SlideShare una empresa de Scribd logo
1 de 399
Descargar para leer sin conexión
EL DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PÚBLICO
EN LA OBRA DE MANUEL BECERRA RAMÍREZ
INSTITUTO DE INVESTIGACIONES JURÍDICAS
Serie Doctrina Jurídica, núm. 1012
DIRECTORIO
Dra. Mónica González Contró
Directora
Dr. Mauricio Padrón Innamorato
Secretario Académico
Mtra. Wendy Vanesa Rocha Cacho
Jefa del Departamento de Publicaciones
Créditos editoriales
Wendy Vanesa Rocha Cacho
Coordinación editorial
Roberto Zavaleta Cornejo
Cuidado de la edición
Oscar Martínez González
Formación en computadora
Edith Aguilar Gálvez
Diseño y elaboración de portada
EL DERECHO
INTERNACIONAL
PÚBLICO EN LA OBRA
DE MANUEL BECERRA
RAMÍREZ
UNIVERSIDAD NACIONAL AUTÓNOMA DE MÉXICO
INSTITUTO DE INVESTIGACIONES JURÍDICAS
México, 2024
Nuria González Martín
Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández
Ingrid Berlanga Vasile
Mónica Elizabeth Nuño Nuño
Coordinadores
Primera edición: 2 de febrero de 2024
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México
Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
Circuito Mario de la Cueva s/n
Ciudad Universitaria, Coyoacán, 04510 Ciudad de México
ISBN (libro electrónico): 978-607-30-8689-9
Hecho en México
Esta edición y sus características son propiedad de la Universidad Nacional Autónoma de
México. Prohibida la reproducción total o parcial por cualquier medio sin la autorización
escrita del titular de los derechos patrimoniales.
Catalogación en la publicación UNAM. Dirección General de Bibliotecas y
Servicios Digitales de Información
Nombres: González Martín, Nuria, editor. | Benavides Hernández, Luis Ángel, editor. |
Berlanga Vasile, Ingrid, editor. | Nuño Nuño, Mónica Elizabeth, editor.
Título: El derecho internacional público en la obra de Manuel Becerra Ramírez / Nuria
González Martín, Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández, Ingrid Berlanga Vasile, Mónica Eli-
zabeth Nuño Nuño, coordinadores.
Descripción: Primera edición. | México : Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México,
Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas, 2024. | Serie: Serie Doctrina jurídica ; núm. 1012.
Identificadores: LIBRUNAM 2226943 (libro electrónico) | ISBN 9786073086899 (li-
bro electrónico).
Temas: Derecho internacional. | Derechos humanos -- Siglo XXI. | Propiedad intelec-
tual -- Aspectos económicos. | Guerra de Ucrania, 2022- . | Rusia -- Aspectos políticos. |
Becerra Ramírez, Manuel.
Clasificación: LCC KZ3410 (libro electrónico) | DDC 341.01—dc23
V
CONTENIDO
Presentación . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . IX
Nuria González Martín
Mónica Elizabeth Nuño Nuño
Ingrid Berlanga Vasile
Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández
Primera parte
DERECHO Y RELACIONES
INTERNACIONALES
Quo Vadis, Humanity? Reflections on Contemporary Geopolitical and
Societal Transformations. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
Rein Müllerson
The Provision of Arms to the Victim of Armed Aggression: The Case
of Ukraine. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25
Stefan Talmon
Common Heritage or Private Property? Power, Strategy, and Law-Ma-
king for the Deep Seabed and Outer Space. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
Michael Byers
Las transformaciones económicas, políticas y jurídicas en la URSS. Su
incidencia en la guerra de Ucrania. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79
Virdzhiniya Petrova Georgieva
Las guerras híbridas: nuevas formas de agresión, injerencismo e inter-
vencionismo. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99
Luis Lorenzo Córdova Arellano
VI CONTENIDO
Segunda parte
DERECHO DE LOS TRATADOS
Obligación de no frustrar el objeto y el fin de un tratado antes de su
entrada en vigor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119
Ricardo Abello-Galvis
Reflexiones sobre los tratados internacionales de derechos humanos. . 131
Sergio García Ramírez
The Holy See and the Treaties of Westphalia. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 175
Maurizio Ragazzi
Tercera parte
PROPIEDAD INTELECTUAL
Secretos industriales, un cambio de paradigma. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195
Mauricio Jaliffe Daher
Los sistemas de inteligencia artificial como inventores: consideraciones
para un debate a partir de fallos judiciales. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207
Jorge Luis Ordelin Font
Blue Economy: The Future of Intellectual Property?. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223
Pablo Ferrera
Cuarta parte
ENSEÑANZA DEL DERECHO
INTERNACIONAL JURÍDICO
Las grandes transformaciones del derecho internacional en un enfo-
que de las ciencias políticas y sociales. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 249
Juan Carlos Velázquez Elizarrarás
VII
CONTENIDO
Las creaciones intelectuales como bienes comunes. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273
Rafael Pérez Miranda
El derecho internacional en el panorama de la producción jurídica. . . 289
Ramiro Contreras Acevedo
María Amelia Solórzano Peña
Notas amistosas. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 317
Acerca de Manuel Becerra Ramírez y su obra. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 387
IX
PRESENTACIÓN
La presente obra tiene por objeto hacer una revisión en torno al pensamien-
to jurídico del doctor Manuel Becerra Ramírez, destacado internacionalista
mexicano.
