdia (mean certitude degree of incorrect answers) : integer; print When I asked you how confident you were about succeeding this task, you told me you were {ccd}% confident succeeding it. If (FAILURE) then If (ccd > 50) then If (mcdia > 50) then print Situation A (F + +) else print Situation B (F + -) end If else If (mcdia ≤ 50) then print Situation C (F - -) else print Situation D (F - +) end If end If else If (ccd ≤ 50) then If (mcdca > 50) then print Situation E (S - +) else print Situation F (S - -) end If else If (mcdca ≤ 50) then print Situation G (S + -) else print Situation H (S + +) end If end If end If 17
  • 18. 5.5.1 Situation A (F + +) Situation: Test unsuccessful, confident in answer, tend to be overconfident when wrong. Feedback: You did not succeed. And you were very confident you would succeed. So you’ve made a bad assumption. You should be more careful in your estimations. When you failed you tend to choose a too high certitude degree. So when you fail your average prudence is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that it should be over {mcdia-lim}%. You should try to be less confident when you choose a certitude degree. You should learn to be a bit more modest and humble. You tend to believe you know when you’re still learning. So give it another try. A try to be more modest if you doubt, even a little. 5.5.2 Situation B (F + -) Situation: Test unsuccessful, confident in answer, tend to be prudent when wrong. Feedback: You did not succeed. You were very confident you would succeed. So you made a bad assumption but I consider this assumption as an accident. Usually you seem prudent in your own estimations. Every time you’ve failed you’ve chosen before a low certitude degree. So when you fail your prudence is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that it should be over {mcdia-lim}% so I trust your judgement. Keep going like that when you choose a certitude degree and maybe go back to the table for some more experimentation. 5.5.3 Situation C (F - -) Situation: Test unsuccessful, prudent in answer, tend to be prudent when wrong. Feedback: You did not succeed. But you certitude in your ability to succeed was low: you were prudent. So your assumption was good: you have failed but you knew it was risky so you associated doubt with your try. I congratulate you for that. It is important for me to know if I can trust you. In case case of course you’ve failed but before failing you told me that you were not sure. And as usual when you say that you’re not sure you do not succeed. So this failure is not important at all. It seems you’re quite good at being prudent: usually when you’ve failed you’ve chosen before a low certitude degree. So when you fail your overall prudence is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that it should be over {mcdia-lim}%. That is a good performance. Continue to do so and I will keep my trust in your judgments. But you still need to succeed this task: give it another try. 5.5.4 Situation D (F - +) Situation: Test unsuccessful, prudent in answer, tend to be overconfident when wrong. Feedback: You did not succeed. But this time your assumption was good: you have failed but you knew it was risky so you associated doubt with your try. I congratulate you for that. You should continue to behave like that because it does not appear you’re very skilled at this on the long run. For instance, when you fail your average prudence is {100-mcdia}%. I consider that it should be 18
  • 19. over {mcdia-lim}%. That is why I said you’re not very skilled. With such a value I will wait for you to improve before fully trusting your judgement. Maybe you should go back to the table for some more experimentation before giving it another try. And do not forget to keep going like you just did in giving your confidence. 5.5.5 Situation E (S - +) Situation: Test successful, prudent in answer, tend to be confident when right. Feedback: To be completed 5.5.6 Situation F (S - -) Situation: Test successful, prudent in answer, tend to be under confident when right. Feedback: To be completed 5.5.7 Situation G (S + -) Situation: Test successful, confident in answer, tend to be under confident when right. Feedback: To be completed 5.5.8 Situation H (S + +) Situation: Test successful, confident in answer, tend to be confident when right. Feedback: To be completed 5.6 Even more complex feedbacks It will really be enjoying for the player to hear the same long feedback. We suggest that all these information should be delivered not at once but over a number of tries. Counter of try and counters of times being in the same situation (e.g., F + - or S + +) should be implemented into the if–then–else loops. So the first time the player is in situation A he will received a more simple feedback but the second time he will receive a different feedback. It will be only after number of correct or incorrect answers that the computed mean values will have any meaning and so can be given to the player. Prudence and confidence can already have significant values computed on 55 value of certitude chosen by the player if we had the suggested game situation into the tutorial. 6 Certitude degrees in LU1.2b The Labset proposition for Elektra learning situation 1.2b (the slope) is similar to what we propose for learning situation 1.2a (the blinds) : every time George wants to release a marble he is asked his confidence in reaching the target on a scale from 0% to 100% by step of 20%. We suggest that beneath to the cursors for the magnet and the fan a third cursor with “confidence to reach the target” record the confidence associated with each try. Feedbacks will be less systematic 19
