SlideShare una empresa de Scribd logo
1 de 42
Descargar para leer sin conexión
Theory in Anthropology since the Sixties
Author(s): Sherry B. Ortner
Source: Comparative Studies in Society and History, Vol. 26, No. 1 (Jan., 1984), pp. 126-166
Published by: Cambridge University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/178524
Accessed: 15/04/2010 21:25

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.




                Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
                Comparative Studies in Society and History.




http://www.jstor.org
Theory in Anthropology
since the Sixties
SHERRY          B. ORTNER

Universityof Michigan


Every year, aroundthe time of the meetings of the AmericanAnthropological
Association, the New YorkTimes asks a Big Name anthropologist contrib-
                                                                     to
ute an op-ed piece on the state of the field. These pieces tend to take a rather
gloomy view. A few years ago, for example, Marvin Harrissuggested that
anthropologywas being taken over by mystics, religious fanatics, and Cal-
ifornia cultists; that the meetings were dominatedby panels on shamanism,
witchcraft,and "abnormalphenomena";and that "scientific papersbased on
empirical studies" had been willfully excluded from the program (Harris
1978). More recently, in a more sober tone, Eric Wolf suggestedthatthe field
of anthropologyis coming apart. The sub-fields (and sub-sub-fields)are in-
creasingly pursuingtheir specialized interests, losing contact with each other
and with the whole. There is no longer a shared discourse, a shared set of
termsto which all practitioners  addressthemselves, a sharedlanguagewe all,
however idiosyncratically, speak (Wolf 1980).
   The state of affairsdoes seem much as Wolf describesit. The field appears
to be a thing of shredsand patches, of individualsand small coteries pursuing
disjunctiveinvestigations and talking mainly to themselves. We do not even
hear stirringargumentsany more. Although anthropologywas never actually
unified in the sense of adoptinga single sharedparadigm,there was at least a
period when there were a few large categories of theoreticalaffiliation, a set
of identifiablecamps or schools, and a few simple epithets one could hurl at

This essay contains much of my own intellectual history. There will be no more appropriate
context in which to thank my teachers, Frederica de Laguna, Clifford Geertz, and David
Schneiderfor having turnedme, for betteror for worse, into an anthropologist. addition,I wish
                                                                            In
to thankthe following friends and colleagues for helpful contributions the developmentof this
                                                                     to
essay: Nancy Chodorow, Salvatore Cucchiari, James Fernandez,Raymond Grew, Keith Hart,
RaymondKelly, David Kertzer, RobertPaul, Paul Rabinow, Joyce Riegelhaupt,Anton Weiler,
and HarrietWhitehead. Parts of this work were presentedat the Departmentof Anthropology,
Princeton University; the Departmentof Social Anthropology, University of Stockholm; the
Social Science History Seminar(founded and coordinatedby Charlesand Louise Tilly), Univer-
sity of Michigan;the HumanitiesSeminar, StanfordUniversity;and the Seminaron Theory and
Methods in ComparativeStudies (coordinatedby Neil Smelser) at the Universityof California,
Berkeley. I received valuable comments and reactions in all of these contexts.
0010-4175/84/1709-0100 $2.50 ? 1984 Society for ComparativeStudy of Society and History

                                           126
THEORY     IN   ANTHROPOLOGY         SINCE    THE    SIXTIES    127


one's opponents. Now there appears to be an apathy of spirit even at this
level. We no longer call each other names. We are no longer sure of how the
sides are to be drawnup, and of where we would place ourselves if we could
identify the sides.
   Yet as anthropologistswe can recognize in all of this the classic symptoms
of liminality-confusion of categories, expressions of chaos and antistruc-
ture. And we know that such disordermay be the breedinggroundfor a new
and perhapsbetterorder. Indeed, if one scrutinizesthe presentmore closely,
one may even discern within it the shape of the new orderto come. That is"
what I propose to do in this article. I will argue that a new key symbol of
theoretical orientation is emerging, which may be labeled "practice" (or
 "action" or "praxis"). This is neither a theory nor a method in itself, but
rather, as I said, a symbol, in the name of which a variety of theories and
methods are being developed. In order to understand significance of this
                                                      the
trend, however,    we must go back at least twenty years and see where we
startedfrom, and how we got to where we are now.
   Before launching this enterprise, however, it is importantto specify its
nature. This essay will be primarily concerned with the relations between
various theoretical schools or approaches,both within periods of time, and
across time. No single approachwill be exhaustivelyoutlinedor discussed in
itself; rather,variousthemes or dimensionsof each will be highlightedinsofar
as they relateto the largertrendsof thoughtwith which I am concerned.Every
anthropologistwill probablyfind his or her favorite school oversimplified,if
not outrightdistorted, insofar as I have choosen to emphasizefeaturesthatdo
not correspondto what are normallytaken, among the practitioners,to be its
most importanttheoretical features. Thus readers seeking more exhaustive
discussions of particular approaches,and/or discussionspursuedfrom a point
of view more interior to the approaches, will have to seek elsewhere. The
concern here, again, is with elucidating relations.

THE SIXTIES:    SYMBOL,    NATURE,     STRUCTURE

Although there is always some arbitrariness choosing a startingpoint for
                                               in
any historicaldiscussion, I have decided to begin in the early 1960s. For one
thing, that is when I started in the field, and since I generally assume the
importanceof seeing any system, at least in part, from the actor's point of
view, I might as well unite theory and practicefrom the outset. It is thus fully
acknowledgedthatthis discussion proceedsnot from some hypotheticalexter-
nal point, but from the perspective of this particularactor moving through
anthropologybetween 1960 and the present.
  But actors always wish to claim universalityfor theirparticular  experiences
and interpretations.I would further suggest then that, in some relatively
objective sense, there was in fact a majorset of revolutionsin anthropological
theory, beginning in the early sixties. Indeed it appearsthat such revisionist
128    SHERRY        B.   ORTNER


upheaval was characteristicof many other fields in that era. In literarycrit-
icism, for example,
by the 1960'sa volatilemixture linguistics,
                               of            psychoanalysis semiotics,struc-
                                                           and
turalism,Marxist       and
                theory reception    aesthetics begun replace oldermoral
                                              had      to       the
humanism. literary
            The        text tendedto move towards statusof phenomenon:
                                                   the                      a
                             and
socio-psycho-culturo-linguisticideological event,arisingfromtheoffered compe-
tenciesof language, available
                   the          taxonomies narrative
                                           of         order,the permutations
                                                                           of
                     optionsof structural
genre,the sociological                             the
                                         formation, ideological   constraints
                                                                           of
the infra-structure.. . . [There was a] broad and contentious revisionist perception
        1981:137).
(Bradbury
   In anthropologyat the close of the fifties, the theoreticalbricoleur's kit
consisted of threemajor, and somewhatexhausted,paradigms-British struc-
tural-functionalism  (descended from A. R. Radcliffe-Brownand Bronislaw
Malinowski),   Americanculturaland psychocultural   anthropology (descended
from MargaretMead, Ruth Benedict, et al.), and Americanevolutionist an-
thropology (centered around Leslie White and Julian Steward, and having
strong affiliations with archaeology). Yet it was also during the fifties that
certain actors and cohorts central to our story were trainedin each of these
areas. They emerged at the beginning of the sixties with aggressive ideas
abouthow to strengthenthe paradigmsof their mentorsand ancestors,as well
as with, apparently,much more combativestancesvis-a-vis the otherschools.
It was this combination of new ideas and intellectual aggressiveness that
launched the three movements with which this account begins: symbolic
anthropology,culturalecology, and structuralism.

SymbolicAnthropology
"Symbolic anthropology" as a label was never used by any of its main
proponentsin the formativeperiod-say, 1963-66. Ratherit was a shorthand
tag (probablyinventedby the opposition), an umbrellafor a numberof rather
diverse trends. Two of its major variantsappearto have been independently
invented, one by Clifford Geertz and his colleagues at the University of
Chicago, and the other by Victor Turner at Cornell.' The importantdif-
ferences between the Geertzians and the Turneriansare probably not fully
appreciated by those outside the symbolic anthropology scene. Whereas
Geertz was primarilyinfluencedby Max Weber (via TalcottParsons),Turner
was primarilyinfluenced by Emile Durkheim.Further,Geertz clearly repre-
sents a transformationupon the earlier American anthropologyconcerned
mainly with the operationsof "culture," while Turnerrepresentsa transfor-

    For the discussion of the sixties and the seventies, I will for the most partinvoke only the
most representativefigures and works. In an articleof this length, many interestingdevelopments
must be by-passed. One importantfigure of this period who gets left by the wayside is Gregory
Bateson (e.g., 1972), who, though himself clearly a powerful and original thinker,never really
founded a major school in anthropology.
THEORY         IN   ANTHROPOLOGY               SINCE     THE     SIXTIES       I29

mation upon the earlierBritish anthropologyconcernedmainly with the oper-
ations of "society."
   Geertz's most radicaltheoreticalmove (1973b) was to arguethat cultureis
not something locked inside people's heads, but ratheris embodiedin public
symbols, symbols throughwhich the membersof a society communicatetheir
worldview, value-orientations,ethos, and all the rest to one another,to future
generations-and to anthropologists.With this formulation,Geertz gave the
hithertoelusive concept of culture a relatively fixed locus, and a degree of
objectivity, that it did not have before. The focus on symbols was for Geertz
and many others heuristicallyliberating:it told them where to find what they
wanted to study. Yet the point about symbols was that they were ultimately
vehicles for meanings;the study of symbols as such was never an end in itself.
Thus, on the one hand, Geertzians2have never been particularly      interestedin
distinguishing  and cataloguingthe varietiesof symbolic types (signals, signs,
icons, indexes, etcetera-see, in contrast, Singer 1980); nor, on the other
hand (and in contrastwith Turnerto whom we will get in a moment), have
they been particularly   interestedin the ways in which symbols performcertain
practicaloperations    in the social process-heal people throughcuring rites,
turn boys and girls into men and women through initiation, kill people
throughsorcery-and so forth. Geertziansdo not ignore these practicalsocial
effects, but such symbols have not been their primary focus of interest.
Rather, the focus of Geertziananthropologyhas consistently been the ques-
tion of how symbols shape the ways social actors see, feel, and think about
the world, or, in other words, how symbols operateas vehicles of "'culture."
   It is furtherworth noting, in anticipationof the discussion of structuralism,
that Geertz's heart has always been more with the "ethos" side of culture
than with the "worldview," more with the affective and stylistic dimensions
than with the cognitive. While of course it is very difficult (not to say unpro-
ductive and ultimately wrong-headed)to separatethe two too sharply, it is
nonetheless possible to distinguishan emphasis on one or the other side. For
Geertz, then (as for Benedict, especially, before him), even the most cogni-
tive or intellectualof culturalsystems-say, the Balinese calendars-are ana-
lyzed not (only) to lay bare a set of cognitive orderingprinciples, but (es-
pecially) to understandhow the Balinese way of chopping up time stamps
their sense of self, of social relations, and of conduct with a particularcultur-
ally distinctive flavor, an ethos (1973e).3
   2 E.g., Ortner 1975; M. Rosaldo 1980; Blu 1980; Meeker 1979; Rosen 1978.
   3 If culture itself had been an elusive phenomenon, one may say that Geertz has pursuedthe
most elusive partof it, the ethos. It may also be suggested thatthis, among otherthings, accounts
for his continuing and broad-basedappeal. Perhaps the majorityof students who go into an-
thropology, and almost certainly the majorityof nonanthropologists      who are fascinatedby our
field, are drawn to it because they have been struck at some point in their experience by the
"otherness" of anotherculture, which we would call its ethos. Geertz's workprovidesone of the
very few handles for grasping that otherness.
I30   SHERRY     B.   ORTNER


   The othermajorcontribution the Geertzianframework
                                 of                           was the insistence
on studyingculture "from the actor'spoint of view" (e.g., 1975). Again, this
does not imply that we must get "into people's heads." What it means, very
simply, is thatcultureis a productof acting social beings tryingto make sense
of the world in which they find themselves, and if we are to make sense of a
culture, we must situate ourselves in the position from which it was con-
structed. Culture is not some abstractlyordered system, deriving its logic
from hidden structuralprinciples, or from special symbols that provide the
 "keys" to its coherence. Its logic-the principles of relations that obtain
among its elements-derives ratherfrom the logic or organizationof action,
from people operating within certain institutionalorders, interpretingtheir
situations in order to act coherently within them (1973d). It may be noted
here, however, that while the actor-centeredperspective is fundamentalto
Geertz's framework,it is not systematicallyelaborated:     Geertzdid not devel-
op  a theory of action or practice as such. He did, however, firmly plant the
actor at the center of his model, and much of the laterpractice-centered   work
builds on a Geertzian(or Geertzo-Weberian)      base,  as we shall see.
   The othermajorfigure in the Chicago school of symbolic anthropology       has
been David Schneider. Schneider, like Geertz, was a productof Parsons,and
he too concentratedprimarilyon refining the cultureconcept. But his efforts
went toward understandingthe internal logic of systems of symbols and
meanings, by way of a notion of "core symbols," and also by way of ideas
akin to ClaudeLevi-Strauss'sconcept of structure    (e.g., 1968, 1977). Indeed,
although   Geertz prominentlyused the phrase "cultural system" (emphasis
added), he never paid much attentionto the systemic aspectsof culture,and it
was Schneider who developed this side of the problem much more fully.
Schneider in his own work cut culture off from social action much more
radically than Geertz did. Yet, perhaps precisely because social action
("practice," "praxis") was so radically separated from "culture" in
Schneider'swork, he and some of his studentswere among the earliestof the
symbolic anthropologiststo see practice itself as a problem (Barnett 1977;
Dolgin, Kemnitzer, and Schneider 1977).
   Victor Turner, finally, comes out of quite a different intellectual back-
ground. He was trained in the Max Gluckmanvariantof British structural-
functionalism,which was influencedby Marxism,and which stressedthatthe
normalstate of society is not one of solidarityand harmoniousintegrationof
parts, but ratherone of conflict and contradiction.Thus, the analyticquestion
was not, as for the straightline descendantsof Durkheim, how solidarityis
fine-tuned, reinforced, and intensified, but ratherhow it is constructedand
maintainedin the first place over and above the conflicts and contradictions
that constitute the normal state of affairs. To the Americanreader,this may
appearto be only a minor varianton the basic functionalistproject, since for
both schools the emphasis is on the maintenanceof integration,and specifi-
THEORY        IN   ANTHROPOLOGY               SINCE     THE     SIXTIES      131


cally on the maintenanceof the integrationof "society"-actors, groups, the
social whole-as opposed to "culture." But Gluckman and his students
(includingTurner)believed their differences from the mainstream be quite
                                                                    to
deep. Moreover, they always constituteda minoritywithin the British estab-
lishment. This backgroundmay account in partfor Turner'soriginalityvis-a-
vis his compatriots,leading ultimatelyto his independentlyinventinghis own
brandof an explicitly symbolic anthropology.
   Despite the relative novelty of Turner'smove to symbols, however, thereis
in his work a deep continuity with British social anthropologicalconcerns,
and, as a result, profounddifferences between Tumerianand Geertziansym-
bolic anthropology.For Turner,symbols are of interestnot as vehicles of, and
analytic windows onto, "culture"-the integratedethos and worldview of a
society-but as what might be called operators in the social process, things
that, when put togetherin certainarrangements certaincontexts (especially
                                                in
rituals), produceessentially  social transformations.Thus, symbols in Ndem-
bu curingor initiationor huntingritualsare investigatedfor the ways in which
they move actors from one status to another, resolve social contradictions,
and wed actorsto the categories and normsof their society (1967). Along the
way toward these rather traditional structural-functional     goals, however,
Turneridentified or elaboratedupon certainritual mechanisms, and some of
the concepts he developed have become indispensablepartsof the vocabulary
of ritualanalysis-liminality, marginality,antistructure,  communitas,and so
forth (1967, 1969).4
   Turnerand the Chicago symbolic anthropologistsdid not so much conflict
with one anotheras simply, for the most part, talk past one another.Yet the
Turnerians5  added an important,and characteristically  British, dimension to
the field of symbolic anthropologyas a whole, a sense of the pragmatics of
symbols. They investigated in much more detail than Geertz, Schneider, et
al., the "effectiveness of symbols," the questionof how symbols actuallydo
what all symbolic anthropologistsclaim they do: operate as active forces in
the social process (see also Levi-Strauss 1963; Tambiah 1968; Lewis 1977;
Fernandez 1974).
   In retrospect, one may say that symbolic anthropologyhad a numberof
significant limitations. I refer not to the charges that it was unscientific,
mystical, literary, soft-headed, and the like leveled at it by practitionersof
culturalecology (see below). Rather, one may point to symbolic anthropol-
   4 Anotherpoint of contrastbetween Turnerand Geertz is thatTurner's
                                                                         concept of meaning, at
least in those early works that launchedhis approach,is largely referential.Meanings are things
that symbols point to or refer to, like "matriliny" or "blood." Geertz, on the other hand, is
primarilyconcernedwith what might be called Meaning, with a capitalM-the purpose,or point,
or largersignificance of things. Thus he quotes NorthropFrye: "You wouldn't go to Macbethto
learnaboutthe history of Scotland-you go to it to learnwhat a man feels like afterhe's gained a
kingdom and lost his soul" (Geertz 1973f:450).
   5 E.g., Munn 1969; Myerhoff 1974; Moore and
                                                    Myerhoff 1975; Babcock 1978.
132    SHERRY       B.   ORTNER


ogy's lack, especially in its American form, of a systematic sociology; its
underdeveloped sense of the politics of culture; and its lack of curiosity
concerning the production and maintenance of symbolic systems. These
points will be discussed more fully in the course of this article.
CulturalEcology6
Culturalecology representeda new synthesis of, and a furtherdevelopment
upon, the materialistevolutionismof Leslie White (1943, 1949), JulianStew-
ard (1953, 1955), and V. Gordon Childe (1942). Its roots go back to Lewis
HenryMorganand E. B. Tylor in the nineteenthcentury, and ultimatelyback
to Marx and Engels, although many of the 1950s evolutionists, for under-
standable political reasons, were not encouraged to emphasize the Marxist
connection.7
   White had been investigating what came to be labeled "general evolu-
tion," or the evolution of culture-in-general,in terms of stages of social
complexity and technological advancement.These stages were subsequently
refinedby Elman Service (1958), and by MarshallSahlins and ElmanService
(1960), into the famous bands-tribes-chiefdoms-states      scheme. The evolu-
tionary mechanisms in White's frameworkderived from more or less for-
tuitous events: technological inventionsthat allowed for the greater "capture
of energy," and populationgrowth (and perhapswarfareand conquest) that
stimulatedthe developmentof more complex forms of social/political organi-
zation and coordination.Steward(1953) attackedboth the focus on the evolu-
tion of culture-in-general opposed to specific cultures), and the lack of a
                           (as
more systematically operative evolutionarymechanism. Instead, he empha-
sized that specific culturesevolve their specific forms in the process of adapt-
ing to specific environmentalconditions, and that the apparentuniformityof
                                                                to
evolutionarystages is actually a matterof similaradaptations similarnatu-
ral conditions in different parts of the world.
   If the idea thatculturewas embodied in public, observablesymbols was the
key to the liberationof symbolic anthropologyfrom earlierAmericancultural
anthropology,the concept that played a similar role in culturalecology was
"adaptation." (See Alland 1975 for a summary.) Just as Geertz had trum-
peted that the study of culture as embodied in symbols removedthe problem
of getting inside people's heads, so Sahlins proclaimedthe focus on adapta-
tion to environmentalfactors as the way aroundsuch amorphousfactors as
cultural gestalten and historical dialectics (1964). There was a large-scale
rejection of the study of the inner workings of both culturein the American
sense and society in the British sense. Internaldynamicswere seen as hardto
 6 This section is partly based on readings, partly on semiformalinterviews with ConradP.
Kottak and Roy A. Rappaport, and partly on general discussions with Raymond C. Kelly.
Absolution is extended to all of the informants.
 7 White and Childe were fairly explicit about the Marxist influence on their work.
THEORY        IN   ANTHROPOLOGY              SINCE     THE     SIXTIES      133

measure, and even harder to choose among for purposes of assigning causal
primacy, whereas external factors of natural and social environment were
amenable to treatment as fixed, measurable, "independent variables:"
For decades, centuries now, intellectual battle has been given over which sector of
culture is the decisive one for change. Many have entered the lists under banners
diverse. Curiously, few seem to fall. Leslie White championstechnologicalgrowthas
the sector most responsible for culturalevolution; Julian Huxley, with many others,
sees "man's view of destiny" as the deciding force; the mode of productionand the
class struggle are still very much in contention. Different as they are, these positions
agree in one respect, that the impulse to developmentis generatedfrom within ....
The case for internalcauses of developmentmay be bolsteredby pointingto a mecha-
nism, such as the Hegelian dialectic, or it may rest more insecurely on an argument
from logic. ... In any event, an unreal and vulnerableassumptionis always there,
that culturesare closed systems. . . . It is precisely on this point that culturalecology
offers a new perspective. . . . [I]t shifts attentionto the relationbetween inside and
outside; it envisions as the mainspringof the evolutionarymovement the interchange
between culture and environment.Now which view shall prevail is not to be decided
on a sheet of paper. . . . But if adaptationwins over inner dynamism, it will be for
certain intrinsic and obvious strengths. Adaptation is real, naturalistic, anchored
to those historic contexts of cultures that inner dynamism ignores (Sahlins
1964:135-36).8
   The Sahlins and Service version of cultural ecology, which was also ad-
hered to by the mainstream of the archaeology wing of anthropology, was still
fundamentally evolutionist. The primary use of the adaptation concept was in
explaining the development, maintenance, and transformation of social
forms. But there was another variant of cultural ecology, which developed
slightly later, and which came to dominate the materialist wing in the sixties.
Its position, expressed most forcefully by Marvin Harris (e.g., 1966) and
perhaps most elegantly by Roy Rappaport (1967), drew heavily on systems
theory. It shifted the analytic focus away from evolution, and toward explain-
ing the existence of particular bits of particular cultures in terms of the
adaptive or system-maintaining functions of those bits. Thus, the Maring
kaiko ritual prevented the degradation of the natural environment (Rappaport
1967), the Kwakiutl potlatch maintained a balance of food distribution over
tribal segments (Piddocke 1969), and the sacredness of the cow in India
protected a vital link in the agricultural food chain (Harris 1966). In these
studies, the interest has shifted from how the environment stimulates (or
prevents) the development of social and cultural forms to the question of the
ways in which social and cultural forms function to maintain an existing
relationship with the environment. It was these latter sorts of studies that came
to represent cultural ecology as a whole in the sixties.
   One would have had to be particularly out of touch with anthropological