Es indudable que México ha contado con destacados internacionalistas
cuyos nombres, por ser conocidos, no es necesario repetir. Sin embargo, el
doctor Becerra pertenece a un grupo muy particular de internacionalistas, a
aquel alejado de la fama y los grandes círculos políticos y diplomáticos, pero
forjado en la academia y en el rigor jurídico, aquél en el que los aplausos no
provienen de los puestos que haya ocupado, sino del reconocimiento y admi-
ración de sus pares, alumnas, alumnos y amigos, un quehacer caracterizado
por el apoyo incondicional que siempre profesa.
Desde el inicio de su carrera Manuel Becerra ha sido una especie de
outsider. Su formación internacionalista no la hizo en alguno de los grandes
centros educativos occidentales. En una época en donde el mundo aún era
bipolar, Manuel Becerra decidió estudiar en la Unión Soviética, en la Uni-
versidad Lomonosov, con el gran profesor internacionalista Grigory Tun-
kin, esto es, decidió estudiar desde otro lente, lejos de la retórica predomi-
nante, este hecho marcaría profundamente su pensamiento jurídico, siempre
tratando de ver las dos caras de la moneda, siendo equilibrado y mesurado.
Sin lugar a duda, su incorporación al Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídi-
cas de la UNAM fue otro paso trascendente en su desarrollo profesional, ello
le permitió combinar dos de sus grandes pasiones, a saber, la investigación y
la docencia. Lo anterior hizo que innumerables estudiantes pudieran cono-
cerle. Destaca allí su labor durante los llamados “veranos de la investigación
científica” que permiten a jóvenes universitarios colaborar con un investiga-
dor y fomentar el amor por la ciencia.
En este sentido, es importante señalar que uno de los reconocimientos
a su enorme calidad académica es el hecho de haber sido nombrado inves-
tigador nacional emérito por el Sistema Nacional de Investigadores como
prueba de la escuela forjada.
Asimismo, no se podría dejar de mencionar la labor realizada por el doc-
tor Becerra a través del Anuario Mexicano de Derecho Internacional, el cual fundó
y dirige desde hace más de veinte años. Desde su concepción, el Anuario fue
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
X PRESENTACIÓN
pensado como un espacio para dar voz no sólo a los internacionalistas en
México, sino también de América Latina y de otras regiones del mundo. El
Anuario Mexicano ha servido de inspiración a otras publicaciones en la región
y hoy en día es un referente en todo el continente.
En muchas ocasiones las personas contamos con alguien que marca
nuestras vidas, casi siempre son los padres, pero también, de manera fre-
cuente, lo son los profesores; para aquellos que hemos tenido la dicha de co-
nocer a Manuel Becerra Ramírez podemos decir, sin temor a equivocarnos,
que él ha marcado las nuestras. El rigor académico junto con la simpatía y
sencillez de su persona hace de él un ser humano extraordinario.