  • 20. as the player/learner should be more aware of his confidence score showed in the certimeter. When the player successfully dropped all 3 balls in the basket Galileo will ask him a transfer question. The player will have to chose out of a number a drawings the one that will represent the trajectory of light when turned on. He will also be asked about his confidence. Imagine they are only 4 drawing to choose from and the player knows that if he fails he can immediately try again. Without confidence degrees the player may try any of the 4 propositions until he finds the right one. But with confidence degrees he knows that if he chooses a wrong one and is confident in his guessing he will loose some of Galileo’s trust. So he might know the right solution, be confident and then will answer with a high confidence degree. He also may guess the right solution but then the chosen certitude should be lower. If guessing all proposition until he finds the correct one, all confidence will be low31 . So teacher will have information on how did the student reached transfer. 7 The tutorial for certitude degrees ORT recommended32 that “The idea of confidence degree should be explained in the beginning of the game (tutorial)”. The player will receive some explications about the Galileans. It is at that moment that certitude degrees should be ex- plained. We propose a theoretical information based on transmission–reception and a gaming situation similar to experimentation–reactivity. The tutorial should include 1. the player should gain the trust of Galileo Galilei 2. Galileo’s trust is based on the fact the when someone says “I know” he can trust that knowledge. And when someone doubt that person is right to doubt. 3. To gain Galileo trust everytime the player will experiment to solve an enigma he will be asked how confident he his that he will succeed resolving the enigma at this exact moment, on this precise try. 4. To indicate his self-confidence the player will chose one certitude degree between 0%, 20%, 40%, 60%, 80% and 100%. Points will be gained and lost based on • if what the player just tried is successful and – if he has chosen a high certitude degree he will gain confidence points – if he has chosen a low confidence degree he will loose confidence points • else if what the player just tried is unsuccessful and – if he has chosen a high certitude degree he will loose prudence points – if he has chosen a low confidence degree he will gain prudence points 31 with the limitation that certitude will go up as the number of possible answers goes down. 32 Hirschberg, G. (2007) DELIVERABLE Name: Phase 1 – Validation Report 20
  • 21. 5. In other word if the player bet 100% on a try and if that try is • successful then he will gain a lot of confidence points • unsuccessful then he will loose a lot of prudence points 6. On the other hand if the player bet 0% on a try and if that try is • successful then he will loose a lot of confidence points • unsuccessful then he will gain a lot of prudence points We suggest that this “theoretical” explanation is to be followed with a Gaming Situation based on betting certitude degrees. This might be something like the Shannon Guessing Game (1951)33 or another gaming situation that UL will provide. 7.1 Shannon’s guessing game “The new method of estimating entropy exploits the fact that anyone speaking a language possesses, implicitly, an enormous knowledge of the statistics of the language. Familiarity with the words, idioms, cliches and grammar enables him to fill in missing or incorrect letters in proof-reading, or to complete an unfinished phrase in conversation. An experimental demonstration of the extent to which English is predictable can be given as follows; Select a short passage unfamiliar to the person who is to do the predicting, He is then asked to guess the first letter in the passage. If the guess is correct he is so informed, and proceeds to guess the second letter. If not, he is told the correct first letter and proceeds to his next guess. This is continued through the text. As the experiment progresses, the subject writes down the correct text up to the current point for use in predicting future letters.” Gilles & Leclercq (1994) 34 have adapted this game to train student to use certitude degrees: each time a letter is chosen a certitude for it being the right next letter in the sentence is asked. Metacognitive indices like realism are computed and a graphical representation of the confidence in retrieved answer is drawn. The student tries to find the text and to score well in metacognitive judgment. In elektra the passage might be a simple phrase like The secret book of the Galileans is in the third drawer of the desk. The player will face an empty parchment that will be filled with letters written by a 3D feather when the player types a letter and a certitude degree. If the letter is incorrect it will burn, disappear and be replaced by the correct letter. Prudence and confidence will be computed and a metacognitive feedback will be generated. Then the player is to guess the next letter and so on. 7.2 Tutorial for teacher We also suggest that informations about metacognition and certitude degrees should be available for teachers. These informations should cover a wide domain, from objectives in the elektra game to proposition of reflection path about 33 Shannon, C. E. (1951) Prediction and entropy in printed English, Bell Syst. Tech. J., 30, 1951, 50-64 34 Leclercq, D. & Gilles, J.