   8 This was the programmatic
                             position. In practice, Sahlins did pay a good deal of attentionto
internal social dynamics.
134   SHERRY        B.   ORTNER


theory at the time not to have been awareof the acrimoniousdebate between
the culturalecologists and the symbolic anthropologists.  Whereasthe cultural
ecologists considered the symbolic anthropologiststo be fuzzy-headedmen-
talists, involved in unscientific and unverifiable flights of subjective in-
terpretation,the symbolic anthropologistsconsidered culturalecology to be
involved with mindless and sterile scientism, countingcalories and measuring
rainfall, and willfully ignoring the one truththat anthropologyhad presum-
ably establishedby that time: that culture mediates all humanbehavior. The
Manichean struggle between "materialism" and "idealism," "hard" and
"soft" approaches, interpretive "emics" and explanatory "etics," domi-
nated the field for a good part of the decade of the sixties, and in some
quarterswell into the seventies.
   That most of us thought and wrote in terms of such oppositions may be
partly rooted in more pervasive schemes of Western thought: subjective/
objective, nature/culture,mind/body, and so on. The practice of fieldwork
itself may furthercontributeto such thinking,based as it is on the paradoxical
injunctionto participateand observe at one and the same time. It may be then
that this sort of polarized construction of the intellectual landscape in an-
thropologyis too deeply motivated, by both culturalcategoriesand the forms
of practiceof the trade, to be completely eliminated. But the emic/etic strug-
gle of the sixties had a numberof unfortunate   effects, not the least of which
was the preventionof adequateself-criticismon both sides of the fence. Both
schools could luxuriatein the faults of the other, and not inspect their own
houses for seriousweaknesses. In fact, both sides were weak not only in being
unable to handle what the other side did (the symbolic anthropologistsin
renouncingall claims to "explanation," the culturalecologists in losing sight
of the frames of meaning within which humanaction takes place); both were
also weak in what neither of them did, which was much of any systematic
sociology.9
   Indeed, from the point of view of British social anthropology,the whole
American struggle was quite meaningless, since it seemed to leave out the
necessary central term of all proper anthropologicaldiscussion: society.
Where were the social groups, social relationships, social structures,social
institutions, that mediate both the ways in which people think ("culture")
and the ways in which people experienceand act upontheirenvironment?    But
this set of questions could not be answered (had anybody bothered to ask
them) in terms of British social anthropological
                                               categories, because the Brit-
ish were having their own intellectualupheavals, to which we will returnin
due course.



 9 The early Turneris a partialexception to this point, but most of his successors are not.
THEORY      IN   ANTHROPOLOGY         SINCE    THE    SIXTIES    135



Structuralism
Structuralism, the more-or-less single-handed invention of Claude Levi-
Strauss, was the only genuinely new paradigmto be developed in the sixties.
One might even say that it is the only genuinely original social science
paradigm(and humanitiestoo, for that matter)to be developed in the twen-
tieth century. Drawing on linguistics and communicationtheory, and consid-
ering himself influenced by both Marx and Freud, Levi-Straussarguedthat
the seemingly bewilderingvariety of social and culturalphenomenacould be
renderedintelligible by demonstratingthe sharedrelationshipsof those phe-
nomena to a few simple underlying principles. He sought to establish the
universal grammarof culture, the ways in which units of culturaldiscourse
are created(by the principleof binaryopposition), and the rules accordingto
which the units (pairs of opposed terms) are arrangedand combined to pro-
duce the actual cultural productions (myths, marriage rules, totemic clan
arrangements, the like) thatanthropologists
                and                                record.Culturesareprimarily
systems   of classification, as well as the sets of institutionaland intellectual
productionsbuilt upon those systems of classification and performingfurther
operations upon them. One of the most importantsecondary operationsof
culture in relation to its own taxonomies is precisely to mediate or reconcile
the oppositions which are the bases of those taxonomies in the first place.
   In practice, structuralanalysis consists of sifting out the basic sets of
oppositions that underlie some complex cultural phenomenon-a myth, a
ritual, a marriage system-and of showing the ways in which the phe-
nomenon in question is both an expression of those contrastsand a reworking
of them, therebyproducinga culturallymeaningfulstatementof, or reflection
upon, order. Even without the full analysis of a myth or ritual, however, the
sheer enumerationof the importantsets of oppositionsin a cultureis takento
be a useful enterprisebecause it reveals the axes of thought, and the limits of
the thinkable,within that andrelatedcultures(e.g., Needham 1973b). But the
fullest demonstrationof the power of structuralanalysis is seen in Levi-
Strauss's four-volume study, Mythologiques (1964-71). Here the method
allows the orderingof data both on a vast scale (includingmost of indigenous
South America, and partsof native North Americaas well), and also in terms
of explicating myriad tiny details-why the jaguar covers his mouth when
laughing or why honey metaphorsdescribe the escape of game animals. The
combinationof wide scope and minute detail is what lends the work its great
power.
   Much has been made of the point that Levi-Straussultimatelygroundsthe
structures discernsbeneathsociety and culturein the structure the mind.
           he                                                      of
Both the point itself, and the criticism of it, are perhapssomewhatirrelevant
for anthropologists. It seems incontrovertiblethat all humans, and all cul-
tures, classify. This suggests in turnan innatementalpropensityof some sort,
136    SHERRY        B.   ORTNER


but it does not mean that any particular    scheme of classificationis inevitable,
no more than the fact that all humanseat motivates some universalsystem of
food categories.
   The enduringcontributionof Levi-Straussianstructuralism in the per-
                                                                   lies
ception that luxuriantvariety, even apparent     randomness,may have a deeper
unity and systematicity, derived from the operation of a small number of
underlyingprinciples. It is in this sense that Levi-Straussclaims affinity with
Marx and Freud, who similarlyarguethatbeneaththe surfaceproliferation           of
forms, a few relatively simple and relatively uniformmechanismsare operat-
ing (DeGeorge and DeGeorge 1972). Such a perception,in turn, allows us to
distinguishmuch more clearly between simple transformations,        which operate
within a given structure,and real change, revolutionif you will, in which the
structureitself is transformed.Thus, despite the naturalisticor biologistic
base of structuralism,and despite Levi-Strauss's personal predilection for
considering that plus ca change, plus c'est la meme chose, the theory has
always had importantimplications for a much more historicaland/or evolu-
tionary anthropologythan that practiced by the master. The work of Louis
Dumont in particularhas developed some of these evolutionaryimplications
in analyzingthe structure the Indiancaste system, and in articulating
                             of                                              some
of the profound structuralchanges involved in the transitionfrom caste to
class (1965, 1970; see also Goldman 1970, Barnett 1977, Sahlins 1981).10
   Structuralism   was never all that popularamong Americananthropologists.
Although    it was seen at first (mostly by the culturalecologists) as a variantof
symbolic anthropology, its central assumptions were in fact ratherdistant
from those of the symbolic anthropologists(with the partialexception of the
Schneiderians).There were a numberof reasons for this, which can be only
very briefly sketched:(1) the very pure cognitive emphasisof Levi-Strauss's
notion of meaning, as againstthe Americans' interestin ethos and values; (2)
Levi-Strauss'sratheraustereemphasis on arbitrariness meaning (all mean-
                                                           of
ing  is established by contrasts, nothing carries any meaning in itself), as
against the Americans' interest in relations between the forms of symbolic
constructs and the contents for which they are vehicles;" and (3) the ex-
plicitly abstractlocus of structures,divorced in every way from the actions
and intentionsof actors, as against the symbolic anthropologists'fairly con-
sistent, if variably defined, actor-centrism(again, Schneider is a partialex-
ception to this point). For all these reasons, and probablymore, structuralism
was not as much embracedby American symbolic anthropologistsas might

  10 Dumont is anotherof those figures who deserve more space than can be affordedhere.
  11 This is not to
                    imply that Americansymbolic anthropologists
                                                              deny the doctrineof arbitrari-
ness of symbols. But they do insist that the choice of a particularsymbolic form among several
possible, equally arbitrary,symbols for the same conception, is not only not arbitrary, has
                                                                                      but
importantimplications that must be investigated.
THEORY        IN   ANTHROPOLOGY              SINCE      THE    SIXTIES      137


have appearedlikely at first glance.12 It was grantedwhat might be called
fictive kinship status, largely because of its tendency to focus on some of the
same domains that symbolic anthropologists      took as their own-myth, ritual,
etiquette, and so forth.
   The main impactof structuralism    outside of Francewas in England,among
some of the more adventurousBritish social anthropologists(see especially
Leach 1966). Levi-Straussand the British were in fact more truly kin to one
another,bornof two lines of descent from Durkheim.In any event, structural-
ism in the British context underwenta numberof important        transformations.
Avoiding    the question of mind, and of universal structures, British an-
thropologistsprimarilyapplied structuralanalysis to particularsocieties and
particularcosmologies (e.g., Leach 1966, 1969; Needham 1973a; Yalman
1969; the point also applies to Dumont (1970) in France). They also focused
in more detail on the process of mediation of oppositions, and produceda
number of quite original ruminationsupon anomaly and antistructure,es-
pecially Mary Douglas's Purity and Danger (see also Turner 1967, 1969;
Leach 1964; Tambiah 1969).
   However, there was also an importantway in which many of the British
purgedstructuralism one of its more radicalfeatures-the eradication the
                       of                                                 of
Durkheimiandistinctionbetween the social "base" and the cultural "reflec-
tion" of it. Levi-Strausshad claimed thatif mythic structures   paralleledsocial
structures,it was not because myth reflected society, but because both myth
and social organizationshared a common underlyingstructure.Many of the
British structuralists (Rodney Needham is the majorexception), on the other
hand, went back to a position more in the traditionof Durkheimand Marcel
Mauss, and considered myth and ritual as reflecting and resolving "at the
symbolic level" oppositions taken to be fundamentallysocial.'3 As long as
British structuralism confined to the study of myth andritual,then, it was
                       was
possible for it to fit nicely into British anthropologywithout having a very
profoundeffect upon it. It became their version of culturalor symbolic an-
thropology, their theory of superstructure. was only later, when a structural
                                             It
(i.e., structural-Marxist)  eye was turned on the British concept of social
structureitself, that the sparksbegan to fly.
   In a numberof fields-linguistics, philosophy, history-there was a strong
reaction against structuralismby the early seventies. Two interrelatedfea-
tures-the denial of the relevance of an intentionalsubject in the social and
   12 James Boon (e.g., 1972) has devoted a fair amount of effort to
                                                                       reconciling Levi-Strauss
and/or Schneideron the one side, with Geertz on the other. The outcome is generallyheavily in
favor of structuralism.(See also Boon and Schneider 1974.)
  13 Levi-Strauss himself movedfrom a Durkheim/Maussposition in "La Geste d'Asdiwal"
(1967) to the more radicalstructuralist
                                      position in Mythologiques.It is no accidentthatLeach, or
whoever made the decision, chose to present "La Geste d'Asdiwal" as the lead essay in the
British collection, The StructuralStudy of Myth and Totemism(1967).
138   SHERRY       B.    ORTNER


cultural process, and the denial of any significant impact of history or
 "event" upon structure-were felt to be particularly       problematic,not to say
unacceptable.  Scholars began to elaboratealternativemodels, in which both
agents and events played a more active role. These models did not, however,
get much play in anthropology until the late seventies, and they will be
discussed in the final section of the essay. In anthropology   duringmost of that
decade,  structuralism  itself, with all its flaws (and virtues), became the basis
of one of the dominantschools of theory, structural      Marxism.We move now
to that decade.

THE   SEVENTIES:        MARX

The anthropologyof the 1970s was much more obviously and transparently
tied to real-worldevents than that of the precedingperiod. Startingin the late
 1960s, in both the United States and France (less so in England), radical
social movements emerged on a vast scale. First came the counterculture,
then the antiwarmovement, and then, just a bit later, the women's movement:
these movements not only affected the academic world, they originatedin
good part within it. Everythingthat was part of the existing orderwas ques-
tioned and criticized. In anthropology,the earliest critiquestook the form of
denouncing the historical links between anthropologyon the one hand, and
colonialism and imperialismon the other (e.g., Asad 1973, Hymes 1974).
But this merely scratchedthe surface. The issue quickly moved to the deeper
question of the natureof our theoreticalframeworks,and especially the de-
gree to which they embody and carry forwardthe assumptionsof bourgeois
Western culture.
   The rallying symbol of the new criticism, and of the theoreticalalternatives
offered to replace the old models, was Marx. Of all the great nineteenth-
century antecedentsof moder social science, Marx had been conspicuously
absent from the mainstreamtheoreticalrepertoire.Parsons'sStructureof So-
cial Action, one of the sacred texts of the Harvard-trained      symbolic an-
thropologists, surveyed the thought of Durkheim and Weber, and of two
economic theorists, Alfred Marshalland Vilfredo Pareto,whose main signifi-
cance in that context seemed to be that they were Not Marx. The British,
including both the symbolic anthropologistsand the structuralists,   were still
firmly embeddedin Durkheim.Levi-Straussclaimed to have been influenced
by Marx, but it took a while for anyone to figure out what he meantby that.
Even the culturalecologists, the only self-proclaimedmaterialistsof the six-
ties, hardlyinvoked Marx at all; indeed MarvinHarrisspecifically repudiated
him (1968). One does not need to be an especially subtle analyst of the
ideological aspects of intellectual history to realize that the absence of a
significantMarxistinfluence before the seventies was just as much a reflex of
real-worldpolitics as was the emergence of a strongMarxistinfluence in the
seventies.
THEORY      IN   ANTHROPOLOGY         SINCE    THE    SIXTIES    I39


   There were at least two distinct Marxistschools of anthropological  theory:
structuralMarxism, developed mainly in France and England, and political
economy, which emerged first in the United States, and later in Englandas
well. There was also a movement that might be called cultural Marxism,
workedout largely in historicaland literarystudies, but this was not pickedup
by anthropologistsuntil recently, and will be addressedin the final section of
the essay.

Structural Marxism
Structural Marxismwas the only one of the schools developed entirelywithin
the field of anthropology,and probablyfor thatreasonwas also the earliestin
its impact. Within it, Marx was used to attackand/or rethink, or at the very
least to expand, virtually every theoretical scheme on the landscape-sym-
bolic anthropology,culturalecology, British social anthropology,and struc-
turalism itself. StructuralMarxism constituted a would-be total intellectual
revolution, and if it did not succeed in establishingitself as the only alterna-
tive to everything else we had, it certainly succeeded in shaking up most of
the received wisdom. This is not to say that it was necessarily the actual
writingsof the structural  Marxiststhemselves (e.g., Althusser1971; Godelier
1977; Terray 1972; Sahlins 1972; Friedman1975) that had this effect; it was
simply that structural  Marxismwas the originalforce within anthropology      for
promulgating   and legitimating "Marx," "Marxism," and "critical inquiry"
in the discourse of the field as a whole (see also Diamond 1979).
   The specific advance of structuralMarxism over its antecedentforms of
materialistanthropologylay in its locating the determinative    forces not in the
natural environment and/or in technology, but specifically within certain
structuresof social relations. Ecological considerationswere not excluded,
but they were encompassedby and subordinated the analysis of the social,
                                                    to
and especially political, organization of production. Culturalecology was
thus attacked as "vulgar materialism," reinforcingratherthan undoing the
classical capitalist fetishization of "things," the dominationof subjects by
objects ratherthan by the social relations embodied in, and symbolized by,
those objects (see especially Friedman1974). The critical social relationsin
question, referredto as the mode(s) of production,are not to be confusedwith
the surface organization of social relations traditionallystudied by British
social anthropologists-lineages, clans, moieties, and all the rest. These sur-
face forms of what the British called "social structure"are seen as native
models of social organizationthat have been boughtby anthropologists the   as
real thing, but that actually mask, or at least only partiallycorrespondto, the
hiddenasymmetricalrelationsof productionthataredrivingthe system. Here,
then, was situated the critique of traditionalBritish social anthropology(see
especially Bloch 1971, 1974, 1977; Terray 1975).
   In addition to critiquing and revising both cultural ecology and British
140   SHERRY     B.   ORTNER


social anthropology,structural    Marxiststurnedtheir attentionto culturalphe-
nomena. Unlike the culturalecologists, the structural  Marxistsdid not dismiss
cultural beliefs and native categories as irrelevantto the real or objective
operations of society, nor, alternatively, did they set about to show that
apparentlyirrationalcultural beliefs, such as the sacred cow, actually had
practical adaptive functions. Just as the New Left in the real world took
culturalissues (life style, consciousness) more seriouslythanthe Old Left had
done, so the structuralMarxists allocated to cultural phenomena (beliefs,
values, classifications)at least one centralfunctionin theirmodel of the social
process. Specifically, culture was convertedto "ideology," and considered
from the point of view of its role in social reproduction:legitimating the
existing order, mediating contradictions in the base, and mystifying the
sources of exploitationand inequalityin the system (O'Laughlin1974; Bloch
1977; Godelier 1977).
   One of the virtues of structural Marxism, then, was that there was a place
for everything in its scheme. Refusing to see inquiriesinto materialrelations
and into "ideology" as opposed enterprises, its practitionersestablished a
model in which the two "levels" were related to one anothervia a core of
social/political/economic processes. In this sense, they offered an explicit
mediation between the "materialist" and "idealist" camps of sixties an-
thropology. The mediation was rathermechanical, as we will discuss in a
moment, but it was there.
   More important,to my mind, the structural   Marxistsput a relativelypower-
ful sociology back into the picture. They cross-fertilizedBritish social an-
thropologicalcategories with Marxistones, and producedan expandedmodel
of social organization("mode of production")which they then proceededto
apply systematicallyto particular  cases. WhereasotherMarxismsemphasized
relations of political/economic organization ("production") almost ex-
clusively, the structuralMarxists were, after all, anthropologists,trainedto
pay attentionto kinship, descent, marriage,exchange, domesticorganization,
and the like. They thus includedthese elements within theirconsiderationsof
political and economic relations (often giving them a more Marxist ring by
calling them "relations of reproduction")and the total effect was to produce
rich and complex pictures of the social process in specific cases. Given the
relative paucity, mentioned earlier, of detailed sociological analysis in the
various sixties schools, this was an importantcontribution.
   All this having been said, one may nonetheless recognize that structural
Marxism had a number of problems. For one thing, the narrowingof the
culture concept to "ideology," which had the powerful effect of allowing
analysts to connect culturalconceptions to specific structuresof social rela-
tion, was too extreme, and posed the problem of relating ideology back to
more general conceptions of culture. For another, the tendency to see cul-
ture/ideology largely in terms of mystification gave most of the culturalor
THEORY      IN   ANTHROPOLOGY         SINCE    THE    SIXTIES    141


ideological studies in this school a decided functionalist flavor, since the
upshot of these analyses was to show how myth, ritual, taboo, or whatever
maintainedthe status quo. Finally, and most seriously, although structural
Marxists offered a way of mediating the materialand ideological "levels,"
they did not actually challenge the notion that such levels are analytically
distinguishable in the first place. Thus despite criticizing the Durkheimian
(and Parsonian)notion of "the social" as the "base" of the system, they
merely offered a deeper and allegedly more real and objective "base." And
despite attemptingto discover more importantfunctions for the "superstruc-
ture" (or despite claiming that what is base and what is superstructure varies
culturally and/or historically, or even occasionally and rathervaguely thatthe
superstructure part of the base) they continuedto reproducethe idea that it
               is
is useful to maintainsuch a set of analytic boxes.
   In this sense, it may be seen that structural Marxism was still very much
rooted in the sixties. While it injected a healthy dose of sociology into the
earlier scheme of categories, and while this sociology was itself relatively
originally conceived, the basic pigeonholes of sixties thoughtwere not radi-
cally revised. Further, unlike the political economy school and other more
recent approaches to be discussed shortly, structuralMarxism was largely
nonhistorical,a factor which, again, tied it to earlierforms of anthropology.
Indeedone may guess thatit was in partthis comfortablemix of old categories
and assumptions wrapped up in a new critical rhetoricthat made structural
Marxism so appealing in its day. It was in many ways the perfect vehicle for
academics who had been trainedin an earlierera, but who, in the seventies,
were feeling the pull of critical thought and action that was exploding all
around them.