La presente obra, que se ha concretado con el invaluable apoyo de Emi-
liano Márquez en la fase final de su compilación, se encuentra dividida en
dos partes. La primera es una compilación en torno a las grandes áreas de
estudio de Manuel Becerra tales como derecho de los tratados, propiedad in-
telectual, derecho internacional en periodos de transformaciones históricas
como la caída del muro de Berlín y de la Unión Soviética, derecho y relacio-
nes internacionales desde América Latina, fuentes del derecho internacional,
entre otros. La diversidad de autores y temas que participan son muestra de la
pluralidad del pensamiento tan característico en Manuel Becerra.
La segunda parte está constituida por las contribuciones de muchas de las
personas a quienes Manuel Becerra ha impactado en su vida, se trata de notas
muy personales, que entrañan recuerdos y agradecimientos, algo de lo mucho
que nos ha brindado.
Dada la diversidad temática de los artículos que constituyen la primera
parte del libro es importante proporcionar al lector una visión general de los
mismos con la finalidad de invitarlo a su lectura.
Así, Rein Müllerson hace una serie de análisis sobre la geopolítica contem-
poránea y su impacto en las transformaciones de las sociedades. Es, a la vez,
una revisión personal a partir de los últimos años de la URSS a la época actual.
Por su parte, Luis Córdova aborda, desde una perspectiva holística, los
nuevos tipos de conflictos internacionales, los llamados conflictos híbridos,
en donde no necesariamente se utilizan armas convencionales, sino que los
teatros de operaciones pueden ser el ciberespacio o el derecho.
En otro tema, Michael Byers compara los esfuerzos de elaboración de
reglas internacionales sobre la minería de los fondos marinos y la minería
espacial. Particularmente se centra en las diferentes estrategias desplegadas
por Estados Unidos, y cómo el G-77 a veces es capaz de resistirlas, o al me-
nos modificar los resultados.
En el artículo de Sergio García Ramírez se hace una reflexión profun-
da sobre la naturaleza de los tratados en materia de derechos humanos, así
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
XI
PRESENTACIÓN
como el diálogo jurisdiccional y control de convencionalidad desarrollados
en tiempos recientes. Sin esos factores no se podría entender el derecho in-
ternacional contemporáneo de los derechos humanos.
En la misma temática de tratados se encuentra el artículo de Ricardo
Abello quien, desde una óptica colombiana, aborda con ejemplos regionales
muy interesantes la obligación de no frustrar el objeto y el fin de un tratado
antes de su entrada en vigor.
En materia de propiedad intelectual, Pablo Ferrara hace un análisis de la
llamada “economía azul” la cual se refiere a aquellas actividades orientadas
a lograr el crecimiento y el desarrollo económicos basados en las actividades
oceánicas, al mismo tiempo que considera los resultados sociales y ambien-
tales de estas actividades.
Siguiendo la misma temática, Rafael Pérez Miranda realiza un análisis
conceptual comparativo sobre los conocimientos intelectuales o intangibles y
las obras artísticas como bienes comunes sobre los cuales aún no hay un con-
cepto universalmente aceptado. Señala que en la doctrina y el derecho se ha
excluido de la protección a productores de conocimientos científicos básicos
y hace énfasis en la importancia de retribuir y reconocer adecuadamente los
derechos de científicos y artistas.
De igual forma, el artículo de Jorge Luis Ordelín Font tiene como obje-
tivo analizar algunos retos de los derechos de propiedad intelectual ante la
capacidad creativa de los sistemas de inteligencia artificial (IA) a partir de
los argumentos expuestos por los jueces de Australia y Reino Unido en tres
resoluciones judiciales. El autor expone las cuestiones fundamentales rela-
cionadas con el caso Device for the Autonomous Bootstrapping of Unified Sentience
(DABUS) y analiza los principales argumentos a favor y en contra del reco-
nocimiento de DABUS como inventor.
Continuando en esa área, Mauricio Jaliffe Daher aborda la represión de
la competencia desleal mediante los llamados “secretos industriales”, sien-
do la figura que a nivel internacional ofrece mayor protección a los activos
de las empresas, en particular a las que manejan tecnologías muy avanzadas.
Destaca la necesidad de revertir la incongruencia de origen en la formación y
valoración empresarial en la aportación de información constitutiva de secre-
tos industriales así como la importancia de contar con un marco legal efectivo
en México para proteger a startups de competidores.