-L. (1994). GUESS, un logiciel pour entraˆ ıner ` l’auto-estimation a de sa comp´tence cognitive. Actes du colloque QCM et questionnaires ferm´s, Paris: ISIEE e e 21
  • 22. metacognition in classroom and support to further metacognitive activities for the students. 8 Conclusion Knowing how to learn, and knowing which strategies work best, are valuable skills that differentiate expert learners from novice learners. Metacognition, or awareness of the process of learning, is a critical ingredient to successful learning. “Metacognition is an important concept in cognitive theory. It consists of two basic processes occurring simultaneously: monitoring your progress as you learn, and making changes and adapting your strategies if you perceive you are not doing so well” (Winn, W. & Snyder, D., 1998).35 Contents 1 Why certitude degrees in learning? 1 2 What is metacognition? 2 2.1 Metacognition in general . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2 2.2 Certitude degrees and metacognition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4 2.3 Metacognition in the demonstrator . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4 2.3.1 What is a JOL? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5 2.3.2 JOL or confidence in retrieved answer . . . . . . . . . . . 5 3 Metacognition in games 6 4 About the demonstrator, 2006 version 7 4.1 A surprise . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7 4.2 General comments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8 4.3 Experiment in world 2 and metacognition . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9 4.4 The metal-wooden door and the blinds . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 5 Deeper with certitude degree 10 5.1 Theoretical background . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11 5.2 Application in the game . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 5.3 Technical implementation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 5.4 Graphic interface . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 5.5 Realistic use of certitude degrees . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 5.5.1 Situation A (F + +) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 35 Winn, W. & Snyder D. (1996). Cognitive perspectives in pyschology. In D.H. Jonassen, ed. Handbook of research for educational communications and technology, 112-142. New York: Simon & Schuster Macmillan 22
  • 23. 5.5.2 Situation B (F + -) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 5.5.3 Situation C (F - -) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 5.5.4 Situation D (F - +) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 5.5.5 Situation E (S - +) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 5.5.6 Situation F (S - -) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 5.5.7 Situation G (S + -) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 5.5.8 Situation H (S + +) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 5.6 Even more complex feedbacks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 6 Certitude degrees in LU1.2b 19 7 The tutorial for certitude degrees 20 7.1 Shannon’s guessing game . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21 7.2 Tutorial for teacher . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21 8 Conclusion 22 List of Tables 1 Flashlight on–off switch enhanced with certitude degree . . . . 10 2 Feedback class associated with the combination of true-false and confidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 3 Exemple for the computation of confidence and imprudence (C for correct answer and I for Incorrect answer). . . . . . . . . . . . 14 List of Figures 1 Main components of metacognitive monitoring and metacognitive control defined by Nelson (1996) and Nelson & Narens (1994) . . 3 2 Cut scene from the elektra demonstrator, 2006 . . . . . . . . . 7 3 Spectral distributions of Hunt’s three situations of knowledge (1993) 11 4 Spectral distribution of knowledge kinds by Jans & Leclercq (1999) based on Hunt’s three situation of knowledge . . . . . . . . . . . 12 5 Leclercq’s (2003) spectral splitting of Jans & Leclercq’s (1999) unusable knowledge . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12 6 Rough design of a possible way to communicate to the player the level of Galileo’s trust gained: the cursor on each certimeter takes the color of the position in the color gradation. Both cursor must be at least light green to gain Galileo’s trust. . . . . . . . . . . . 16 23