Political Economy
The political economy school has taken its inspirationprimarilyfrom world-
systems and underdevelopmenttheories in political sociology (Wallerstein
1976; GunderFrank 1967). In contrastto structural      Marxism, which focused
largely, in the mannerof conventional anthropologicalstudies, on relatively
discrete societies or cultures, the political economists have shiftedthe focus to
large-scale regional political/economic systems (e.g., Hart 1982). Insofaras
they have attemptedto combine this focus with traditional    fieldworkin specif-
ic communitiesor microregions,theirresearchhas generallytakenthe formof
studying the effects of capitalist penetrationupon those communities (e.g.,
AmericanEthnologist 1978; Schneiderand Schneider1976). The emphasison
the impact of external forces, and on the ways in which societies change or
evolve largely in adaptationto such impact, ties the political economy school
in certain ways to the culturalecology of the sixties, and indeed many of its
currentpractitioners   were trainedin thatschool (e.g., Ross 1980). But where-
as for sixties cultural ecology, often studying relatively "primitive" so-
142   SHERRY     B.   ORTNER


cieties, the importantexternal forces were those of the naturalenvironment,
for the seventies political economists, generally studying "peasants," the
important  externalforces are those of the state andthe capitalistworld system.
   At the level of theory, the political economists differ from their cultural
ecology forebearspartly in showing a greaterwillingness to incorporate      cul-
tural or symbolic issues into their inquiries (e.g., Schneider 1978;
Riegelhaupt 1978). Specifically, their work tends to focus on symbols in-
volved in the developmentof class or group identity, in the context of politi-
cal/economic struggles of one sort or another.The political economy school
thus overlaps with the burgeoning "ethnicity" industry,althoughthe litera-
ture in the latter field is too vast and too amorphousfor me to do more than
nod to here. In any event, the willingness of the political economists to pay
attention,in however circumscribedfashion, to symbolic processes, is partof
the general relaxation of the old materialism/idealismwars of the sixties.
   The emphasisof this school upon largerregionalprocesses is also salutary,
at least up to a point. Anthropologistsdo have a tendency to treat societies,
even villages, as if they were islands unto themselves, with little sense of the
largersystems of relationsin which these units are embedded.The occasional
work (e.g., EdmundLeach's Political Systems of Highland Burma) that has
viewed societies in larger regional context has been something of an un-
classifiable (if admired) freak. To ignore the fact that peasants are part of
states, and that even "primitive" societies and communitiesare invariably
involved in wider systems of exchanges of all sorts, is to seriouslydistortthe
data, and it is the virtueof the political economiststhatthey remindus of this.
   Finally, the political economists must be given leading credit for stressing
very strongly the importanceof history for anthropologicalstudy. They are
not the first to have done so, nor are they the only ones doing so now, and I
will say more aboutanthropology'srapprochement        with historyin the conclu-
sions of this essay. Nonetheless, it is certainlythe membersof this school who
appear the most committed to a fully historical anthropology,and who are
producing sustained and systematic work groundedin this commitment.
   On the negative side of the ledger, we may complainfirst that the political
economy model is too economic, too strictlymaterialist.One hearsa lot about
wages, the market, the cash nexus, economic exploitation, underdevelop-
ment, and so forth, but not enough aboutthe relationsof power, domination,
manipulation,control, and the like which those economic relationsplay into,
and which for actors constitute much of the experienced pain of economic
injustice. Political economy, in other words, is not political enough.
   My main objection, however, is located deeper in the theoreticalmodel of
political economy. Specifically, I find the capitalism-centered     view of the
world questionable, to say the least, especially for anthropology.At the core
of the model is the assumptionthat virtuallyeverythingwe study has already
been touched ("penetrated") by the capitalist world system, and that there-
THEORY      IN   ANTHROPOLOGY         SINCE    THE    SIXTIES    I43


fore much of what we see in our fieldwork and describe in our monographs
must be understoodas having been shapedin responseto that system. Perhaps
this is true for Europeanpeasants, but even here one would want at least to
leave the question open. When we get even further from the "center,"
however, the assumptionbecomes very problematicindeed. A society, even a
village, has its own structureand history, and this must be as muchpartof the
analysis as its relations with the largercontext within which it operates. (See
Joel Kahn (1980) for a more balanced view.)
   The problems derived from the capitalism-centered      worldview also affect
the political economists' view of history. Historyis often treatedas something
that arrives, like a ship, from outside the society in question. Thus we do not
get the history of that society, but the impact of (our) history on that society.
The accounts producedfrom such a perspectiveare often quite unsatisfactory
in terms of traditionalanthropologicalconcerns: the actual organizationand
cultureof the society in question. Traditionalstudies of course had their own
problemswith respect to history. They often presentedus with a thin chapter
on "historical background" at the beginning and an inadequatechapteron
 "social change" at the end. The political economy study invertsthis relation-
ship, but only to create the inverse problem.
   The political economists, moreover, tend to situatethemselves more on the
ship of (capitalist) history than on the shore. They say in effect that we can
never know what the other system, in its unique, "traditional," aspects,
really looked like anyway. By realizing that much of what we see as tradition
is in fact a responseto Westernimpact, so the argumentgoes, we not only get
a more accuratepictureof what is going on, but we acknowledgeat the same
time the perniciouseffects of our own system upon others. Such a view is also
present, but in modes of anger and/or despair ratherthan pragmatism,in a
number of recent works that question philosophically whether we can ever
truly know the "other"-Edward Said's Orientalismis the prime example
(see also Rabinow 1977; Crapanzano1980; Riesman 1977).
   To such a position we can only respond:try. The effort is as important      as
the results, in terms of both our theories and our practices. The attemptto
view other systems from groundlevel is the basis, perhapsthe only basis, of
anthropology'sdistinctive contribution the humansciences. It is our capac-
                                          to
ity, largely developed in fieldwork, to take the perspectiveof the folks on the
shore, that allows us to learn anything at all-even in our own culture-
beyond what we alreadyknow. (Indeed, as more and more anthropologists         are
doing fieldwork in Westerncultures, including the United States, the impor-
tance of maintaininga capacity to see otherness, even next door, becomes
more and more acute.) Further,it is our location "on the ground"thatputs us
in a position to see people not simply as passive reactorsto and enactorsof
some "system," but as active agents and subjects in their own history.
   In concluding this section, I must confess thatmy placementof the political
144    SHERRY        B.   ORTNER


economy school in the seventies is somethingof an ideological move. In fact
political economy is very much alive and well in the eighties, and it will
probably thrive for some time. My periodization is thus, like that of all
histories, only partly related to real time. I have included political economy
and structural Marxismwithin this period/categorybecauseboth schools con-
tinue to share a set of assumptionsdistinctfrom what I wish to emphasizefor
the anthropologyof the eighties. Specifically, both assume, together with
earlier anthropologies, that human action and historical process are almost
entirely structurallyor systemically determined. Whether it be the hidden
hand of structureor the juggernautof capitalismthat is seen as the agent of
society/history, it is certainly not in any central way real people doing real
things. These are precisely the views from which at least some anthropolo-
gists, as well as practitionersin many other fields, appearto be strugglingto
break free as we move into the present decade.

INTO   THE EIGHTIES:          PRACTICE

I began this article by noting the apparentaccuracyof Wolf's remarksto the
effect that the field of anthropologyis disintegrating,even grantingthe low
degree of integrationit had in the past. I also suggested that one could find
scattered over the landscape the elements of a new trend that seems to be
gatheringforce and coherence. In this final section I call attentionto this new
trend, sketch it, and subject it to a preliminarycritique.
   For the past several years, there has been growing interest in analysis
focused through one or anotherof a bundle of interrelatedterms: practice,
praxis, action, interaction,activity, experience, performance.A second, and
closely related, bundle of terms focuses on the doer of all that doing: agent,
actor, person, self, individual, subject.
   In some fields, movement in this direction began relatively early in the
seventies, some of it in direct reaction to structuralism.In linguistics, for
example, there was an early rejection of structurallinguistics and a strong
move to view language as communicationand performance(e.g., Bauman
and Sherzer 1974; Cole and Morgan 1975). In anthropologytoo there were
scatteredcalls for a more action based approach.In France, PierreBourdieu
published his Outline of a Theory of Practice in 1972. In the United States,
Geertz attacked both hypercoherentstudies of symbolic systems (many of
them inspiredby his own programmatic      papers)and what he saw as the sterile
formalismof structuralism,   calling insteadfor anthropologists see "human
                                                                to
behavior     . . as . . . symbolic action" (1973a:10; see also Dolgin, Kem-
nitzer, and Schneider 1977; Wagner 1975; T. Turner1969). In England,there
was a minoritywing thatcriticizedtraditionalviews of "social structure"not
from the point of view of structuralMarxism, but from the perspective of
individualchoice and decision making (e.g., Kapferer1976).14

  14 The transactionalist tradition in British
                                               anthropology may of course be traced back further,
THEORY        IN    ANTHROPOLOGY              SINCE      THE     SIXTIES      145


  For much of the seventies, however, the structural  Marxistsand, later, the
political economists,  remained dominant, at least within anthropology.For
them, social and culturalphenomena were to be explained largely by being
referredto systemic/structural  mechanismsof one sort or another.It was only
in the late seventies that the hegemony of structuralMarxism, if not that of
political economy, began   to wane. An English translation Bourdieu'sbook
                                                          of
was published in 1978, and it was at aboutthat time that the calls for a more
practice-orientedapproachbecame increasingly audible. Here is a sampler:
The instruments reasoning changing societyis less andless represented
                of           are       and                                 as
anelaborate machine a quasi-organism as a serious
                    or               than           game,a sidewalk  drama,or
a behavioral (Geertz1980a:168).
             text

We needto watchthesesystems[of kinship] action,to studytacticsandstrategy,
                                        in
not merelythe rulesof the game(Barnes1980:301).

? . . genderconceptions in any society are to be understoodas functioningaspectsof a
cultural           whichactors
       systemthrough         manipulate,                and
                                              legitimize, reproduce
                                      interpret,
the patterns . . . that order their social world (Collier and Rosaldo 1981:311).'5

Whatdo actorswantandhow canthey get it? (Ortner
                                              1981:366)
If structural/semiotic
                    analysis to be extended general
                           is             to      anthropology themodel
                                                             on
of its pertinence "language," whatis lostis notmerely
                 to           then                         and
                                                     history change,  but
practice-humanactionin the world. Some mightthinkthatwhat is lost is what
anthropology all about(Sahlins1981:6).
              is
   As was the case with the strong revisionist trendin the sixties, the present
movement appears much broader than the field of anthropologyalone. In
linguistics, Alton Becker, in a much-cited article, has emphasizedissues of
text building over and against reification of The Text (1979). In spciology,
symbolic interactionismand other forms of so-called microsociology appear
to be attractingnew attention,16 and Anthony Giddens has dubbedthe rela-
tionship between structureand "agency" one of the "central problems" of
modem social theory (1979). In history, E. P. Thompsonhas railed against
theorists (everything from Parsoniansto Stalinists) who treat "history as a
'process withouta subject' [and]concurin the eviction fromhistoryof human
agency" (1978:79). In literarystudies, RaymondWilliams insists that litera-
ture must be treatedas the productof particular   practices, and accuses those
who abstractliteraturefrom practice of performing "an extraordinary       ideo-
logical feat" (1977:46). If we push further-and here we skirt dangerous

to Barthand to Bailey in the sixties, to the earlierworks of Leach (e.g., 1960), and ultimatelyto
Raymond Firth (e.g., 1963 [1951]). See also Marriott(1976) in the United States.
   15 I would argue, if I had more
                                       space, that feminist anthropologyis one of the primary
contexts in which a practice approachhas been developing. The Collier and Rosaldo (1981)
article is a good example. See also Ortner(1981).
   16 MayerZald, personalcommunication,at the Social Science HistorySeminar(Universityof
Michigan), 1982.
146    SHERRY       B.   ORTNER


ground-we might even see the whole sociobiology movementas partof this
general trend, insofar as it shifts the evolutionarymechanismfrom random
mutation to intentional choice on the part of actors seeking to maximize
reproductivesuccess. (I should probablysay, righthere and not in a footnote,
that I have a range of very strong objections to sociobiology. Nonetheless, I
do not think it is too far-fetched to see its emergence as part of the broad
movement to which I am drawing attentionhere.)
   The practice approachis diverse, and I will not attemptto compare and
contrast its many strands. Rather I will select for discussion a number of
works that seem to share a common orientation within the larger set, an
orientationthat seems to me particularly  promising. I do not wish to canonize
any single   one of these works, nor do I wish to provide a label for the subset
and endow it with more reality than it has. What I do here is more like
beginning to develop a photograph, to coax a latent form into something
recognizable.
   We may begin by contrasting, in a general way, this (subset of) newer
practice-oriented   work with certain more established approaches,especially
with symbolic interactionismin sociology (Blumer 1962; Goffman 1959; see
also Berreman 1962, and more recently Gregor 1977 in anthropology)and
with what was called transactionalism anthropology(Kapferer1976, Mar-
                                        in
riott 1976, Goody 1978, Barth 1966, Bailey 1969). The first point to note is
that these approacheswere elaboratedin opposition to the dominant, essen-
tially Parsonian/Durkheimian,view of the world as ordered by rules and
norms.17 Recognizing that institutionalorganizationand culturalpatterning
exist, the symbolic interactionistsand transactionalistsnonetheless sought to
minimize or bracket the relevance of these phenomena for understanding
social life:
                  of
From standpoint symbolic
     the                                socialorganization a framework
                             interaction,                is            inside
of whichactingunitsdeveloptheiractions.Structural features,suchas "culture,"
"socialsystems," "socialstratification," "socialroles," set conditions their
                                       or                            for
actionbutdo not determinetheiraction(Blumer  1962:152).
  The newer practice theorists, on the other hand, share a view that "the
system" (in a variety of senses to be discussed below) does in fact have very
powerful, even "determining," effect upon human action and the shape of
events. Their interestin the study of action and interaction thus not a matter
                                                            is
of denying or minimizing this point, but expresses ratheran urgent need to
understandwhere "the system" comes from-how it is produced and re-
produced, and how it may have changed in the past or be changed in the
future. As Giddens argues in his importantrecent book (1979), the study of
  17 Parsons and his colleagues gave the term "action" central place in their scheme (1962
[1951]), but what they meant by this was essentially en-actmentof rules and norms. Bourdieu,
Giddens, and others have pointed this out, and have cast their argumentsin part against this
position.
THEORY      IN   ANTHROPOLOGY         SINCE   THE    SIXTIES    147


practiceis not an antagonisticalternativeto the study of systems or structures,
but a necessary complement to it.
   The other major aspect of the newer practice orientation,differentiatingit
significantly from earlier interactionistand transactionalistapproaches, re-
sides in a palpable Marxist influence carrying through from the seventies.
Partly this is visible in the way in which things like culture and/or structure
are viewed. That is, although the newer practice theorists share with sixties
anthropologya strong sense of the shaping power of culture/structure,       this
shapingpower      is viewed ratherdarkly, as a matterof "constraint," "hegem-
ony," and "symbolic domination." We will come back to this position in
greaterdetail later. More generally, the Marxistinfluence is to be seen in the
assumptionthat the most importantforms of action or interactionfor analytic
purposes are those which take place in asymmetricalor dominatedrelations,
that it is these forms of action or interactionthatbest explain the shapeof any
given system at any given time. Whetherit is a matterof focusing directlyon
interaction (even "struggle") between asymmetrically related actors, or
whether it is more broadly a matter of defining actors (whatever they are
doing) in terms of roles and statuses derived from asymmetricalrelationsin
which they participate,the approachtends to highlight social asymmetryas
the most importantdimension of both action and structure.
   Not all of currentpractice work manifests the Marxistinfluence. Some of
it-like symbolic interactionismand transactionalism      themselves-is more in
the spirit of Adam Smith. The members of the subset with which I am
concerned, however, implicitly or explicitly shareat least the criticalflavorof
seventies anthropology, if not a systematic allegiance to Marxist theory per
se.
   Yet to speak of a Marxist influence in all of this is actually to obscure an
importantaspect of what is going on: an interpenetration,      almost a merger,
between Marxist and Weberian frameworks. In the sixties, the opposition
between Marxand Weber, as "materialist"and "idealist," had been empha-
sized. The practice theorists, in contrast, draw on a set of writers who in-
terpretthe Marxistcorpus in such a way as to renderit quite compatiblewith
Weber's views. As Weber put the actor at the center of his model, so these
writersemphasize issues of human praxis in Marx. As Weber subsumedthe
economic within the political, so these writersencompasseconomic exploita-
tion within political domination. And as Weber was centrallyconcernedwith
ethos and consciousness, so these writers stress similar issues within Marx's
work. Choosing Marx over Weber as one's theoristof reference is a tactical
move of a certainsort. In reality, the theoreticalframeworkinvolved is about
equally indebted to both. (On theory, see Giddens 1971; Williams 1976;
Avineri 1971; Ollman 1971; Bauman 1973; Habermas1973; Goldmann1977.
For substantivecase analyses in this Weberian-Marxist       vein, see Thompson
1966; Williams 1973; Genovese 1976.)
148   SHERRY     B.   ORTNER


   I will proceed to explicate and evaluate the "new practice" position by
way of posing a series of questions:What is it that a practiceapproachseeks
to explain?What is practice?How is it motivated?And what sorts of analytic
relationshipsare postulatedin the model? Let me emphasizevery stronglythat
I do not offer here a coherenttheoryof practice.I merely sortout anddiscuss,
in a very preliminaryfashion, some of the central axes of such a theory.