En un análisis histórico de las relaciones internacionales Maurizio Ra-
gazzi hace un recuento del impacto de los tratados de Westphalia en las re-
laciones internacionales, especialmente del papel que jugó la santa sede en
el contexto diplomático del siglo XVII y de los tres papas, siendo particular-
mente el de Urbano VIII.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
XII PRESENTACIÓN
A su vez, Ramiro Contreras Acevedo y María Amelia Solórzano Peña
hacen un análisis del desarrollo de la producción científica en materia de de-
recho internacional desde finales del siglo XX hasta la actualidad, llevando
a cabo un ejercicio de mapeo, eligiendo bases de datos bibliográficas sobre
derecho internacional de acceso abierto en español, destacando el Anuario
Mexicano de Derecho Internacional por el número de artículos publicados.
Por su parte, Juan Carlos Velázquez Elizarrarás realiza un análisis so-
bre la enseñanza-aprendizaje del derecho internacional en el contexto de las
ciencias políticas y sociales, concibiendo al derecho internacional como un
contribuyente ordenador y eje de conocimiento insustituible de las relaciones
internacionales, que a la vez está condicionado a una constante adecuación
y transformación del derecho internacional e incluso a una ampliación y di-
versificación tanto temática como de investigación.
El artículo de Stephan Talmon analiza, en el contexto de la guerra entre
Rusia y Ucrania, si la norma de neutralidad de no proveer de armamento a
una de las partes en un conflicto puede admitir una excepción, esta excep-
ción se argumenta bajo distintos supuestos, por ejemplo, invocando el artícu-
lo 51 de la Carta de la ONU debido a que una de las partes del conflicto es
miembro del Consejo de Seguridad y utiliza el veto para obstruir la decisión
de dicho Consejo o cuando el conflicto inicia por una agresión.
La autora Virdzhiniya Petrova Georgieva retoma una serie de entrevistas
realizadas por el doctor Manuel Becerra a selectos académicos y estudiosos
de la URSS en noviembre de 1991. Las preguntas, que versaban sobre las
transformaciones ocurridas en la URSS después del final de la Guerra Fría
y desde las disciplinas de la economía internacional, la política internacio-
nal y el derecho internacional, son retomados por la autora como punto de
partida para tomar sus principales hallazgos y paralelismo en su origen para
hacer un análisis que incide en la guerra de Ucrania.
La presente obra nace de la gran admiración de parte de alumnos, cole-
gas y amigos, así como del reconocimiento por la enorme labor formadora,
en todos los sentidos de la palabra, que en muchos de nosotros ha tenido
Manuel Becerra. Don Manuel ha sido más que un profesor, ha fungido como
un verdadero mentor y en más de una ocasión ha actuado con un verdadero
sentido paternal.
Nuria González Martín
Mónica Elizabeth Nuño Nuño
Ingrid Berlanga Vasile
Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
Primera parte
DERECHO Y RELACIONES
INTERNACIONALES
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
3
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY
GEOPOLITICAL AND SOCIETAL TRANSFORMATIONS
Rein Müllerson*
Summary: I. Introduction. II. On Current Geopolitical Configurations.
III. Liberalism versus Democracy. IV. On the Adaptability to Rapid
Change. V. Populism as an Inadequate Response to the Conflict Between
the Elites and the Masses. VI. “Illiberal Democracy”, “Undemocratic
Liberalism” and “Liberal Imperialism”. VII. Is “e pluribus unum”
indeed Replacing “ex uno plures”? VIII. Bibliography.
I. Introduction
It was almost forty years ago when, as a young academic at Moscow Universi-
ty, I met an even younger scholar from Mexico —Manuel Becerra Ramirez—.