What is Being Explained?
As previously indicated, modem practicetheory seeks to explain the relation-
ship(s) that obtain between human action, on the one hand, and some global
entity which we may call "the system," on the other. Questionsconcerning
these relationshipsmay go in either direction-the impact of the system on
practice, and the impactof practiceon the system. How these processes work
will be taken up below. Here we must say a few words about the natureof
 "the system."
   In two recent works in anthropologythat explicitly attemptto elaboratea
practice-basedmodel (Bourdieu 1978 [1972]; and Sahlins 1981), the authors
nominallytake a Frenchstructuralist   view of the system (patternsof relations
between categories, and of relationsbetween relations). In fact however both
Bourdieu's habitus and Sahlins's "cosmological dramas" behave in many
ways like the American concept of culture, combining elements of ethos,
affect, and value with more strictly cognitive schemes of classification. The
choice of a French or an American perspective on the system does have
certainconsequences for the shape of the analysis as a whole, but we will not
pursue these here. The point is that practice anthropologistsassume that
society and historyare not simply sums of ad hoc responsesand adaptations    to
particular stimuli, but are governedby organizational evaluativeschemes.
                                                      and
It is these (embodied, of course, within institutional,symbolic, and material
forms) that constitute the system.
   The system, further,is not broken up into units like base and superstruc-
ture, or society and culture, but is rather a relatively seamless whole. An
institution-say, a marriagesystem-is at once a system of social relations,
economic arrangements,political processes, culturalcategories, norms, val-
ues, ideals, emotional patterns,and so on and on. No attemptis made to sort
these componentsinto levels and to assign primacyto one or the other level.
Nor, for example, is marriage as a whole assigned to "society," while
religion is assigned to "culture." A practice approachhas no need to break
the system into artificial chunks like base and superstructure  (and to argue
over which determineswhich), since the analytic effort is not to explain one
chunk of the system by referringit to anotherchunk, but ratherto explain the
system as an integral whole (which is not to say a harmoniouslyintegrated
one) by referringit to practice.
   But if the system is an integral whole, at the same time all of its parts or
THEORY      IN   ANTHROPOLOGY            SINCE     THE    SIXTIES    149


dimensions do not have equal analyticsignificance. At the core of the system,
both forming it and deforming it, are the specific realities of asymmetry,
inequality, and dominationin a given time and place. RaymondWilliams, a
Marxist literary/culturalhistorian, sums up both the insistence upon holism
and the privileged position of dominationcharacteristic this view. Picking
                                                       of
up Antonio Gramsci's term "hegemony" as his label for the system, he
argues that
"hegemony" is a concept which at once includes and goes beyond two powerful
earlierconcepts: that of "culture" as a "whole social process," in which men define
and shape their whole lives; and that of "ideology" in any of its Marxist senses, in
which a system of meanings and values is the expression or projectionof a particular
class interest.
   "Hegemony" goes beyond "culture" in its insistenceon relatingthe "whole social
process" to specific distributionsof power and influence. To say that men define and
shape their whole lives is true only in abstraction. In any actual society there are
specific inequalities in means and therefore in capacity to realize this process....
Gramscithereforeintroducesthe necessary recognition of dominanceand subordina-
tion in what has still, however, to be recognized as a whole process.
   It is in just this recognition of the wholeness of the process that the concept of
"hegemony" goes beyond "ideology." What is decisive is not only the conscious
system of ideas and beliefs, but the whole lived social process as practicallyorganized
by specific and dominantmeanings and values. ...
   [Hegemony] is in the strongestsense a "culture," but a culturewhich has also to be
seen as the lived dominance and subordination of particular classes (Williams
1977:108-109, 110).
What a practice theory seeks to explain, then, is the genesis, reproduction,
and change of form and meaning of a given social/cultural whole, defined
in-more or less-this sense.

What is Practice?
In principle, the answer to this question is almost unlimited:anythingpeople
do. Given the centrality of domination in the model, however, the most
significant forms of practice are those with intentionalor unintentional   politi-
cal implications. Then again, almost anything people do has such implica-
tions. So the study of practice is after all the study of all forms of human
action, but from a particular-political-angle.
   Beyond this general point, furtherdistinctionsmay be introduced.There is
first of all the question of what are taken to be the acting units. Most practice
anthropologyto date takes these units to be individualactors, whetheractual
historical individuals, or social types ("women," "commoners," "work-
ers," "junior siblings," etcetera). The analyst takes these people and their
doings as the reference point for understandinga particularunfolding of
events, and/or for understanding processes involved in the reproduction
                                    the                                        or
change of some set of structural   features. In contrastto a large body of work
in the field of history, there has been relatively little done in anthropologyon
150   SHERRY     B.   ORTNER

concertedcollective action (but see Wolf 1969; Friedrich1970; Blu 1980; see
also the literature cargo cults, especially Worsley 1968). Even in studiesof
                   on
collective action, however, the collectivity is handledmethodologicallyas a
single subject. We shall be discussing, throughoutthis section, some of the
problemsthat arise from the essential individualismof most currentforms of
practice theory.
   A second set of questions concerns the temporal organizationof action.
Some authors(Bourdieuis an example) treat action in terms of relatively ad
hoc decision making, and/or relatively short-term"moves." Otherssuggest,
even if they do not develop the point, that humanbeings act within plans or
programsthat are always more long range than any single move, and indeed
that most moves are intelligible only within the context of these largerplans
(Sahlins (1981) implies this, as do Ortner(1981) and Collier and Rosaldo
(1981); for an older example, see Hartand Pilling (1960)). Many such plans
are culturally provided (the normative life cycle, for example), but many
others must be constructedby actors themselves. Even projects generated
("creatively") by actors, however, tend to take stereotypedforms, insofaras
the constraints and the resources of the system are relatively constant for
actors in similar positions. In any event, an emphasis on larger "projects"
rather than particular "moves" underlines the point that action itself has
(developmental) structure, as well as operating in, and in relation to,
structure.
   Finally, there is the question of the kinds of action takento be analytically
centralto the currentapproach.Everyone seems to agree in opposing a Parso-
nian or Saussurianview in which action is seen as sheeren-actmentor execu-
tion of rules and norms (Bourdieu 1978; Sahlins 1981; Giddens 1979). More-
over, everyone seems also to agree that a kind of romantic or heroic
 "voluntarism," emphasizing the freedom and relatively unrestrictedin-
ventiveness of actors, will not do either (e.g., Thompson1978). Whatis left,
then, is a view of action largely in terms of pragmaticchoice and decision
making, and/or active calculating and strategizing. I will have more to say
about the strategic model in the next section, when I discuss the views of
motivation entailed in practice theory. Here, however, I wish to question
whether the critique of en-actmentor execution may not have gone too far.
Indeed, despite the attackson Parsonsby Bourdieuand Giddens, both recog-
nize the central role of highly patternedand routinizedbehaviorin systemic
reproduction.It is precisely in those areasof life-especially in the so-called
domestic domain-where action proceeds with little reflection, that much of
the conservatism of a system tends to be located. Either because practice
theorists wish to emphasize the activeness and intentionalityof action, or
because of a growing interestin change as againstreproduction,or both, the
degree to which actors really do simply enact norms because "that was the
way of our ancestors" may be unduly undervalued.
THEORY      IN   ANTHROPOLOGY         SINCE    THE    SIXTIES    151



 WhatMotivates Action?
 A theory of practice requires some sort of theory of motivation. At the
 moment, the dominant theory of motivation in practice anthropologyis de-
 rived from interesttheory. The model is that of an essentially individualistic,
.and somewhat aggressive, actor, self-interested,rational,pragmatic,and per-
 haps with a maximizing orientationas well. What actorsdo, it is assumed, is
 rationallygo after what they want, and what they want is what is materially
 and politically useful for them within the context of their culturaland histor-
 ical situations.
    Interesttheory has been rakedover the coals many times before. Here it is
 sufficient simply to note a few points that have particularrelevance for an-
 thropological studies of practice.
    Insofar as interest theory is, even if it pretendsnot to be, a psychological
 theory, it is clearly far too narrow. In particular, although pragmaticra-
 tionalityis certainlyone aspect of motivation, it is never the only one, and not
 always even the dominantone. To accordit the statusof exclusive motivating
 force is to exclude from the analytic discourse a whole range of emotional
 terms-need, fear, suffering, desire, and others-that must surely be partof
 motivation.
    Unfortunately, anthropologistshave generally found that actors with too
 much psychological plumbingare hardto handlemethodologically,and prac-
 tice theorists are no exception. There is, however, a growing body of litera-
 ture which explores the variable constructionof self, person, emotion, and
 motive in cross-culturalperspective (e.g., M. Rosaldo 1980, 1981; Friedrich
 1977; Geertz 1973a, 1975; Singer 1980; Kirkpatrick1977; Guemple 1972).
 The growth of this body of work is itself part of the larger trend toward an
 interestin elaboratingan actor-centered    paradigm,as is the fact that the sub-
 field of psychological anthropology seems to be enjoying something of a
 renaissance (e.g., Paul 1982; Kracke 1978; Levy 1973). One may hope for
 some cross-fertilization between the more sociologically oriented practice
 accounts, with their relatively denaturedviews of motive, and some of these
 more richly textured accounts of emotion and motivation.
    If interesttheory assumes too much rationalityon the partof actors, it also
 assumes too much active-ness. The idea that actors are always pressing
 claims, pursuinggoals, advancing purposes, and the like may simply be an
 overly energetic (and overly political) view of how and why people act. We
 may recall here the distinction, underscored Geertz, between interesttheo-
                                                by
 ry and strain theory (1973c). If actors in interest theory are always actively
 striving for gains, actors in strain theory are seen as experiencingthe com-
 plexities of their situations and attemptingto solve problemsposed by those
 situations. It follows from these points that the strain perspective places
 greateremphasis on the analysis of the system itself, the forces in play upon
152   SHERRY     B.   ORTNER


actors, as a way of understanding    where actors, as we say, are coming from.
In particular,a system is analyzedwith the aim of revealingthe sortsof binds
it creates for actors, the sorts of burdensit places upon them, and so on. This
analysis, in turn, provides much of the context for understandingactors'
motives, and the kinds of projectsthey constructfor dealing with their situa-
tions (see also Ortner 1975, 1978).
   While strain theory does not rectify the psychological shortcomings of
interesttheory, it does at least make for a more systematicexplorationof the
social forces shaping motives than interesttheory does. Indeed, one may say
that strain theory is a theory of the social, as opposed to psychological,
productionof "interests," the latterbeing seen less as direct expressions of
utility and advantagefor actors, and more as images of solutions to experi-
enced stresses and problems.
   Finally, an interestapproachtends to go handin handwith seeing action in
terms of short-termtactical "moves" ratherthan long-term developmental
"projects." From a tactical point of view, actors seek particulargains,
whereas from a developmentalpoint of view, actors are seen as involved in
relatively far-reachingtransformations their states of being-of their rela-
                                           of
tionships   with things, persons, and self. We may say, in the spiritof Gramsci,
that action in a developmentalor "projects" perspectiveis more a matterof
"becoming" thanof "getting" (1957). Intrinsicto this latterperspectiveis a
sense of motive and action as shapednot only by problemsbeing solved, and
gains being sought, but by images and ideals of what constitutesgoodness-
in people, in relationships, and in conditions of life.
   It iS a peculiarityof interesttheorythat it is sharedacross a broadspectrum
of analysts, Marxist and non-Marxist, "old" and "new" practicetheorists.
The popularityand durabilityof the perspective,despite numerousattacksand
criticisms, suggest that especially deep changes in our own practiceswill be
requiredif anything is to be dislodged in this area.
The Nature of Interactions between Practice and the System
    1. How does the systemshape practice? Anthropologists-American ones,
anyway-have for the most partlong agreedthat cultureshapes, guides, and
even to some extent dictates behavior. In the sixties, Geertzelaboratedsome
of the important   mechanismsinvolved in this process, and it seems to me that
most moder practice theorists, including those who write in Marxistand/or
structuralist  terms, hold an essentially Geertzianview. But there are certain
changes   of emphasis, derived from the centralityof dominationwithin the
practiceframework.For one thing, as noted earlier, the emphasishas shifted
from what culture allows and enables people to see, feel, and do, to what it
restrictsand inhibitsthem from seeing, feeling, and doing. Further,although
it is agreed that culture powerfully constitutesthe reality that actors live in,
this reality is looked upon with criticaleyes: why this one and not some other?
And what sorts of alternativesare people being dis-abled from seeing?
THEORY       IN   ANTHROPOLOGY          SINCE     THE   SIXTIES     153


    It is important note that this view is at least partlydistinctfrom a view of
                     to
cultureas mystification. In a mystificationview, culture(= "ideology") tells
lies aboutthe realities of people's lives, and the analyticproblemis to under-
stand how people come to believe these lies (e.g., Bloch 1977). In the ap-
proach under discussion here, however, there is only one reality, and it is
culturally constituted from top to bottom. The problem is not that of the
system telling lies aboutsome extrasystemic"reality," but of why the system
as a whole has a certain configuration, and of why and how it excludes
alternativepossible configurations.
    In any event, in termsof the specific questionof how the system constrains
practice, the emphasis tends to be laid on essentially culturaland psychologi-
cal mechanisms: mechanisms of the formationand transformation "con-         of
sciousness." Although constraintsof material and political sorts, including
force, are fully acknowledged, there seems to be general agreement that
action is constrainedmost deeply and systematically by the ways in which
culturecontrols the definitions of the world for actors, limits their conceptual
tools, and restricts their emotional repertoires.Culturebecomes part of the
self. Speaking of the sense of honor among the Kabyle, for example, Bour-
dieu says:
? . . honour a permanent
               is              disposition, embedded the agents'verybodiesin the
                                                      in
formof mental     dispositions, schemes perception thought,
                                        of           and           extremelygeneralin
theirapplication,    such as those whichdivideup the worldin accordance the  with
oppositions   between maleandthe female,eastandwest, future past,topand
                       the                                            and
bottom,    rightandleft, etc., andalso, at a deeperlevel, in theformof bodilypostures
andstances,waysof standing,                                  or
                                  sitting,looking,speaking, walking.    Whatis called
the sense of honour nothing
                       is         otherthanthe cultivated  disposition,        in
                                                                       inscribed the
bodyschemaandthe schemesof thought           (1978:15).
In a similar vein, Foucault says of the discourse of "perversions":
Themachinery powerthatfocuseson thiswholealienstrain notaimto suppress
               of                                       did
it, butrather give it ananalytical,
            to                    visible,andpermanent      it
                                                     reality: wasimplantedin
bodies,slippedin beneath   modesof conduct,madeintoa principle classification
                                                                of
andintelligibility,
                  established a raisond'etreanda natural
                             as                         order disorder....
                                                               of
Thestrategy behind dissemination to strewreality
                    this             was             withthemandincorporate
themintothe individual   (1980:44).
Thus insofar as dominationis as much a matterof culturaland psychological
processes as of material and political ones, it operates by shaping actors'
dispositions such that, in the extreme case, "the agents' aspirationshave the
same limits as the objective conditions of which they are the product"(Bour-
dieu 1978:166; see also Rabinow 1975; Barnettand Silverman1979; Rabinow
and Sullivan 1979).
   At the same time, however, those authorswho emphasizeculturaldomina-
tion also place importantlimits on the scope and depth of culturalcontrols.
The extreme case is never reached, and often never even approached.Thus
while accepting the view of culture as powerfully constraining, they argue
154   SHERRY     B.   ORTNER


that hegemony is always more fragile than its appears,and never as total as it
(or as traditionalculturalanthropology)would claim. The reasons given for
this state of affairs are various, and relate directly to the ways in which the
different authorsconceptualize systemic change. This brings us to our final
set of questions.
   2. How does practice shape the system?Therearereallytwo considerations
here-how practice reproduces the system, and how the system may be
changed by practice. A unified theory of practice should ideally be able to
account for both within a single framework.At the moment, however, it is
clear that a focus on reproductiontends to producea ratherdifferentpicture
from a focus on change, and we will thus take these issues separately.
   Beginning with reproduction,there is of course a long traditionin an-
thropologyof asking how it is thatnorms, values, and conceptualschemes get
reproducedby and for actors. Prior to the sixties, at least in American an-
thropology, emphasis was laid upon socialization practices as the primary
agents of this process. In England,however, the influenceof the Durkheimian
paradigmgenerated an emphasis on ritual. It was throughthe enactmentof
ritualsof various kinds that actors were seen as coming to be wedded to the
normsand values of theirculture, and/or to be purged,at least temporarily,of
whatever dissident sentiments they might harbor(e.g., Gluckman 1955; V.
Turner1969; Beidelman 1966). The ritualfocus, or what might be called for
focus on extraordinarypractice, became even stronger in the sixties and
seventies. Americansymbolic anthropologists      took up the view thatritualwas
one of the primary matrices for the reproductionof consciousness (Geertz
1973b;Ortner1978), even if they dissentedfromcertainaspectsof the British
approach.And the structural    Marxiststoo placed greatweight on the power of
ritual to mediate social structural contradictionsand mystify the workingsof
the system.Ritualin factis a formof practice-people do it-and to studythe re-
productionof consciousness, mystified or otherwise, in the processes of ritual
behavioris to study at least one way in which practicereproducesthe system.
   The newer practiceapproaches,by contrast,place greateremphasison the
practicesof ordinaryliving. Althoughthese were not by any means ignoredin
earlierwork, they assume greaterprominencehere. Thus despite his stress on
the highly intentionalized moments of practice, Bourdieu also pays close
attention to the little routines people enact, again and again, in working,
eating, sleeping, and relaxing, as well as the little scenariosof etiquettethey
play out again and again in social interaction. All of these routines and
scenariosare predicatedupon, and embody withinthemselves, the fundamen-
tal notions of temporal,spatial, and social orderingthatunderlieand organize
the system as a whole. In enacting these routines, actorsnot only continueto
be shaped by the underlying organizationalprinciples involved, but con-
tinually re-endorse those principles in the world of public observationand
discourse.
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner
Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner

Más contenido relacionado

Destacado

Princiiples of Scientific Method in Anthropology
Princiiples of Scientific Method in AnthropologyPrinciiples of Scientific Method in Anthropology
Princiiples of Scientific Method in AnthropologyPaulVMcDowell
 
Anthropological Theories and Theoretical Orientations
Anthropological Theories and Theoretical OrientationsAnthropological Theories and Theoretical Orientations
Anthropological Theories and Theoretical OrientationsBrax Reantillo
 
Forensic Dentistry-Age Determination In Children
Forensic Dentistry-Age Determination In ChildrenForensic Dentistry-Age Determination In Children
Forensic Dentistry-Age Determination In ChildrenDr. Shirin
 
Introduction to Theory of Evolution
Introduction to Theory of EvolutionIntroduction to Theory of Evolution
Introduction to Theory of EvolutionEmily Neistadt
 
Age estimation by bones
Age estimation by bonesAge estimation by bones
Age estimation by boneschetan samra
 

Destacado (6)

Princiiples of Scientific Method in Anthropology
Princiiples of Scientific Method in AnthropologyPrinciiples of Scientific Method in Anthropology
Princiiples of Scientific Method in Anthropology
 
Anthropological Theories and Theoretical Orientations
Anthropological Theories and Theoretical OrientationsAnthropological Theories and Theoretical Orientations
Anthropological Theories and Theoretical Orientations
 
Forensic Dentistry-Age Determination In Children
Forensic Dentistry-Age Determination In ChildrenForensic Dentistry-Age Determination In Children
Forensic Dentistry-Age Determination In Children
 
Introduction to Theory of Evolution
Introduction to Theory of EvolutionIntroduction to Theory of Evolution
Introduction to Theory of Evolution
 
Sex Determination
Sex DeterminationSex Determination
Sex Determination
 
Age estimation by bones
Age estimation by bonesAge estimation by bones
Age estimation by bones
 

Similar a Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner

Anthropological Approaches
Anthropological ApproachesAnthropological Approaches
Anthropological ApproachesCynthia King
 
Resistance and the problem of - Ortner
Resistance and the problem of - Ortner Resistance and the problem of - Ortner
Resistance and the problem of - Ortner Laura Calle
 
Sujay theories of cultural change final final final final final
Sujay theories of cultural change final final final final finalSujay theories of cultural change final final final final final
Sujay theories of cultural change final final final final finalSujay Rao Mandavilli
 
Sujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdfSujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdfSujay Rao Mandavilli
 
Anthropology Is A Study Of Humankind
Anthropology Is A Study Of HumankindAnthropology Is A Study Of Humankind
Anthropology Is A Study Of HumankindTammy Moncrief
 
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2hectorjpr
 
Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...
Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...
Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...Sham Lumba
 
Rushton - Race, Evolution and Behavior
Rushton - Race, Evolution and BehaviorRushton - Race, Evolution and Behavior
Rushton - Race, Evolution and BehaviorDadang Solihin
 
Early anthropologist
Early anthropologistEarly anthropologist
Early anthropologistRAJ SP
 
Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4
Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4
Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4TiffannyUtami
 
A critical engagment ab (final)
A critical engagment ab (final)A critical engagment ab (final)
A critical engagment ab (final)Spencer Ruelos
 
Ewrt1 c class 3 post qhq
Ewrt1 c class 3 post qhqEwrt1 c class 3 post qhq
Ewrt1 c class 3 post qhqjordanlachance
 
A critical engagment ab
A critical engagment abA critical engagment ab
A critical engagment abSpencer Ruelos
 
Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams
Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its DreamsReview of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams
Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its DreamsJohn Rapko
 
Patriarchal Society Essay.pdf
Patriarchal Society Essay.pdfPatriarchal Society Essay.pdf
Patriarchal Society Essay.pdfCarmen Ercoli
 
A Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social Anthropology
A Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social AnthropologyA Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social Anthropology
A Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social AnthropologyUkrit Chalermsan
 

Similar a Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner (20)

Neurobiology, layered texts, and correlative cosmologies — a cross cultural f...
Neurobiology, layered texts, and correlative cosmologies — a cross cultural f...Neurobiology, layered texts, and correlative cosmologies — a cross cultural f...
Neurobiology, layered texts, and correlative cosmologies — a cross cultural f...
 
Anthropological Approaches
Anthropological ApproachesAnthropological Approaches
Anthropological Approaches
 
Resistance and the problem of - Ortner
Resistance and the problem of - Ortner Resistance and the problem of - Ortner
Resistance and the problem of - Ortner
 
Sujay theories of cultural change final final final final final
Sujay theories of cultural change final final final final finalSujay theories of cultural change final final final final final
Sujay theories of cultural change final final final final final
 
Sujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdfSujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
Sujay Theories of Cultural change FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL FINAL.pdf
 
Anthropology Is A Study Of Humankind
Anthropology Is A Study Of HumankindAnthropology Is A Study Of Humankind
Anthropology Is A Study Of Humankind
 
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
Narcisismo cultural best seller q2
 
Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...
Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...
Handout 1Understanding Culture, Society, and Politics narra NHS SHS Narra Pal...
 
Rushton - Race, Evolution and Behavior
Rushton - Race, Evolution and BehaviorRushton - Race, Evolution and Behavior
Rushton - Race, Evolution and Behavior
 
Early anthropologist
Early anthropologistEarly anthropologist
Early anthropologist
 
Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4
Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4
Tiffanny tessantya utami 039 2020_b_review jurnal 4
 
Mclaren on postmodern ism
Mclaren on postmodern ismMclaren on postmodern ism
Mclaren on postmodern ism
 
A critical engagment ab (final)
A critical engagment ab (final)A critical engagment ab (final)
A critical engagment ab (final)
 
Ewrt1 c class 3 post qhq
Ewrt1 c class 3 post qhqEwrt1 c class 3 post qhq
Ewrt1 c class 3 post qhq
 
Neuro Correlative
Neuro CorrelativeNeuro Correlative
Neuro Correlative
 
A critical engagment ab
A critical engagment abA critical engagment ab
A critical engagment ab
 
Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams
Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its DreamsReview of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams
Review of Raymond Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams
 
Patriarchal Society Essay.pdf
Patriarchal Society Essay.pdfPatriarchal Society Essay.pdf
Patriarchal Society Essay.pdf
 
A Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social Anthropology
A Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social AnthropologyA Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social Anthropology
A Student’s Guide to Reading and Writing in Social Anthropology
 
Is the sociology_of_deviance_still_relev
Is the sociology_of_deviance_still_relevIs the sociology_of_deviance_still_relev
Is the sociology_of_deviance_still_relev
 

Más de Laura Calle

Hall, Race, Culture and Comunications
Hall, Race, Culture and ComunicationsHall, Race, Culture and Comunications
Hall, Race, Culture and ComunicationsLaura Calle
 
Hall, The neoliberal revolution
Hall, The neoliberal revolutionHall, The neoliberal revolution
Hall, The neoliberal revolutionLaura Calle
 
Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel Laura Calle
 
Tomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcelTomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcelLaura Calle
 
Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel Laura Calle
 
Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel
Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel
Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel Laura Calle
 
Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel Laura Calle
 
Gramsci prison notebooks vol1
Gramsci prison notebooks vol1Gramsci prison notebooks vol1
Gramsci prison notebooks vol1Laura Calle
 
Reseña political anthropology swartz turner y tuden
Reseña political anthropology swartz turner y tudenReseña political anthropology swartz turner y tuden
Reseña political anthropology swartz turner y tudenLaura Calle
 
Antropología politica josé llobera
Antropología politica josé lloberaAntropología politica josé llobera
Antropología politica josé lloberaLaura Calle
 
Antropologia de los procesos politicos y del poder
Antropologia de los procesos politicos y del poderAntropologia de los procesos politicos y del poder
Antropologia de los procesos politicos y del poderLaura Calle
 
Antropología e poder
Antropología e poderAntropología e poder
Antropología e poderLaura Calle
 

Más de Laura Calle (12)

Hall, Race, Culture and Comunications
Hall, Race, Culture and ComunicationsHall, Race, Culture and Comunications
Hall, Race, Culture and Comunications
 
Hall, The neoliberal revolution
Hall, The neoliberal revolutionHall, The neoliberal revolution
Hall, The neoliberal revolution
 
Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 5 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
 
Tomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcelTomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
Tomo 4 Gramsci Cuadernos de la carcel
 
Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 3 Gramsci Cuadernos de la cárcel
 
Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel
Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel
Tomo 2 Gramsci - Cuadernos de la Cárcel
 
Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel
Tomo 1 Gramsci cuadernos de la cárcel
 
Gramsci prison notebooks vol1
Gramsci prison notebooks vol1Gramsci prison notebooks vol1
Gramsci prison notebooks vol1
 
Reseña political anthropology swartz turner y tuden
Reseña political anthropology swartz turner y tudenReseña political anthropology swartz turner y tuden
Reseña political anthropology swartz turner y tuden
 
Antropología politica josé llobera
Antropología politica josé lloberaAntropología politica josé llobera
Antropología politica josé llobera
 
Antropologia de los procesos politicos y del poder
Antropologia de los procesos politicos y del poderAntropologia de los procesos politicos y del poder
Antropologia de los procesos politicos y del poder
 
Antropología e poder
Antropología e poderAntropología e poder
Antropología e poder
 

Último

ACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdf
ACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdfACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdf
ACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdfSpandanaRallapalli
 
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Celine George
 
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptxJudging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptxSherlyMaeNeri
 
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERPWhat is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERPCeline George
 
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptxINTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptxHumphrey A Beña
 
Science 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptx
Science 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptxScience 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptx
Science 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptxMaryGraceBautista27
 
HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...
HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...
HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...Nguyen Thanh Tu Collection
 
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptxGas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptxDr.Ibrahim Hassaan
 
4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptx
4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptx4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptx
4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptxmary850239
 
THEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION
THEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATIONTHEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION
THEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATIONHumphrey A Beña
 
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTSGRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTSJoshuaGantuangco2
 
Barangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptx
Barangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptxBarangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptx
Barangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptxCarlos105
 
How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17
How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17
How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17Celine George
 
ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4
ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4
ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4MiaBumagat1
 
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Jisc
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxiammrhaywood
 
Q4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptx
Q4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptxQ4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptx
Q4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptxnelietumpap1
 

Último (20)

ACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdf
ACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdfACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdf
ACC 2024 Chronicles. Cardiology. Exam.pdf
 
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
Difference Between Search & Browse Methods in Odoo 17
 
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptxJudging the Relevance  and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
Judging the Relevance and worth of ideas part 2.pptx
 
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERPWhat is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
What is Model Inheritance in Odoo 17 ERP
 
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptxINTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
INTRODUCTION TO CATHOLIC CHRISTOLOGY.pptx
 
Science 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptx
Science 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptxScience 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptx
Science 7 Quarter 4 Module 2: Natural Resources.pptx
 
HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...
HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...
HỌC TỐT TIẾNG ANH 11 THEO CHƯƠNG TRÌNH GLOBAL SUCCESS ĐÁP ÁN CHI TIẾT - CẢ NĂ...
 
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptxGas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
Gas measurement O2,Co2,& ph) 04/2024.pptx
 
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdfTataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
 
4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptx
4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptx4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptx
4.18.24 Movement Legacies, Reflection, and Review.pptx
 
YOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
YOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptxYOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
YOUVE GOT EMAIL_FINALS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
 
THEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION
THEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATIONTHEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION
THEORIES OF ORGANIZATION-PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION
 
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTSGRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
GRADE 4 - SUMMATIVE TEST QUARTER 4 ALL SUBJECTS
 
LEFT_ON_C'N_ PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
LEFT_ON_C'N_ PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptxLEFT_ON_C'N_ PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
LEFT_ON_C'N_ PRELIMS_EL_DORADO_2024.pptx
 
Barangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptx
Barangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptxBarangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptx
Barangay Council for the Protection of Children (BCPC) Orientation.pptx
 
How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17
How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17
How to Add Barcode on PDF Report in Odoo 17
 
ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4
ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4
ANG SEKTOR NG agrikultura.pptx QUARTER 4
 
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
Procuring digital preservation CAN be quick and painless with our new dynamic...
 
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptxECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
ECONOMIC CONTEXT - PAPER 1 Q3: NEWSPAPERS.pptx
 
Q4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptx
Q4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptxQ4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptx
Q4 English4 Week3 PPT Melcnmg-based.pptx
 