He had just become a Ph.D. student of the most famous soviet specialist on
international law —professor Grigory Ivanovitch Tunkin—. I know from my
personal experience how difficult is the russian language for those for whom it
is not a native tongue. However, I had mastered the language of Pushkin well
before I started my legal studies. Therefore, for Manuel, it was all even more
difficult. However, due to his intelligence and hard work, he not only became
fluent in russian but also excelled as an international lawyer, successfully de-
fending his Ph.D. thesis. Since then, I have followed his progress by reading
his works and even contributing to the excellent Mexican Yearbook of International
Law, so ably edited already for years by professor Becerra. Several years ago, it
was my great pleasure to meet him personally in UNAM and see with my own
eyes the high respect bestowed to Manuel Becerra Ramirez by his colleagues
as well as students. I am extremely happy to contribute my following reflec-
tions, that are not only and even not so much on international law as on the
*		
Ph. D., l’Institut de Droit International (IDI), Geneva, Switzerland, Member and for-
mer President; Tallinn University Professor Emeritus. Estonia.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
4 REIN MÜLLERSON
causes that prevent the law prevail over politics, as we expected when we were
young, to the book that celebrates high achievements of my mexican friend.
II. On Current Geopolitical Configurations
Since the end of the 1980s the world is passing through two interrelated re-
volutionary processes, one of which is global, affecting all the nations in the
world, the other being specific, though not limited, to western nations. Or ma-
ybe it would be better to say that if decades ago it plagued mainly non-western
countries, today it has become mostly a western phenomenon. Revolutionary
processes, by definition, put pressure on all kinds of normative systems, inclu-
ding law and morality, since, as being normative phenomena, they function well
in circumstances that could be called normal. In revolutionary periods in any
society —be it, say, in France at the end of the Eighteenth century, or in Rus-
sia at the beginning of the Twentieth, when normalcy was an exception and
expediency ruled, law broke down, and even morality often lost its guiding
force—. In that respect, the international society is not an exception.
The first revolutionary change is geopolitical. Starting from about the
end of the 1980s, the world entered into a period of radical geopolitical re-
configuration, whose results cannot be predicted with any certainty even to-
day. This process started with the collapse of the rather stable bipolar system,
going then through a unipolar moment of the long 1990s, and has today a
tendency of moving with jolts and jerks towards some kind of multipolarity.
While the West, led by Washington, tries to perpetuate its absolute domi-
nance acquired after the collapse of its erstwhile rival (the USSR), those be-
longing to the rest, led by China, Russia, India, Mexico, and other nations,
use different means to put an end to western hegemony. The war in Ukraine
epitomises the relentlessness of this geopolitical transformation of the world,
unfortunate victims of which are mostly people in Ukraine. In this country,
the collective west, notwithstanding Russia’s illegal use of military force aga-
inst its neighbour that was provoked by the movement of NATO to the fron-
tiers of Russia, is using Ukrainian territory and ukrainian people to bring
down Russia as one of the nations that has openly disobeyed the american
hegemony. Until the “revolutionary dust” settles down, one way or other,
and new “normalcy” emerges (or the old returns, though less plausible scena-
rio), it is difficult to expect that international law could function “normally”.
The second revolutionary transformation, not unrelated to the first, is
the crisis of liberal democracy that was meant, and for a while even seemed,
to triumph when the failure of its main ideological rival at the end of the
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
5
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
1980s had become obvious. After the collapse of the Soviet Union and
the bipolar world, it seemed to many that it was exactly liberal democracy
that had prevailed, and it would continue to flourish until the whole world
would become the same. However, the disappearance of the main enemy,
combined with a wave of globalisation, started revealing, though not imme-
diately, internal contradictions of liberal democracy.
Modern democracy, originating in western european societies, has had
dialectical relationships (i.e. situations, where different phenomena, depen-
ding on concrete circumstances, have a kind of friend/enemy relations-
hips) with three other phenomena that have, on the one hand, supported
democracy’s emergence and growth while also putting limits on its expansion
and deepening. These three phenomena are nationalism, capitalism, and li-
beralism. As in the post-WWII, the last two have been considered almost in-
separable (i.e. individual liberties and market freedoms have been often seen
as two sides of the same coin), the controversial (i.e. dialectical) relationship
of democracy with capitalism and liberalism can be dealt with as one dialec-
tical controversy, notwithstanding that there have been societies and periods
where and when free market has coexisted (or still coexists) with conservative,
even authoritarian and anti-liberal, social policies.