Theory in anthropology since the sixties sherry ortner

  • 1. Theory in Anthropology since the Sixties Author(s): Sherry B. Ortner Source: Comparative Studies in Society and History, Vol. 26, No. 1 (Jan., 1984), pp. 126-166 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/178524 Accessed: 15/04/2010 21:25 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Comparative Studies in Society and History. http://www.jstor.org
  • 2. Theory in Anthropology since the Sixties SHERRY B. ORTNER Universityof Michigan Every year, aroundthe time of the meetings of the AmericanAnthropological Association, the New YorkTimes asks a Big Name anthropologist contrib- to ute an op-ed piece on the state of the field. These pieces tend to take a rather gloomy view. A few years ago, for example, Marvin Harrissuggested that anthropologywas being taken over by mystics, religious fanatics, and Cal- ifornia cultists; that the meetings were dominatedby panels on shamanism, witchcraft,and "abnormalphenomena";and that "scientific papersbased on empirical studies" had been willfully excluded from the program (Harris 1978). More recently, in a more sober tone, Eric Wolf suggestedthatthe field of anthropologyis coming apart. The sub-fields (and sub-sub-fields)are in- creasingly pursuingtheir specialized interests, losing contact with each other and with the whole. There is no longer a shared discourse, a shared set of termsto which all practitioners addressthemselves, a sharedlanguagewe all, however idiosyncratically, speak (Wolf 1980). The state of affairsdoes seem much as Wolf describesit. The field appears to be a thing of shredsand patches, of individualsand small coteries pursuing disjunctiveinvestigations and talking mainly to themselves. We do not even hear stirringargumentsany more. Although anthropologywas never actually unified in the sense of adoptinga single sharedparadigm,there was at least a period when there were a few large categories of theoreticalaffiliation, a set of identifiablecamps or schools, and a few simple epithets one could hurl at This essay contains much of my own intellectual history. There will be no more appropriate context in which to thank my teachers, Frederica de Laguna, Clifford Geertz, and David Schneiderfor having turnedme, for betteror for worse, into an anthropologist. addition,I wish In to thankthe following friends and colleagues for helpful contributions the developmentof this to essay: Nancy Chodorow, Salvatore Cucchiari, James Fernandez,Raymond Grew, Keith Hart, RaymondKelly, David Kertzer, RobertPaul, Paul Rabinow, Joyce Riegelhaupt,Anton Weiler, and HarrietWhitehead. Parts of this work were presentedat the Departmentof Anthropology, Princeton University; the Departmentof Social Anthropology, University of Stockholm; the Social Science History Seminar(founded and coordinatedby Charlesand Louise Tilly), Univer- sity of Michigan;the HumanitiesSeminar, StanfordUniversity;and the Seminaron Theory and Methods in ComparativeStudies (coordinatedby Neil Smelser) at the Universityof California, Berkeley. I received valuable comments and reactions in all of these contexts. 0010-4175/84/1709-0100 $2.50 ? 1984 Society for ComparativeStudy of Society and History 126
  • 3. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 127 one's opponents. Now there appears to be an apathy of spirit even at this level. We no longer call each other names. We are no longer sure of how the sides are to be drawnup, and of where we would place ourselves if we could identify the sides. Yet as anthropologistswe can recognize in all of this the classic symptoms of liminality-confusion of categories, expressions of chaos and antistruc- ture. And we know that such disordermay be the breedinggroundfor a new and perhapsbetterorder. Indeed, if one scrutinizesthe presentmore closely, one may even discern within it the shape of the new orderto come. That is" what I propose to do in this article. I will argue that a new key symbol of theoretical orientation is emerging, which may be labeled "practice" (or "action" or "praxis"). This is neither a theory nor a method in itself, but rather, as I said, a symbol, in the name of which a variety of theories and methods are being developed. In order to understand significance of this the trend, however, we must go back at least twenty years and see where we startedfrom, and how we got to where we are now. Before launching this enterprise, however, it is importantto specify its nature. This essay will be primarily concerned with the relations between various theoretical schools or approaches,both within periods of time, and across time. No single approachwill be exhaustivelyoutlinedor discussed in itself; rather,variousthemes or dimensionsof each will be highlightedinsofar as they relateto the largertrendsof thoughtwith which I am concerned.Every anthropologistwill probablyfind his or her favorite school oversimplified,if not outrightdistorted, insofar as I have choosen to emphasizefeaturesthatdo not correspondto what are normallytaken, among the practitioners,to be its most importanttheoretical features. Thus readers seeking more exhaustive discussions of particular approaches,and/or discussionspursuedfrom a point of view more interior to the approaches, will have to seek elsewhere. The concern here, again, is with elucidating relations. THE SIXTIES: SYMBOL, NATURE, STRUCTURE Although there is always some arbitrariness choosing a startingpoint for in any historicaldiscussion, I have decided to begin in the early 1960s. For one thing, that is when I started in the field, and since I generally assume the importanceof seeing any system, at least in part, from the actor's point of view, I might as well unite theory and practicefrom the outset. It is thus fully acknowledgedthatthis discussion proceedsnot from some hypotheticalexter- nal point, but from the perspective of this particularactor moving through anthropologybetween 1960 and the present. But actors always wish to claim universalityfor theirparticular experiences and interpretations.I would further suggest then that, in some relatively objective sense, there was in fact a majorset of revolutionsin anthropological theory, beginning in the early sixties. Indeed it appearsthat such revisionist
  • 4. 128 SHERRY B. ORTNER upheaval was characteristicof many other fields in that era. In literarycrit- icism, for example, by the 1960'sa volatilemixture linguistics, of psychoanalysis semiotics,struc- and turalism,Marxist and theory reception aesthetics begun replace oldermoral had to the humanism. literary The text tendedto move towards statusof phenomenon: the a and socio-psycho-culturo-linguisticideological event,arisingfromtheoffered compe- tenciesof language, available the taxonomies narrative of order,the permutations of optionsof structural genre,the sociological the formation, ideological constraints of the infra-structure.. . . [There was a] broad and contentious revisionist perception 1981:137). (Bradbury In anthropologyat the close of the fifties, the theoreticalbricoleur's kit consisted of threemajor, and somewhatexhausted,paradigms-British struc- tural-functionalism (descended from A. R. Radcliffe-Brownand Bronislaw Malinowski), Americanculturaland psychocultural anthropology (descended from MargaretMead, Ruth Benedict, et al.), and Americanevolutionist an- thropology (centered around Leslie White and Julian Steward, and having strong affiliations with archaeology). Yet it was also during the fifties that certain actors and cohorts central to our story were trainedin each of these areas. They emerged at the beginning of the sixties with aggressive ideas abouthow to strengthenthe paradigmsof their mentorsand ancestors,as well as with, apparently,much more combativestancesvis-a-vis the otherschools. It was this combination of new ideas and intellectual aggressiveness that launched the three movements with which this account begins: symbolic anthropology,culturalecology, and structuralism. SymbolicAnthropology "Symbolic anthropology" as a label was never used by any of its main proponentsin the formativeperiod-say, 1963-66. Ratherit was a shorthand tag (probablyinventedby the opposition), an umbrellafor a numberof rather diverse trends. Two of its major variantsappearto have been independently invented, one by Clifford Geertz and his colleagues at the University of Chicago, and the other by Victor Turner at Cornell.' The importantdif- ferences between the Geertzians and the Turneriansare probably not fully appreciated by those outside the symbolic anthropology scene. Whereas Geertz was primarilyinfluencedby Max Weber (via TalcottParsons),Turner was primarilyinfluenced by Emile Durkheim.Further,Geertz clearly repre- sents a transformationupon the earlier American anthropologyconcerned mainly with the operationsof "culture," while Turnerrepresentsa transfor- For the discussion of the sixties and the seventies, I will for the most partinvoke only the most representativefigures and works. In an articleof this length, many interestingdevelopments must be by-passed. One importantfigure of this period who gets left by the wayside is Gregory Bateson (e.g., 1972), who, though himself clearly a powerful and original thinker,never really founded a major school in anthropology.
  • 5. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES I29 mation upon the earlierBritish anthropologyconcernedmainly with the oper- ations of "society." Geertz's most radicaltheoreticalmove (1973b) was to arguethat cultureis not something locked inside people's heads, but ratheris embodiedin public symbols, symbols throughwhich the membersof a society communicatetheir worldview, value-orientations,ethos, and all the rest to one another,to future generations-and to anthropologists.With this formulation,Geertz gave the hithertoelusive concept of culture a relatively fixed locus, and a degree of objectivity, that it did not have before. The focus on symbols was for Geertz and many others heuristicallyliberating:it told them where to find what they wanted to study. Yet the point about symbols was that they were ultimately vehicles for meanings;the study of symbols as such was never an end in itself. Thus, on the one hand, Geertzians2have never been particularly interestedin distinguishing and cataloguingthe varietiesof symbolic types (signals, signs, icons, indexes, etcetera-see, in contrast, Singer 1980); nor, on the other hand (and in contrastwith Turnerto whom we will get in a moment), have they been particularly interestedin the ways in which symbols performcertain practicaloperations in the social process-heal people throughcuring rites, turn boys and girls into men and women through initiation, kill people throughsorcery-and so forth. Geertziansdo not ignore these practicalsocial effects, but such symbols have not been their primary focus of interest. Rather, the focus of Geertziananthropologyhas consistently been the ques- tion of how symbols shape the ways social actors see, feel, and think about the world, or, in other words, how symbols operateas vehicles of "'culture." It is furtherworth noting, in anticipationof the discussion of structuralism, that Geertz's heart has always been more with the "ethos" side of culture than with the "worldview," more with the affective and stylistic dimensions than with the cognitive. While of course it is very difficult (not to say unpro- ductive and ultimately wrong-headed)to separatethe two too sharply, it is nonetheless possible to distinguishan emphasis on one or the other side. For Geertz, then (as for Benedict, especially, before him), even the most cogni- tive or intellectualof culturalsystems-say, the Balinese calendars-are ana- lyzed not (only) to lay bare a set of cognitive orderingprinciples, but (es- pecially) to understandhow the Balinese way of chopping up time stamps their sense of self, of social relations, and of conduct with a particularcultur- ally distinctive flavor, an ethos (1973e).3 2 E.g., Ortner 1975; M. Rosaldo 1980; Blu 1980; Meeker 1979; Rosen 1978. 3 If culture itself had been an elusive phenomenon, one may say that Geertz has pursuedthe most elusive partof it, the ethos. It may also be suggested thatthis, among otherthings, accounts for his continuing and broad-basedappeal. Perhaps the majorityof students who go into an- thropology, and almost certainly the majorityof nonanthropologists who are fascinatedby our field, are drawn to it because they have been struck at some point in their experience by the "otherness" of anotherculture, which we would call its ethos. Geertz's workprovidesone of the very few handles for grasping that otherness.
  • 6. I30 SHERRY B. ORTNER The othermajorcontribution the Geertzianframework of was the insistence on studyingculture "from the actor'spoint of view" (e.g., 1975). Again, this does not imply that we must get "into people's heads." What it means, very simply, is thatcultureis a productof acting social beings tryingto make sense of the world in which they find themselves, and if we are to make sense of a culture, we must situate ourselves in the position from which it was con- structed. Culture is not some abstractlyordered system, deriving its logic from hidden structuralprinciples, or from special symbols that provide the "keys" to its coherence. Its logic-the principles of relations that obtain among its elements-derives ratherfrom the logic or organizationof action, from people operating within certain institutionalorders, interpretingtheir situations in order to act coherently within them (1973d). It may be noted here, however, that while the actor-centeredperspective is fundamentalto Geertz's framework,it is not systematicallyelaborated: Geertzdid not devel- op a theory of action or practice as such. He did, however, firmly plant the actor at the center of his model, and much of the laterpractice-centered work builds on a Geertzian(or Geertzo-Weberian) base, as we shall see. The othermajorfigure in the Chicago school of symbolic anthropology has been David Schneider. Schneider, like Geertz, was a productof Parsons,and he too concentratedprimarilyon refining the cultureconcept. But his efforts went toward understandingthe internal logic of systems of symbols and meanings, by way of a notion of "core symbols," and also by way of ideas akin to ClaudeLevi-Strauss'sconcept of structure (e.g., 1968, 1977). Indeed, although Geertz prominentlyused the phrase "cultural system" (emphasis added), he never paid much attentionto the systemic aspectsof culture,and it was Schneider who developed this side of the problem much more fully. Schneider in his own work cut culture off from social action much more radically than Geertz did. Yet, perhaps precisely because social action ("practice," "praxis") was so radically separated from "culture" in Schneider'swork, he and some of his studentswere among the earliestof the symbolic anthropologiststo see practice itself as a problem (Barnett 1977; Dolgin, Kemnitzer, and Schneider 1977). Victor Turner, finally, comes out of quite a different intellectual back- ground. He was trained in the Max Gluckmanvariantof British structural- functionalism,which was influencedby Marxism,and which stressedthatthe normalstate of society is not one of solidarityand harmoniousintegrationof parts, but ratherone of conflict and contradiction.Thus, the analyticquestion was not, as for the straightline descendantsof Durkheim, how solidarityis fine-tuned, reinforced, and intensified, but ratherhow it is constructedand maintainedin the first place over and above the conflicts and contradictions that constitute the normal state of affairs. To the Americanreader,this may appearto be only a minor varianton the basic functionalistproject, since for both schools the emphasis is on the maintenanceof integration,and specifi-
  • 7. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 131 cally on the maintenanceof the integrationof "society"-actors, groups, the social whole-as opposed to "culture." But Gluckman and his students (includingTurner)believed their differences from the mainstream be quite to deep. Moreover, they always constituteda minoritywithin the British estab- lishment. This backgroundmay account in partfor Turner'soriginalityvis-a- vis his compatriots,leading ultimatelyto his independentlyinventinghis own brandof an explicitly symbolic anthropology. Despite the relative novelty of Turner'smove to symbols, however, thereis in his work a deep continuity with British social anthropologicalconcerns, and, as a result, profounddifferences between Tumerianand Geertziansym- bolic anthropology.For Turner,symbols are of interestnot as vehicles of, and analytic windows onto, "culture"-the integratedethos and worldview of a society-but as what might be called operators in the social process, things that, when put togetherin certainarrangements certaincontexts (especially in rituals), produceessentially social transformations.Thus, symbols in Ndem- bu curingor initiationor huntingritualsare investigatedfor the ways in which they move actors from one status to another, resolve social contradictions, and wed actorsto the categories and normsof their society (1967). Along the way toward these rather traditional structural-functional goals, however, Turneridentified or elaboratedupon certainritual mechanisms, and some of the concepts he developed have become indispensablepartsof the vocabulary of ritualanalysis-liminality, marginality,antistructure, communitas,and so forth (1967, 1969).4 Turnerand the Chicago symbolic anthropologistsdid not so much conflict with one anotheras simply, for the most part, talk past one another.Yet the Turnerians5 added an important,and characteristically British, dimension to the field of symbolic anthropologyas a whole, a sense of the pragmatics of symbols. They investigated in much more detail than Geertz, Schneider, et al., the "effectiveness of symbols," the questionof how symbols actuallydo what all symbolic anthropologistsclaim they do: operate as active forces in the social process (see also Levi-Strauss 1963; Tambiah 1968; Lewis 1977; Fernandez 1974). In retrospect, one may say that symbolic anthropologyhad a numberof significant limitations. I refer not to the charges that it was unscientific, mystical, literary, soft-headed, and the like leveled at it by practitionersof culturalecology (see below). Rather, one may point to symbolic anthropol- 4 Anotherpoint of contrastbetween Turnerand Geertz is thatTurner's concept of meaning, at least in those early works that launchedhis approach,is largely referential.Meanings are things that symbols point to or refer to, like "matriliny" or "blood." Geertz, on the other hand, is primarilyconcernedwith what might be called Meaning, with a capitalM-the purpose,or point, or largersignificance of things. Thus he quotes NorthropFrye: "You wouldn't go to Macbethto learnaboutthe history of Scotland-you go to it to learnwhat a man feels like afterhe's gained a kingdom and lost his soul" (Geertz 1973f:450). 5 E.g., Munn 1969; Myerhoff 1974; Moore and Myerhoff 1975; Babcock 1978.
  • 8. 132 SHERRY B. ORTNER ogy's lack, especially in its American form, of a systematic sociology; its underdeveloped sense of the politics of culture; and its lack of curiosity concerning the production and maintenance of symbolic systems. These points will be discussed more fully in the course of this article. CulturalEcology6 Culturalecology representeda new synthesis of, and a furtherdevelopment upon, the materialistevolutionismof Leslie White (1943, 1949), JulianStew- ard (1953, 1955), and V. Gordon Childe (1942). Its roots go back to Lewis HenryMorganand E. B. Tylor in the nineteenthcentury, and ultimatelyback to Marx and Engels, although many of the 1950s evolutionists, for under- standable political reasons, were not encouraged to emphasize the Marxist connection.7 White had been investigating what came to be labeled "general evolu- tion," or the evolution of culture-in-general,in terms of stages of social complexity and technological advancement.These stages were subsequently refinedby Elman Service (1958), and by MarshallSahlins and ElmanService (1960), into the famous bands-tribes-chiefdoms-states scheme. The evolu- tionary mechanisms in White's frameworkderived from more or less for- tuitous events: technological inventionsthat allowed for the greater "capture of energy," and populationgrowth (and perhapswarfareand conquest) that stimulatedthe developmentof more complex forms of social/political organi- zation and coordination.Steward(1953) attackedboth the focus on the evolu- tion of culture-in-general opposed to specific cultures), and the lack of a (as more systematically operative evolutionarymechanism. Instead, he empha- sized that specific culturesevolve their specific forms in the process of adapt- ing to specific environmentalconditions, and that the apparentuniformityof to evolutionarystages is actually a matterof similaradaptations similarnatu- ral conditions in different parts of the world. If the idea thatculturewas embodied in public, observablesymbols was the key to the liberationof symbolic anthropologyfrom earlierAmericancultural anthropology,the concept that played a similar role in culturalecology was "adaptation." (See Alland 1975 for a summary.) Just as Geertz had trum- peted that the study of culture as embodied in symbols removedthe problem of getting inside people's heads, so Sahlins proclaimedthe focus on adapta- tion to environmentalfactors as the way aroundsuch amorphousfactors as cultural gestalten and historical dialectics (1964). There was a large-scale rejection of the study of the inner workings of both culturein the American sense and society in the British sense. Internaldynamicswere seen as hardto 6 This section is partly based on readings, partly on semiformalinterviews with ConradP. Kottak and Roy A. Rappaport, and partly on general discussions with Raymond C. Kelly. Absolution is extended to all of the informants. 7 White and Childe were fairly explicit about the Marxist influence on their work.
  • 9. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 133 measure, and even harder to choose among for purposes of assigning causal primacy, whereas external factors of natural and social environment were amenable to treatment as fixed, measurable, "independent variables:" For decades, centuries now, intellectual battle has been given over which sector of culture is the decisive one for change. Many have entered the lists under banners diverse. Curiously, few seem to fall. Leslie White championstechnologicalgrowthas the sector most responsible for culturalevolution; Julian Huxley, with many others, sees "man's view of destiny" as the deciding force; the mode of productionand the class struggle are still very much in contention. Different as they are, these positions agree in one respect, that the impulse to developmentis generatedfrom within .... The case for internalcauses of developmentmay be bolsteredby pointingto a mecha- nism, such as the Hegelian dialectic, or it may rest more insecurely on an argument from logic. ... In any event, an unreal and vulnerableassumptionis always there, that culturesare closed systems. . . . It is precisely on this point that culturalecology offers a new perspective. . . . [I]t shifts attentionto the relationbetween inside and outside; it envisions as the mainspringof the evolutionarymovement the interchange between culture and environment.Now which view shall prevail is not to be decided on a sheet of paper. . . . But if adaptationwins over inner dynamism, it will be for certain intrinsic and obvious strengths. Adaptation is real, naturalistic, anchored to those historic contexts of cultures that inner dynamism ignores (Sahlins 1964:135-36).8 The Sahlins and Service version of cultural ecology, which was also ad- hered to by the mainstream of the archaeology wing of anthropology, was still fundamentally evolutionist. The primary use of the adaptation concept was in explaining the development, maintenance, and transformation of social forms. But there was another variant of cultural ecology, which developed slightly later, and which came to dominate the materialist wing in the sixties. Its position, expressed most forcefully by Marvin Harris (e.g., 1966) and perhaps most elegantly by Roy Rappaport (1967), drew heavily on systems theory. It shifted the analytic focus away from evolution, and toward explain- ing the existence of particular bits of particular cultures in terms of the adaptive or system-maintaining functions of those bits. Thus, the Maring kaiko ritual prevented the degradation of the natural environment (Rappaport 1967), the Kwakiutl potlatch maintained a balance of food distribution over tribal segments (Piddocke 1969), and the sacredness of the cow in India protected a vital link in the agricultural food chain (Harris 1966). In these studies, the interest has shifted from how the environment stimulates (or prevents) the development of social and cultural forms to the question of the ways in which social and cultural forms function to maintain an existing relationship with the environment. It was these latter sorts of studies that came to represent cultural ecology as a whole in the sixties. One would have had to be particularly out of touch with anthropological 8 This was the programmatic position. In practice, Sahlins did pay a good deal of attentionto internal social dynamics.
  • 10. 134 SHERRY B. ORTNER theory at the time not to have been awareof the acrimoniousdebate between the culturalecologists and the symbolic anthropologists. Whereasthe cultural ecologists considered the symbolic anthropologiststo be fuzzy-headedmen- talists, involved in unscientific and unverifiable flights of subjective in- terpretation,the symbolic anthropologistsconsidered culturalecology to be involved with mindless and sterile scientism, countingcalories and measuring rainfall, and willfully ignoring the one truththat anthropologyhad presum- ably establishedby that time: that culture mediates all humanbehavior. The Manichean struggle between "materialism" and "idealism," "hard" and "soft" approaches, interpretive "emics" and explanatory "etics," domi- nated the field for a good part of the decade of the sixties, and in some quarterswell into the seventies. That most of us thought and wrote in terms of such oppositions may be partly rooted in more pervasive schemes of Western thought: subjective/ objective, nature/culture,mind/body, and so on. The practice of fieldwork itself may furthercontributeto such thinking,based as it is on the paradoxical injunctionto participateand observe at one and the same time. It may be then that this sort of polarized construction of the intellectual landscape in an- thropologyis too deeply motivated, by both culturalcategoriesand the forms of practiceof the trade, to be completely eliminated. But the emic/etic strug- gle of the sixties had a numberof unfortunate effects, not the least of which was the preventionof adequateself-criticismon both sides of the fence. Both schools could luxuriatein the faults of the other, and not inspect their own houses for seriousweaknesses. In fact, both sides were weak not only in being unable to handle what the other side did (the symbolic anthropologistsin renouncingall claims to "explanation," the culturalecologists in losing sight of the frames of meaning within which humanaction takes place); both were also weak in what neither of them did, which was much of any systematic sociology.9 Indeed, from the point of view of British social anthropology,the whole American struggle was quite meaningless, since it seemed to leave out the necessary central term of all proper anthropologicaldiscussion: society. Where were the social groups, social relationships, social structures,social institutions, that mediate both the ways in which people think ("culture") and the ways in which people experienceand act upontheirenvironment? But this set of questions could not be answered (had anybody bothered to ask them) in terms of British social anthropological categories, because the Brit- ish were having their own intellectualupheavals, to which we will returnin due course. 9 The early Turneris a partialexception to this point, but most of his successors are not.
  • 11. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 135 Structuralism Structuralism, the more-or-less single-handed invention of Claude Levi- Strauss, was the only genuinely new paradigmto be developed in the sixties. One might even say that it is the only genuinely original social science paradigm(and humanitiestoo, for that matter)to be developed in the twen- tieth century. Drawing on linguistics and communicationtheory, and consid- ering himself influenced by both Marx and Freud, Levi-Straussarguedthat the seemingly bewilderingvariety of social and culturalphenomenacould be renderedintelligible by demonstratingthe sharedrelationshipsof those phe- nomena to a few simple underlying principles. He sought to establish the universal grammarof culture, the ways in which units of culturaldiscourse are created(by the principleof binaryopposition), and the rules accordingto which the units (pairs of opposed terms) are arrangedand combined to pro- duce the actual cultural productions (myths, marriage rules, totemic clan arrangements, the like) thatanthropologists and record.Culturesareprimarily systems of classification, as well as the sets of institutionaland intellectual productionsbuilt upon those systems of classification and performingfurther operations upon them. One of the most importantsecondary operationsof culture in relation to its own taxonomies is precisely to mediate or reconcile the oppositions which are the bases of those taxonomies in the first place. In practice, structuralanalysis consists of sifting out the basic sets of oppositions that underlie some complex cultural phenomenon-a myth, a ritual, a marriage system-and of showing the ways in which the phe- nomenon in question is both an expression of those contrastsand a reworking of them, therebyproducinga culturallymeaningfulstatementof, or reflection upon, order. Even without the full analysis of a myth or ritual, however, the sheer enumerationof the importantsets of oppositionsin a cultureis takento be a useful enterprisebecause it reveals the axes of thought, and the limits of the thinkable,within that andrelatedcultures(e.g., Needham 1973b). But the fullest demonstrationof the power of structuralanalysis is seen in Levi- Strauss's four-volume study, Mythologiques (1964-71). Here the method allows the orderingof data both on a vast scale (includingmost of indigenous South America, and partsof native North Americaas well), and also in terms of explicating myriad tiny details-why the jaguar covers his mouth when laughing or why honey metaphorsdescribe the escape of game animals. The combinationof wide scope and minute detail is what lends the work its great power. Much has been made of the point that Levi-Straussultimatelygroundsthe structures discernsbeneathsociety and culturein the structure the mind. he of Both the point itself, and the criticism of it, are perhapssomewhatirrelevant for anthropologists. It seems incontrovertiblethat all humans, and all cul- tures, classify. This suggests in turnan innatementalpropensityof some sort,
  • 12. 136 SHERRY B. ORTNER but it does not mean that any particular scheme of classificationis inevitable, no more than the fact that all humanseat motivates some universalsystem of food categories. The enduringcontributionof Levi-Straussianstructuralism in the per- lies ception that luxuriantvariety, even apparent randomness,may have a deeper unity and systematicity, derived from the operation of a small number of underlyingprinciples. It is in this sense that Levi-Straussclaims affinity with Marx and Freud, who similarlyarguethatbeneaththe surfaceproliferation of forms, a few relatively simple and relatively uniformmechanismsare operat- ing (DeGeorge and DeGeorge 1972). Such a perception,in turn, allows us to distinguishmuch more clearly between simple transformations, which operate within a given structure,and real change, revolutionif you will, in which the structureitself is transformed.Thus, despite the naturalisticor biologistic base of structuralism,and despite Levi-Strauss's personal predilection for considering that plus ca change, plus c'est la meme chose, the theory has always had importantimplications for a much more historicaland/or evolu- tionary anthropologythan that practiced by the master. The work of Louis Dumont in particularhas developed some of these evolutionaryimplications in analyzingthe structure the Indiancaste system, and in articulating of some of the profound structuralchanges involved in the transitionfrom caste to class (1965, 1970; see also Goldman 1970, Barnett 1977, Sahlins 1981).10 Structuralism was never all that popularamong Americananthropologists. Although it was seen at first (mostly by the culturalecologists) as a variantof symbolic anthropology, its central assumptions were in fact ratherdistant from those of the symbolic anthropologists(with the partialexception of the Schneiderians).There were a numberof reasons for this, which can be only very briefly sketched:(1) the very pure cognitive emphasisof Levi-Strauss's notion of meaning, as againstthe Americans' interestin ethos and values; (2) Levi-Strauss'sratheraustereemphasis on arbitrariness meaning (all mean- of ing is established by contrasts, nothing carries any meaning in itself), as against the Americans' interest in relations between the forms of symbolic constructs and the contents for which they are vehicles;" and (3) the ex- plicitly abstractlocus of structures,divorced in every way from the actions and intentionsof actors, as against the symbolic anthropologists'fairly con- sistent, if variably defined, actor-centrism(again, Schneider is a partialex- ception to this point). For all these reasons, and probablymore, structuralism was not as much embracedby American symbolic anthropologistsas might 10 Dumont is anotherof those figures who deserve more space than can be affordedhere. 11 This is not to imply that Americansymbolic anthropologists deny the doctrineof arbitrari- ness of symbols. But they do insist that the choice of a particularsymbolic form among several possible, equally arbitrary,symbols for the same conception, is not only not arbitrary, has but importantimplications that must be investigated.
  • 13. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 137 have appearedlikely at first glance.12 It was grantedwhat might be called fictive kinship status, largely because of its tendency to focus on some of the same domains that symbolic anthropologists took as their own-myth, ritual, etiquette, and so forth. The main impactof structuralism outside of Francewas in England,among some of the more adventurousBritish social anthropologists(see especially Leach 1966). Levi-Straussand the British were in fact more truly kin to one another,bornof two lines of descent from Durkheim.In any event, structural- ism in the British context underwenta numberof important transformations. Avoiding the question of mind, and of universal structures, British an- thropologistsprimarilyapplied structuralanalysis to particularsocieties and particularcosmologies (e.g., Leach 1966, 1969; Needham 1973a; Yalman 1969; the point also applies to Dumont (1970) in France). They also focused in more detail on the process of mediation of oppositions, and produceda number of quite original ruminationsupon anomaly and antistructure,es- pecially Mary Douglas's Purity and Danger (see also Turner 1967, 1969; Leach 1964; Tambiah 1969). However, there was also an importantway in which many of the British purgedstructuralism one of its more radicalfeatures-the eradication the of of Durkheimiandistinctionbetween the social "base" and the cultural "reflec- tion" of it. Levi-Strausshad claimed thatif mythic structures paralleledsocial structures,it was not because myth reflected society, but because both myth and social organizationshared a common underlyingstructure.Many of the British structuralists (Rodney Needham is the majorexception), on the other hand, went back to a position more in the traditionof Durkheimand Marcel Mauss, and considered myth and ritual as reflecting and resolving "at the symbolic level" oppositions taken to be fundamentallysocial.'3 As long as British structuralism confined to the study of myth andritual,then, it was was possible for it to fit nicely into British anthropologywithout having a very profoundeffect upon it. It became their version of culturalor symbolic an- thropology, their theory of superstructure. was only later, when a structural It (i.e., structural-Marxist) eye was turned on the British concept of social structureitself, that the sparksbegan to fly. In a numberof fields-linguistics, philosophy, history-there was a strong reaction against structuralismby the early seventies. Two interrelatedfea- tures-the denial of the relevance of an intentionalsubject in the social and 12 James Boon (e.g., 1972) has devoted a fair amount of effort to reconciling Levi-Strauss and/or Schneideron the one side, with Geertz on the other. The outcome is generallyheavily in favor of structuralism.(See also Boon and Schneider 1974.) 13 Levi-Strauss himself movedfrom a Durkheim/Maussposition in "La Geste d'Asdiwal" (1967) to the more radicalstructuralist position in Mythologiques.It is no accidentthatLeach, or whoever made the decision, chose to present "La Geste d'Asdiwal" as the lead essay in the British collection, The StructuralStudy of Myth and Totemism(1967).
  • 14. 138 SHERRY B. ORTNER cultural process, and the denial of any significant impact of history or "event" upon structure-were felt to be particularly problematic,not to say unacceptable. Scholars began to elaboratealternativemodels, in which both agents and events played a more active role. These models did not, however, get much play in anthropology until the late seventies, and they will be discussed in the final section of the essay. In anthropology duringmost of that decade, structuralism itself, with all its flaws (and virtues), became the basis of one of the dominantschools of theory, structural Marxism.We move now to that decade. THE SEVENTIES: MARX The anthropologyof the 1970s was much more obviously and transparently tied to real-worldevents than that of the precedingperiod. Startingin the late 1960s, in both the United States and France (less so in England), radical social movements emerged on a vast scale. First came the counterculture, then the antiwarmovement, and then, just a bit later, the women's movement: these movements not only affected the academic world, they originatedin good part within it. Everythingthat was part of the existing orderwas ques- tioned and criticized. In anthropology,the earliest critiquestook the form of denouncing the historical links between anthropologyon the one hand, and colonialism and imperialismon the other (e.g., Asad 1973, Hymes 1974). But this merely scratchedthe surface. The issue quickly moved to the deeper question of the natureof our theoreticalframeworks,and especially the de- gree to which they embody and carry forwardthe assumptionsof bourgeois Western culture. The rallying symbol of the new criticism, and of the theoreticalalternatives offered to replace the old models, was Marx. Of all the great nineteenth- century antecedentsof moder social science, Marx had been conspicuously absent from the mainstreamtheoreticalrepertoire.Parsons'sStructureof So- cial Action, one of the sacred texts of the Harvard-trained symbolic an- thropologists, surveyed the thought of Durkheim and Weber, and of two economic theorists, Alfred Marshalland Vilfredo Pareto,whose main signifi- cance in that context seemed to be that they were Not Marx. The British, including both the symbolic anthropologistsand the structuralists, were still firmly embeddedin Durkheim.Levi-Straussclaimed to have been influenced by Marx, but it took a while for anyone to figure out what he meantby that. Even the culturalecologists, the only self-proclaimedmaterialistsof the six- ties, hardlyinvoked Marx at all; indeed MarvinHarrisspecifically repudiated him (1968). One does not need to be an especially subtle analyst of the ideological aspects of intellectual history to realize that the absence of a significantMarxistinfluence before the seventies was just as much a reflex of real-worldpolitics as was the emergence of a strongMarxistinfluence in the seventies.
  • 15. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES I39 There were at least two distinct Marxistschools of anthropological theory: structuralMarxism, developed mainly in France and England, and political economy, which emerged first in the United States, and later in Englandas well. There was also a movement that might be called cultural Marxism, workedout largely in historicaland literarystudies, but this was not pickedup by anthropologistsuntil recently, and will be addressedin the final section of the essay. Structural Marxism Structural Marxismwas the only one of the schools developed entirelywithin the field of anthropology,and probablyfor thatreasonwas also the earliestin its impact. Within it, Marx was used to attackand/or rethink, or at the very least to expand, virtually every theoretical scheme on the landscape-sym- bolic anthropology,culturalecology, British social anthropology,and struc- turalism itself. StructuralMarxism constituted a would-be total intellectual revolution, and if it did not succeed in establishingitself as the only alterna- tive to everything else we had, it certainly succeeded in shaking up most of the received wisdom. This is not to say that it was necessarily the actual writingsof the structural Marxiststhemselves (e.g., Althusser1971; Godelier 1977; Terray 1972; Sahlins 1972; Friedman1975) that had this effect; it was simply that structural Marxismwas the originalforce within anthropology for promulgating and legitimating "Marx," "Marxism," and "critical inquiry" in the discourse of the field as a whole (see also Diamond 1979). The specific advance of structuralMarxism over its antecedentforms of materialistanthropologylay in its locating the determinative forces not in the natural environment and/or in technology, but specifically within certain structuresof social relations. Ecological considerationswere not excluded, but they were encompassedby and subordinated the analysis of the social, to and especially political, organization of production. Culturalecology was thus attacked as "vulgar materialism," reinforcingratherthan undoing the classical capitalist fetishization of "things," the dominationof subjects by objects ratherthan by the social relations embodied in, and symbolized by, those objects (see especially Friedman1974). The critical social relationsin question, referredto as the mode(s) of production,are not to be confusedwith the surface organization of social relations traditionallystudied by British social anthropologists-lineages, clans, moieties, and all the rest. These sur- face forms of what the British called "social structure"are seen as native models of social organizationthat have been boughtby anthropologists the as real thing, but that actually mask, or at least only partiallycorrespondto, the hiddenasymmetricalrelationsof productionthataredrivingthe system. Here, then, was situated the critique of traditionalBritish social anthropology(see especially Bloch 1971, 1974, 1977; Terray 1975). In addition to critiquing and revising both cultural ecology and British
  • 16. 140 SHERRY B. ORTNER social anthropology,structural Marxiststurnedtheir attentionto culturalphe- nomena. Unlike the culturalecologists, the structural Marxistsdid not dismiss cultural beliefs and native categories as irrelevantto the real or objective operations of society, nor, alternatively, did they set about to show that apparentlyirrationalcultural beliefs, such as the sacred cow, actually had practical adaptive functions. Just as the New Left in the real world took culturalissues (life style, consciousness) more seriouslythanthe Old Left had done, so the structuralMarxists allocated to cultural phenomena (beliefs, values, classifications)at least one centralfunctionin theirmodel of the social process. Specifically, culture was convertedto "ideology," and considered from the point of view of its role in social reproduction:legitimating the existing order, mediating contradictions in the base, and mystifying the sources of exploitationand inequalityin the system (O'Laughlin1974; Bloch 1977; Godelier 1977). One of the virtues of structural Marxism, then, was that there was a place for everything in its scheme. Refusing to see inquiriesinto materialrelations and into "ideology" as opposed enterprises, its practitionersestablished a model in which the two "levels" were related to one anothervia a core of social/political/economic processes. In this sense, they offered an explicit mediation between the "materialist" and "idealist" camps of sixties an- thropology. The mediation was rathermechanical, as we will discuss in a moment, but it was there. More important,to my mind, the structural Marxistsput a relativelypower- ful sociology back into the picture. They cross-fertilizedBritish social an- thropologicalcategories with Marxistones, and producedan expandedmodel of social organization("mode of production")which they then proceededto apply systematicallyto particular cases. WhereasotherMarxismsemphasized relations of political/economic organization ("production") almost ex- clusively, the structuralMarxists were, after all, anthropologists,trainedto pay attentionto kinship, descent, marriage,exchange, domesticorganization, and the like. They thus includedthese elements within theirconsiderationsof political and economic relations (often giving them a more Marxist ring by calling them "relations of reproduction")and the total effect was to produce rich and complex pictures of the social process in specific cases. Given the relative paucity, mentioned earlier, of detailed sociological analysis in the various sixties schools, this was an importantcontribution. All this having been said, one may nonetheless recognize that structural Marxism had a number of problems. For one thing, the narrowingof the culture concept to "ideology," which had the powerful effect of allowing analysts to connect culturalconceptions to specific structuresof social rela- tion, was too extreme, and posed the problem of relating ideology back to more general conceptions of culture. For another, the tendency to see cul- ture/ideology largely in terms of mystification gave most of the culturalor
  • 17. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 141 ideological studies in this school a decided functionalist flavor, since the upshot of these analyses was to show how myth, ritual, taboo, or whatever maintainedthe status quo. Finally, and most seriously, although structural Marxists offered a way of mediating the materialand ideological "levels," they did not actually challenge the notion that such levels are analytically distinguishable in the first place. Thus despite criticizing the Durkheimian (and Parsonian)notion of "the social" as the "base" of the system, they merely offered a deeper and allegedly more real and objective "base." And despite attemptingto discover more importantfunctions for the "superstruc- ture" (or despite claiming that what is base and what is superstructure varies culturally and/or historically, or even occasionally and rathervaguely thatthe superstructure part of the base) they continuedto reproducethe idea that it is is useful to maintainsuch a set of analytic boxes. In this sense, it may be seen that structural Marxism was still very much rooted in the sixties. While it injected a healthy dose of sociology into the earlier scheme of categories, and while this sociology was itself relatively originally conceived, the basic pigeonholes of sixties thoughtwere not radi- cally revised. Further, unlike the political economy school and other more recent approaches to be discussed shortly, structuralMarxism was largely nonhistorical,a factor which, again, tied it to earlierforms of anthropology. Indeedone may guess thatit was in partthis comfortablemix of old categories and assumptions wrapped up in a new critical rhetoricthat made structural Marxism so appealing in its day. It was in many ways the perfect vehicle for academics who had been trainedin an earlierera, but who, in the seventies, were feeling the pull of critical thought and action that was exploding all around them. Political Economy The political economy school has taken its inspirationprimarilyfrom world- systems and underdevelopmenttheories in political sociology (Wallerstein 1976; GunderFrank 1967). In contrastto structural Marxism, which focused largely, in the mannerof conventional anthropologicalstudies, on relatively discrete societies or cultures, the political economists have shiftedthe focus to large-scale regional political/economic systems (e.g., Hart 1982). Insofaras they have attemptedto combine this focus with traditional fieldworkin specif- ic communitiesor microregions,theirresearchhas generallytakenthe formof studying the effects of capitalist penetrationupon those communities (e.g., AmericanEthnologist 1978; Schneiderand Schneider1976). The emphasison the impact of external forces, and on the ways in which societies change or evolve largely in adaptationto such impact, ties the political economy school in certain ways to the culturalecology of the sixties, and indeed many of its currentpractitioners were trainedin thatschool (e.g., Ross 1980). But where- as for sixties cultural ecology, often studying relatively "primitive" so-
  • 18. 142 SHERRY B. ORTNER cieties, the importantexternal forces were those of the naturalenvironment, for the seventies political economists, generally studying "peasants," the important externalforces are those of the state andthe capitalistworld system. At the level of theory, the political economists differ from their cultural ecology forebearspartly in showing a greaterwillingness to incorporate cul- tural or symbolic issues into their inquiries (e.g., Schneider 1978; Riegelhaupt 1978). Specifically, their work tends to focus on symbols in- volved in the developmentof class or group identity, in the context of politi- cal/economic struggles of one sort or another.The political economy school thus overlaps with the burgeoning "ethnicity" industry,althoughthe litera- ture in the latter field is too vast and too amorphousfor me to do more than nod to here. In any event, the willingness of the political economists to pay attention,in however circumscribedfashion, to symbolic processes, is partof the general relaxation of the old materialism/idealismwars of the sixties. The emphasisof this school upon largerregionalprocesses is also salutary, at least up to a point. Anthropologistsdo have a tendency to treat societies, even villages, as if they were islands unto themselves, with little sense of the largersystems of relationsin which these units are embedded.The occasional work (e.g., EdmundLeach's Political Systems of Highland Burma) that has viewed societies in larger regional context has been something of an un- classifiable (if admired) freak. To ignore the fact that peasants are part of states, and that even "primitive" societies and communitiesare invariably involved in wider systems of exchanges of all sorts, is to seriouslydistortthe data, and it is the virtueof the political economiststhatthey remindus of this. Finally, the political economists must be given leading credit for stressing very strongly the importanceof history for anthropologicalstudy. They are not the first to have done so, nor are they the only ones doing so now, and I will say more aboutanthropology'srapprochement with historyin the conclu- sions of this essay. Nonetheless, it is certainlythe membersof this school who appear the most committed to a fully historical anthropology,and who are producing sustained and systematic work groundedin this commitment. On the negative side of the ledger, we may complainfirst that the political economy model is too economic, too strictlymaterialist.One hearsa lot about wages, the market, the cash nexus, economic exploitation, underdevelop- ment, and so forth, but not enough aboutthe relationsof power, domination, manipulation,control, and the like which those economic relationsplay into, and which for actors constitute much of the experienced pain of economic injustice. Political economy, in other words, is not political enough. My main objection, however, is located deeper in the theoreticalmodel of political economy. Specifically, I find the capitalism-centered view of the world questionable, to say the least, especially for anthropology.At the core of the model is the assumptionthat virtuallyeverythingwe study has already been touched ("penetrated") by the capitalist world system, and that there-
  • 19. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES I43 fore much of what we see in our fieldwork and describe in our monographs must be understoodas having been shapedin responseto that system. Perhaps this is true for Europeanpeasants, but even here one would want at least to leave the question open. When we get even further from the "center," however, the assumptionbecomes very problematicindeed. A society, even a village, has its own structureand history, and this must be as muchpartof the analysis as its relations with the largercontext within which it operates. (See Joel Kahn (1980) for a more balanced view.) The problems derived from the capitalism-centered worldview also affect the political economists' view of history. Historyis often treatedas something that arrives, like a ship, from outside the society in question. Thus we do not get the history of that society, but the impact of (our) history on that society. The accounts producedfrom such a perspectiveare often quite unsatisfactory in terms of traditionalanthropologicalconcerns: the actual organizationand cultureof the society in question. Traditionalstudies of course had their own problemswith respect to history. They often presentedus with a thin chapter on "historical background" at the beginning and an inadequatechapteron "social change" at the end. The political economy study invertsthis relation- ship, but only to create the inverse problem. The political economists, moreover, tend to situatethemselves more on the ship of (capitalist) history than on the shore. They say in effect that we can never know what the other system, in its unique, "traditional," aspects, really looked like anyway. By realizing that much of what we see as tradition is in fact a responseto Westernimpact, so the argumentgoes, we not only get a more accuratepictureof what is going on, but we acknowledgeat the same time the perniciouseffects of our own system upon others. Such a view is also present, but in modes of anger and/or despair ratherthan pragmatism,in a number of recent works that question philosophically whether we can ever truly know the "other"-Edward Said's Orientalismis the prime example (see also Rabinow 1977; Crapanzano1980; Riesman 1977). To such a position we can only respond:try. The effort is as important as the results, in terms of both our theories and our practices. The attemptto view other systems from groundlevel is the basis, perhapsthe only basis, of anthropology'sdistinctive contribution the humansciences. It is our capac- to ity, largely developed in fieldwork, to take the perspectiveof the folks on the shore, that allows us to learn anything at all-even in our own culture- beyond what we alreadyknow. (Indeed, as more and more anthropologists are doing fieldwork in Westerncultures, including the United States, the impor- tance of maintaininga capacity to see otherness, even next door, becomes more and more acute.) Further,it is our location "on the ground"thatputs us in a position to see people not simply as passive reactorsto and enactorsof some "system," but as active agents and subjects in their own history. In concluding this section, I must confess thatmy placementof the political
  • 20. 144 SHERRY B. ORTNER economy school in the seventies is somethingof an ideological move. In fact political economy is very much alive and well in the eighties, and it will probably thrive for some time. My periodization is thus, like that of all histories, only partly related to real time. I have included political economy and structural Marxismwithin this period/categorybecauseboth schools con- tinue to share a set of assumptionsdistinctfrom what I wish to emphasizefor the anthropologyof the eighties. Specifically, both assume, together with earlier anthropologies, that human action and historical process are almost entirely structurallyor systemically determined. Whether it be the hidden hand of structureor the juggernautof capitalismthat is seen as the agent of society/history, it is certainly not in any central way real people doing real things. These are precisely the views from which at least some anthropolo- gists, as well as practitionersin many other fields, appearto be strugglingto break free as we move into the present decade. INTO THE EIGHTIES: PRACTICE I began this article by noting the apparentaccuracyof Wolf's remarksto the effect that the field of anthropologyis disintegrating,even grantingthe low degree of integrationit had in the past. I also suggested that one could find scattered over the landscape the elements of a new trend that seems to be gatheringforce and coherence. In this final section I call attentionto this new trend, sketch it, and subject it to a preliminarycritique. For the past several years, there has been growing interest in analysis focused through one or anotherof a bundle of interrelatedterms: practice, praxis, action, interaction,activity, experience, performance.A second, and closely related, bundle of terms focuses on the doer of all that doing: agent, actor, person, self, individual, subject. In some fields, movement in this direction began relatively early in the seventies, some of it in direct reaction to structuralism.In linguistics, for example, there was an early rejection of structurallinguistics and a strong move to view language as communicationand performance(e.g., Bauman and Sherzer 1974; Cole and Morgan 1975). In anthropologytoo there were scatteredcalls for a more action based approach.In France, PierreBourdieu published his Outline of a Theory of Practice in 1972. In the United States, Geertz attacked both hypercoherentstudies of symbolic systems (many of them inspiredby his own programmatic papers)and what he saw as the sterile formalismof structuralism, calling insteadfor anthropologists see "human to behavior . . as . . . symbolic action" (1973a:10; see also Dolgin, Kem- nitzer, and Schneider 1977; Wagner 1975; T. Turner1969). In England,there was a minoritywing thatcriticizedtraditionalviews of "social structure"not from the point of view of structuralMarxism, but from the perspective of individualchoice and decision making (e.g., Kapferer1976).14 14 The transactionalist tradition in British anthropology may of course be traced back further,