In this article, I will not dwell at length on an important and controversial
issue of the relationship between democracy and nationalism since I have
dealt with it elsewhere, in detail particularly in one of my recent articles.1
The process of globalisation has revealed and made acute the contradiction
between democracy and nationalism, whose ideal had become enshrined in
the concept of the nation-state and where modern democracy emerged and
evolved (the nation-state and democracy as a kind of twin brothers though
not always in best terms). Without nationalism there wouldn’t have been na-
tion-states, without nation-states there would not have been democracy, at
least in its current form. Therefore, I conclude in the aforementioned article
that without and beyond nation-states (even if they are multi-ethnic) the-
re could hardly exist democracy, though nationalism may also undermine
democracy, especially in multi-ethnic or multi-confessional societies. Besides
the revolutionary situation in international relations, where the existing ba-
lance of powers was broken and competing visions of future —a unipolarity
with one centre of power and refashioned multipolarity with different centres
of power— are competing, there is also a revolutionary situation in countries
that have been most stable and have served as examples for others. This is
the crisis of liberal democracy that is also related to, and even conditioned by,
1		
Müllerson, R., “The Nation-State: Not Yet Ready for the Dustbin of History?”, The
Chinese Journal of International Law, vol. 20, núm. 4, 2021, pp. 699-725.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
6 REIN MÜLLERSON
processes of globalisation. Below, therefore, I will concentrate on this contro-
versial, i.e. dialectical, relationship between democracy and liberalism.
III. Liberalism versus Democracy
At the beginning of the twenty-first century, the positive aspects of the rela-
tionship between democracy and liberalism, which for decades had prevailed
in the post-Second World War west, have become overwhelmed by negative
features. Democracy and liberalism, which had rather peacefully and with mu-
tual benefits coexisted for many decades, are now undermining each other’s
potentials. The main reason for such a turnaround lies in the negative aspects
or consequences of the processes of globalisation, which the french call la
mondialisation malheureuse in contradistinction to that of heureuse.2
As Harvard
economist Dani Rodrik has argued, there is a fundamental incompatibility
between hyper-globalization, on the one hand, and democracy and national
sovereignty, on the other.3
You cannot have all of them at the same time.
The spread of market economy and democracy —the concepts that are
considered by many to be as obvious goods as God, motherhood and apple-
pie— have in practice turned out to be a mixed blessing. If the planned
economy of the soviet type left everybody, and society as a whole, poor and
market freedoms may indeed be one of the preconditions for political free-
doms and personal liberties —the shock introduction of markets, especia-
lly unbridled markets, make a few extremely rich while many become even
poorer than they were under the previous system—. As one of the central
tenets of democracy (with some important qualifications of course) is that
the voice, interests or values of the many count more than those of the few, it
should be clear that economic “shock therapy” and political democracy are
incompatible and one either has a shock or democracy, not both. Cambridge
economist Ha-Joon Chang goes even further writing that “free market and
democracy are not natural partners”,4
though it must be emphasised that
professor Chang is speaking rather of “unbridled markets”, as advocated
by Milton Friedman or Alissa Zinovievna Rosenbaum (alias Ayn Rand) and
their followers.
2		
See, e.g., Guénolé, Thomas, La Mondialisation Malheureuse: Inégalité-pillage-oligarchie, First,
2016.
3		
Rodrik, D., “The Inescapable Trilemma of the World Economy”, June, 27 2007, avai-
lable at: https://rodrik.typepad.com/dani_rodriks_weblog/2007/06/the-inescapable.html.
4		
Chang, H. J., Bad Samaritans. Rich Nations, Poor Policies & the Threat to the Developing World,
Random House Business Books, 2007, p. 18.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
7
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
However, already more than half a century ago one of the most persistent
market-friendly advocates of political freedoms, Karl Popper, incisively wrote:
Even if the state protects its citizens from being bullied by physical violence (as
it does in principle, under the system of unrestrained capitalism), it may defeat
our ends by its failure to protect them from the misuse of economic power. In
such a state, the economically strong is still free to bully one who is economi-
cally weak, and to rob of his freedom. Under these circumstances, unlimited
economic freedom can be just as self-defeating as unlimited physical freedom,
and economic power may be nearly as dangerous as physical violence.5
Free market (capitalism) and liberal democracy, phenomena that, on the
one hand, presume each other, are at the same time also in constant rivalry.
The freer is a market, the greater is the economic inequality; the greater in-
equality, the less would there be democracy, and vice versa. Strong democracy
attained by curbing inequality almost inevitably also bridles market freedoms.