  • 21. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 145 For much of the seventies, however, the structural Marxistsand, later, the political economists, remained dominant, at least within anthropology.For them, social and culturalphenomena were to be explained largely by being referredto systemic/structural mechanismsof one sort or another.It was only in the late seventies that the hegemony of structuralMarxism, if not that of political economy, began to wane. An English translation Bourdieu'sbook of was published in 1978, and it was at aboutthat time that the calls for a more practice-orientedapproachbecame increasingly audible. Here is a sampler: The instruments reasoning changing societyis less andless represented of are and as anelaborate machine a quasi-organism as a serious or than game,a sidewalk drama,or a behavioral (Geertz1980a:168). text We needto watchthesesystems[of kinship] action,to studytacticsandstrategy, in not merelythe rulesof the game(Barnes1980:301). ? . . genderconceptions in any society are to be understoodas functioningaspectsof a cultural whichactors systemthrough manipulate, and legitimize, reproduce interpret, the patterns . . . that order their social world (Collier and Rosaldo 1981:311).'5 Whatdo actorswantandhow canthey get it? (Ortner 1981:366) If structural/semiotic analysis to be extended general is to anthropology themodel on of its pertinence "language," whatis lostis notmerely to then and history change, but practice-humanactionin the world. Some mightthinkthatwhat is lost is what anthropology all about(Sahlins1981:6). is As was the case with the strong revisionist trendin the sixties, the present movement appears much broader than the field of anthropologyalone. In linguistics, Alton Becker, in a much-cited article, has emphasizedissues of text building over and against reification of The Text (1979). In spciology, symbolic interactionismand other forms of so-called microsociology appear to be attractingnew attention,16 and Anthony Giddens has dubbedthe rela- tionship between structureand "agency" one of the "central problems" of modem social theory (1979). In history, E. P. Thompsonhas railed against theorists (everything from Parsoniansto Stalinists) who treat "history as a 'process withouta subject' [and]concurin the eviction fromhistoryof human agency" (1978:79). In literarystudies, RaymondWilliams insists that litera- ture must be treatedas the productof particular practices, and accuses those who abstractliteraturefrom practice of performing "an extraordinary ideo- logical feat" (1977:46). If we push further-and here we skirt dangerous to Barthand to Bailey in the sixties, to the earlierworks of Leach (e.g., 1960), and ultimatelyto Raymond Firth (e.g., 1963 [1951]). See also Marriott(1976) in the United States. 15 I would argue, if I had more space, that feminist anthropologyis one of the primary contexts in which a practice approachhas been developing. The Collier and Rosaldo (1981) article is a good example. See also Ortner(1981). 16 MayerZald, personalcommunication,at the Social Science HistorySeminar(Universityof Michigan), 1982.
  • 22. 146 SHERRY B. ORTNER ground-we might even see the whole sociobiology movementas partof this general trend, insofar as it shifts the evolutionarymechanismfrom random mutation to intentional choice on the part of actors seeking to maximize reproductivesuccess. (I should probablysay, righthere and not in a footnote, that I have a range of very strong objections to sociobiology. Nonetheless, I do not think it is too far-fetched to see its emergence as part of the broad movement to which I am drawing attentionhere.) The practice approachis diverse, and I will not attemptto compare and contrast its many strands. Rather I will select for discussion a number of works that seem to share a common orientation within the larger set, an orientationthat seems to me particularly promising. I do not wish to canonize any single one of these works, nor do I wish to provide a label for the subset and endow it with more reality than it has. What I do here is more like beginning to develop a photograph, to coax a latent form into something recognizable. We may begin by contrasting, in a general way, this (subset of) newer practice-oriented work with certain more established approaches,especially with symbolic interactionismin sociology (Blumer 1962; Goffman 1959; see also Berreman 1962, and more recently Gregor 1977 in anthropology)and with what was called transactionalism anthropology(Kapferer1976, Mar- in riott 1976, Goody 1978, Barth 1966, Bailey 1969). The first point to note is that these approacheswere elaboratedin opposition to the dominant, essen- tially Parsonian/Durkheimian,view of the world as ordered by rules and norms.17 Recognizing that institutionalorganizationand culturalpatterning exist, the symbolic interactionistsand transactionalistsnonetheless sought to minimize or bracket the relevance of these phenomena for understanding social life: of From standpoint symbolic the socialorganization a framework interaction, is inside of whichactingunitsdeveloptheiractions.Structural features,suchas "culture," "socialsystems," "socialstratification," "socialroles," set conditions their or for actionbutdo not determinetheiraction(Blumer 1962:152). The newer practice theorists, on the other hand, share a view that "the system" (in a variety of senses to be discussed below) does in fact have very powerful, even "determining," effect upon human action and the shape of events. Their interestin the study of action and interaction thus not a matter is of denying or minimizing this point, but expresses ratheran urgent need to understandwhere "the system" comes from-how it is produced and re- produced, and how it may have changed in the past or be changed in the future. As Giddens argues in his importantrecent book (1979), the study of 17 Parsons and his colleagues gave the term "action" central place in their scheme (1962 [1951]), but what they meant by this was essentially en-actmentof rules and norms. Bourdieu, Giddens, and others have pointed this out, and have cast their argumentsin part against this position.
  • 23. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 147 practiceis not an antagonisticalternativeto the study of systems or structures, but a necessary complement to it. The other major aspect of the newer practice orientation,differentiatingit significantly from earlier interactionistand transactionalistapproaches, re- sides in a palpable Marxist influence carrying through from the seventies. Partly this is visible in the way in which things like culture and/or structure are viewed. That is, although the newer practice theorists share with sixties anthropologya strong sense of the shaping power of culture/structure, this shapingpower is viewed ratherdarkly, as a matterof "constraint," "hegem- ony," and "symbolic domination." We will come back to this position in greaterdetail later. More generally, the Marxistinfluence is to be seen in the assumptionthat the most importantforms of action or interactionfor analytic purposes are those which take place in asymmetricalor dominatedrelations, that it is these forms of action or interactionthatbest explain the shapeof any given system at any given time. Whetherit is a matterof focusing directlyon interaction (even "struggle") between asymmetrically related actors, or whether it is more broadly a matter of defining actors (whatever they are doing) in terms of roles and statuses derived from asymmetricalrelationsin which they participate,the approachtends to highlight social asymmetryas the most importantdimension of both action and structure. Not all of currentpractice work manifests the Marxistinfluence. Some of it-like symbolic interactionismand transactionalism themselves-is more in the spirit of Adam Smith. The members of the subset with which I am concerned, however, implicitly or explicitly shareat least the criticalflavorof seventies anthropology, if not a systematic allegiance to Marxist theory per se. Yet to speak of a Marxist influence in all of this is actually to obscure an importantaspect of what is going on: an interpenetration, almost a merger, between Marxist and Weberian frameworks. In the sixties, the opposition between Marxand Weber, as "materialist"and "idealist," had been empha- sized. The practice theorists, in contrast, draw on a set of writers who in- terpretthe Marxistcorpus in such a way as to renderit quite compatiblewith Weber's views. As Weber put the actor at the center of his model, so these writersemphasize issues of human praxis in Marx. As Weber subsumedthe economic within the political, so these writersencompasseconomic exploita- tion within political domination. And as Weber was centrallyconcernedwith ethos and consciousness, so these writers stress similar issues within Marx's work. Choosing Marx over Weber as one's theoristof reference is a tactical move of a certainsort. In reality, the theoreticalframeworkinvolved is about equally indebted to both. (On theory, see Giddens 1971; Williams 1976; Avineri 1971; Ollman 1971; Bauman 1973; Habermas1973; Goldmann1977. For substantivecase analyses in this Weberian-Marxist vein, see Thompson 1966; Williams 1973; Genovese 1976.)
  • 24. 148 SHERRY B. ORTNER I will proceed to explicate and evaluate the "new practice" position by way of posing a series of questions:What is it that a practiceapproachseeks to explain?What is practice?How is it motivated?And what sorts of analytic relationshipsare postulatedin the model? Let me emphasizevery stronglythat I do not offer here a coherenttheoryof practice.I merely sortout anddiscuss, in a very preliminaryfashion, some of the central axes of such a theory. What is Being Explained? As previously indicated, modem practicetheory seeks to explain the relation- ship(s) that obtain between human action, on the one hand, and some global entity which we may call "the system," on the other. Questionsconcerning these relationshipsmay go in either direction-the impact of the system on practice, and the impactof practiceon the system. How these processes work will be taken up below. Here we must say a few words about the natureof "the system." In two recent works in anthropologythat explicitly attemptto elaboratea practice-basedmodel (Bourdieu 1978 [1972]; and Sahlins 1981), the authors nominallytake a Frenchstructuralist view of the system (patternsof relations between categories, and of relationsbetween relations). In fact however both Bourdieu's habitus and Sahlins's "cosmological dramas" behave in many ways like the American concept of culture, combining elements of ethos, affect, and value with more strictly cognitive schemes of classification. The choice of a French or an American perspective on the system does have certainconsequences for the shape of the analysis as a whole, but we will not pursue these here. The point is that practice anthropologistsassume that society and historyare not simply sums of ad hoc responsesand adaptations to particular stimuli, but are governedby organizational evaluativeschemes. and It is these (embodied, of course, within institutional,symbolic, and material forms) that constitute the system. The system, further,is not broken up into units like base and superstruc- ture, or society and culture, but is rather a relatively seamless whole. An institution-say, a marriagesystem-is at once a system of social relations, economic arrangements,political processes, culturalcategories, norms, val- ues, ideals, emotional patterns,and so on and on. No attemptis made to sort these componentsinto levels and to assign primacyto one or the other level. Nor, for example, is marriage as a whole assigned to "society," while religion is assigned to "culture." A practice approachhas no need to break the system into artificial chunks like base and superstructure (and to argue over which determineswhich), since the analytic effort is not to explain one chunk of the system by referringit to anotherchunk, but ratherto explain the system as an integral whole (which is not to say a harmoniouslyintegrated one) by referringit to practice. But if the system is an integral whole, at the same time all of its parts or
  • 25. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 149 dimensions do not have equal analyticsignificance. At the core of the system, both forming it and deforming it, are the specific realities of asymmetry, inequality, and dominationin a given time and place. RaymondWilliams, a Marxist literary/culturalhistorian, sums up both the insistence upon holism and the privileged position of dominationcharacteristic this view. Picking of up Antonio Gramsci's term "hegemony" as his label for the system, he argues that "hegemony" is a concept which at once includes and goes beyond two powerful earlierconcepts: that of "culture" as a "whole social process," in which men define and shape their whole lives; and that of "ideology" in any of its Marxist senses, in which a system of meanings and values is the expression or projectionof a particular class interest. "Hegemony" goes beyond "culture" in its insistenceon relatingthe "whole social process" to specific distributionsof power and influence. To say that men define and shape their whole lives is true only in abstraction. In any actual society there are specific inequalities in means and therefore in capacity to realize this process.... Gramscithereforeintroducesthe necessary recognition of dominanceand subordina- tion in what has still, however, to be recognized as a whole process. It is in just this recognition of the wholeness of the process that the concept of "hegemony" goes beyond "ideology." What is decisive is not only the conscious system of ideas and beliefs, but the whole lived social process as practicallyorganized by specific and dominantmeanings and values. ... [Hegemony] is in the strongestsense a "culture," but a culturewhich has also to be seen as the lived dominance and subordination of particular classes (Williams 1977:108-109, 110). What a practice theory seeks to explain, then, is the genesis, reproduction, and change of form and meaning of a given social/cultural whole, defined in-more or less-this sense. What is Practice? In principle, the answer to this question is almost unlimited:anythingpeople do. Given the centrality of domination in the model, however, the most significant forms of practice are those with intentionalor unintentional politi- cal implications. Then again, almost anything people do has such implica- tions. So the study of practice is after all the study of all forms of human action, but from a particular-political-angle. Beyond this general point, furtherdistinctionsmay be introduced.There is first of all the question of what are taken to be the acting units. Most practice anthropologyto date takes these units to be individualactors, whetheractual historical individuals, or social types ("women," "commoners," "work- ers," "junior siblings," etcetera). The analyst takes these people and their doings as the reference point for understandinga particularunfolding of events, and/or for understanding processes involved in the reproduction the or change of some set of structural features. In contrastto a large body of work in the field of history, there has been relatively little done in anthropologyon
  • 26. 150 SHERRY B. ORTNER concertedcollective action (but see Wolf 1969; Friedrich1970; Blu 1980; see also the literature cargo cults, especially Worsley 1968). Even in studiesof on collective action, however, the collectivity is handledmethodologicallyas a single subject. We shall be discussing, throughoutthis section, some of the problemsthat arise from the essential individualismof most currentforms of practice theory. A second set of questions concerns the temporal organizationof action. Some authors(Bourdieuis an example) treat action in terms of relatively ad hoc decision making, and/or relatively short-term"moves." Otherssuggest, even if they do not develop the point, that humanbeings act within plans or programsthat are always more long range than any single move, and indeed that most moves are intelligible only within the context of these largerplans (Sahlins (1981) implies this, as do Ortner(1981) and Collier and Rosaldo (1981); for an older example, see Hartand Pilling (1960)). Many such plans are culturally provided (the normative life cycle, for example), but many others must be constructedby actors themselves. Even projects generated ("creatively") by actors, however, tend to take stereotypedforms, insofaras the constraints and the resources of the system are relatively constant for actors in similar positions. In any event, an emphasis on larger "projects" rather than particular "moves" underlines the point that action itself has (developmental) structure, as well as operating in, and in relation to, structure. Finally, there is the question of the kinds of action takento be analytically centralto the currentapproach.Everyone seems to agree in opposing a Parso- nian or Saussurianview in which action is seen as sheeren-actmentor execu- tion of rules and norms (Bourdieu 1978; Sahlins 1981; Giddens 1979). More- over, everyone seems also to agree that a kind of romantic or heroic "voluntarism," emphasizing the freedom and relatively unrestrictedin- ventiveness of actors, will not do either (e.g., Thompson1978). Whatis left, then, is a view of action largely in terms of pragmaticchoice and decision making, and/or active calculating and strategizing. I will have more to say about the strategic model in the next section, when I discuss the views of motivation entailed in practice theory. Here, however, I wish to question whether the critique of en-actmentor execution may not have gone too far. Indeed, despite the attackson Parsonsby Bourdieuand Giddens, both recog- nize the central role of highly patternedand routinizedbehaviorin systemic reproduction.It is precisely in those areasof life-especially in the so-called domestic domain-where action proceeds with little reflection, that much of the conservatism of a system tends to be located. Either because practice theorists wish to emphasize the activeness and intentionalityof action, or because of a growing interestin change as againstreproduction,or both, the degree to which actors really do simply enact norms because "that was the way of our ancestors" may be unduly undervalued.
  • 27. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 151 WhatMotivates Action? A theory of practice requires some sort of theory of motivation. At the moment, the dominant theory of motivation in practice anthropologyis de- rived from interesttheory. The model is that of an essentially individualistic, .and somewhat aggressive, actor, self-interested,rational,pragmatic,and per- haps with a maximizing orientationas well. What actorsdo, it is assumed, is rationallygo after what they want, and what they want is what is materially and politically useful for them within the context of their culturaland histor- ical situations. Interesttheory has been rakedover the coals many times before. Here it is sufficient simply to note a few points that have particularrelevance for an- thropological studies of practice. Insofar as interest theory is, even if it pretendsnot to be, a psychological theory, it is clearly far too narrow. In particular, although pragmaticra- tionalityis certainlyone aspect of motivation, it is never the only one, and not always even the dominantone. To accordit the statusof exclusive motivating force is to exclude from the analytic discourse a whole range of emotional terms-need, fear, suffering, desire, and others-that must surely be partof motivation. Unfortunately, anthropologistshave generally found that actors with too much psychological plumbingare hardto handlemethodologically,and prac- tice theorists are no exception. There is, however, a growing body of litera- ture which explores the variable constructionof self, person, emotion, and motive in cross-culturalperspective (e.g., M. Rosaldo 1980, 1981; Friedrich 1977; Geertz 1973a, 1975; Singer 1980; Kirkpatrick1977; Guemple 1972). The growth of this body of work is itself part of the larger trend toward an interestin elaboratingan actor-centered paradigm,as is the fact that the sub- field of psychological anthropology seems to be enjoying something of a renaissance (e.g., Paul 1982; Kracke 1978; Levy 1973). One may hope for some cross-fertilization between the more sociologically oriented practice accounts, with their relatively denaturedviews of motive, and some of these more richly textured accounts of emotion and motivation. If interesttheory assumes too much rationalityon the partof actors, it also assumes too much active-ness. The idea that actors are always pressing claims, pursuinggoals, advancing purposes, and the like may simply be an overly energetic (and overly political) view of how and why people act. We may recall here the distinction, underscored Geertz, between interesttheo- by ry and strain theory (1973c). If actors in interest theory are always actively striving for gains, actors in strain theory are seen as experiencingthe com- plexities of their situations and attemptingto solve problemsposed by those situations. It follows from these points that the strain perspective places greateremphasis on the analysis of the system itself, the forces in play upon
  • 28. 152 SHERRY B. ORTNER actors, as a way of understanding where actors, as we say, are coming from. In particular,a system is analyzedwith the aim of revealingthe sortsof binds it creates for actors, the sorts of burdensit places upon them, and so on. This analysis, in turn, provides much of the context for understandingactors' motives, and the kinds of projectsthey constructfor dealing with their situa- tions (see also Ortner 1975, 1978). While strain theory does not rectify the psychological shortcomings of interesttheory, it does at least make for a more systematicexplorationof the social forces shaping motives than interesttheory does. Indeed, one may say that strain theory is a theory of the social, as opposed to psychological, productionof "interests," the latterbeing seen less as direct expressions of utility and advantagefor actors, and more as images of solutions to experi- enced stresses and problems. Finally, an interestapproachtends to go handin handwith seeing action in terms of short-termtactical "moves" ratherthan long-term developmental "projects." From a tactical point of view, actors seek particulargains, whereas from a developmentalpoint of view, actors are seen as involved in relatively far-reachingtransformations their states of being-of their rela- of tionships with things, persons, and self. We may say, in the spiritof Gramsci, that action in a developmentalor "projects" perspectiveis more a matterof "becoming" thanof "getting" (1957). Intrinsicto this latterperspectiveis a sense of motive and action as shapednot only by problemsbeing solved, and gains being sought, but by images and ideals of what constitutesgoodness- in people, in relationships, and in conditions of life. It iS a peculiarityof interesttheorythat it is sharedacross a broadspectrum of analysts, Marxist and non-Marxist, "old" and "new" practicetheorists. The popularityand durabilityof the perspective,despite numerousattacksand criticisms, suggest that especially deep changes in our own practiceswill be requiredif anything is to be dislodged in this area. The Nature of Interactions between Practice and the System 1. How does the systemshape practice? Anthropologists-American ones, anyway-have for the most partlong agreedthat cultureshapes, guides, and even to some extent dictates behavior. In the sixties, Geertzelaboratedsome of the important mechanismsinvolved in this process, and it seems to me that most moder practice theorists, including those who write in Marxistand/or structuralist terms, hold an essentially Geertzianview. But there are certain changes of emphasis, derived from the centralityof dominationwithin the practiceframework.For one thing, as noted earlier, the emphasishas shifted from what culture allows and enables people to see, feel, and do, to what it restrictsand inhibitsthem from seeing, feeling, and doing. Further,although it is agreed that culture powerfully constitutesthe reality that actors live in, this reality is looked upon with criticaleyes: why this one and not some other? And what sorts of alternativesare people being dis-abled from seeing?
  • 29. THEORY IN ANTHROPOLOGY SINCE THE SIXTIES 153 It is important note that this view is at least partlydistinctfrom a view of to cultureas mystification. In a mystificationview, culture(= "ideology") tells lies aboutthe realities of people's lives, and the analyticproblemis to under- stand how people come to believe these lies (e.g., Bloch 1977). In the ap- proach under discussion here, however, there is only one reality, and it is culturally constituted from top to bottom. The problem is not that of the system telling lies aboutsome extrasystemic"reality," but of why the system as a whole has a certain configuration, and of why and how it excludes alternativepossible configurations. In any event, in termsof the specific questionof how the system constrains practice, the emphasis tends to be laid on essentially culturaland psychologi- cal mechanisms: mechanisms of the formationand transformation "con- of sciousness." Although constraintsof material and political sorts, including force, are fully acknowledged, there seems to be general agreement that action is constrainedmost deeply and systematically by the ways in which culturecontrols the definitions of the world for actors, limits their conceptual tools, and restricts their emotional repertoires.Culturebecomes part of the self. Speaking of the sense of honor among the Kabyle, for example, Bour- dieu says: ? . . honour a permanent is disposition, embedded the agents'verybodiesin the in formof mental dispositions, schemes perception thought, of and extremelygeneralin theirapplication, such as those whichdivideup the worldin accordance the with oppositions between maleandthe female,eastandwest, future past,topand the and bottom, rightandleft, etc., andalso, at a deeperlevel, in theformof bodilypostures andstances,waysof standing, or sitting,looking,speaking, walking. Whatis called the sense of honour nothing is otherthanthe cultivated disposition, in inscribed the bodyschemaandthe schemesof thought (1978:15). In a similar vein, Foucault says of the discourse of "perversions": Themachinery powerthatfocuseson thiswholealienstrain notaimto suppress of did it, butrather give it ananalytical, to visible,andpermanent it reality: wasimplantedin bodies,slippedin beneath modesof conduct,madeintoa principle classification of andintelligibility, established a raisond'etreanda natural as order disorder.... of Thestrategy behind dissemination to strewreality this was withthemandincorporate themintothe individual (1980:44). Thus insofar as dominationis as much a matterof culturaland psychological processes as of material and political ones, it operates by shaping actors' dispositions such that, in the extreme case, "the agents' aspirationshave the same limits as the objective conditions of which they are the product"(Bour- dieu 1978:166; see also Rabinow 1975; Barnettand Silverman1979; Rabinow and Sullivan 1979). At the same time, however, those authorswho emphasizeculturaldomina- tion also place importantlimits on the scope and depth of culturalcontrols. The extreme case is never reached, and often never even approached.Thus while accepting the view of culture as powerfully constraining, they argue
  • 30. 154 SHERRY B. ORTNER that hegemony is always more fragile than its appears,and never as total as it (or as traditionalculturalanthropology)would claim. The reasons given for this state of affairs are various, and relate directly to the ways in which the different authorsconceptualize systemic change. This brings us to our final set of questions. 2. How does practice shape the system?Therearereallytwo considerations here-how practice reproduces the system, and how the system may be changed by practice. A unified theory of practice should ideally be able to account for both within a single framework.At the moment, however, it is clear that a focus on reproductiontends to producea ratherdifferentpicture from a focus on change, and we will thus take these issues separately. Beginning with reproduction,there is of course a long traditionin an- thropologyof asking how it is thatnorms, values, and conceptualschemes get reproducedby and for actors. Prior to the sixties, at least in American an- thropology, emphasis was laid upon socialization practices as the primary agents of this process. In England,however, the influenceof the Durkheimian paradigmgenerated an emphasis on ritual. It was throughthe enactmentof ritualsof various kinds that actors were seen as coming to be wedded to the normsand values of theirculture, and/or to be purged,at least temporarily,of whatever dissident sentiments they might harbor(e.g., Gluckman 1955; V. Turner1969; Beidelman 1966). The ritualfocus, or what might be called for focus on extraordinarypractice, became even stronger in the sixties and seventies. Americansymbolic anthropologists took up the view thatritualwas one of the primary matrices for the reproductionof consciousness (Geertz 1973b;Ortner1978), even if they dissentedfromcertainaspectsof the British approach.And the structural Marxiststoo placed greatweight on the power of ritual to mediate social structural contradictionsand mystify the workingsof the system.Ritualin factis a formof practice-people do it-and to studythe re- productionof consciousness, mystified or otherwise, in the processes of ritual behavioris to study at least one way in which practicereproducesthe system. The newer practiceapproaches,by contrast,place greateremphasison the practicesof ordinaryliving. Althoughthese were not by any means ignoredin earlierwork, they assume greaterprominencehere. Thus despite his stress on the highly intentionalized moments of practice, Bourdieu also pays close attention to the little routines people enact, again and again, in working, eating, sleeping, and relaxing, as well as the little scenariosof etiquettethey play out again and again in social interaction. All of these routines and scenariosare predicatedupon, and embody withinthemselves, the fundamen- tal notions of temporal,spatial, and social orderingthatunderlieand organize the system as a whole. In enacting these routines, actorsnot only continueto be shaped by the underlying organizationalprinciples involved, but con- tinually re-endorse those principles in the world of public observationand discourse.