Economic inequality de facto and inevitably also increases political inequality,
while political equality puts breaks on the widening economic inequality. De-
mocracy tries to make a society more equal, while unbridled market increa-
ses inequality. The result of such constant balancing has been that in Wes-
tern European liberal democratic societies these two spheres —political and
economic— while supporting each other have also constantly tempered each
other, softened each other’s excesses.
However, this balance has not withstood the impact of the latest wave
of globalisation. John Dunn has observed that within the liberal democratic
movement “the partisans of the order of egoism”, i.e. capitalists, have defea-
ted “the partisans of equality”,6
i.e. democrats. One of the important causes
of equality’s defeat in the hands of economic egoism has been that, in the
long run, the uncompromising instruments for attempting to realize equality
and the rigidities inherent in its pursuit have blunted equality’s appeal as a
goal.7
Both the french and especially the russian revolutions, where contrary
to the american revolution, the aim was not, as Hannah Arendt wrote, the
“freedom from oppression” but “freedom from want”, and one of the main
requirements, therefore was egalité (equality), have contributed to such a mis-
balance within today’s liberal-democracy. Hannah Arendt observes that the
inescapable fact was that liberation from tyranny spelled freedom only for
5		
Popper, K., The Open Society and Its Enemies, Routledge, 1996, vol. 2 “Hegel & Marx”,
p. 124.
6		
Dunn, J., Setting the People Free. The Story of Democracy, Atlantic Books, 2005, p. 134.
7		
Ibidem, p. 129.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
8 REIN MÜLLERSON
a few and was hardly felt by the many who remained loaded down by their
misery. These had to be liberated once more and compared to this liberation
from the yoke of necessity, the original liberation from tyranny must have
looked like child’s play.8
Excesses of radical attempts to get rid of the “yoke
of necessity”, be it as a result of the french or the russian or the cuban revo-
lutions, have always led to radical suppression of individual liberties. These
facts, in turn, have been used by proponents of liberalism or neoliberalism
to suppress calls for more equality and also more democracy, while equality
has often been defined only as an equality of opportunity —you have the
right but cannot.
The process of globalisation has revealed and made acute not only the
contradiction between democracy and nationalism, whose ideal had become
enshrined in the concept of the nation-state and where modern democracy
emerged and evolved, but also between democracy and liberalism —both
economic and social—. Moreover, there is a bundle of interlinks that can-
not be unravelled without irreparably damaging at least some, if not all, of
them. Contemporary democracy, i.e. the government by the people and for
the people, emerged and evolved within nation-states and seems inseparable
from it. Yet, economic liberalism with global uncontrolled world financial
markets, together with social liberalism, putting the primacy of the indivi-
dual with her interests and desires above the interests of society, are destro-
ying social bonds that have helped hold societies together, and are, as a result,
also undermining nation-states —the cradles of democracy.
As it often happens, rare early warnings usually remain unheard. It was
more than twenty years ago when Richard Rorty published a small book,
Achieving our Country, where he wrote that the american liberal left, concentra-
ting on the rights of ethnic, racial, religious, cultural, and sexual minorities,
had neglected the widening gap between the rich and the poor. At some
point, Rorty warned
...something will crack. The nonsuburban electorate will decide that the sys-
tem has failed and start looking around for a strongman to vote for someone
willing to assure them that, once he is elected, the smug bureaucrats, tricky
lawyers, overpaid bond salesmen, and postmodern professors will no longer
be calling the shots.9
Sounds eerily familiar and up to date, doesn’t it? Rorty considered him-
self to belong to the category of liberal left, though as one of the brightest
8		
Arendt, H., On Revolution, Penguin Books, 1965, p. 74.
9		
Rorty, R., Achieving Our Country, Harvard, Harvard University Press, 1997, p. 90.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
9
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
representatives of american pragmatism, he hardly be branded as a post-
modern professor. And differently from many, if not from most, he did not
ridicule, deplore or detest those who were different, but tried to understand
them, which doesn’t necessarily mean to justify.10
IV. On the Adaptability to Rapid Change
The recent wave of globalisation has also exponentially increased the rapidity
of alterations in technology, economy, politics and in ways of life generally.
This speed of changes is exacerbating the rift between the elites and the mas-
ses since they have different adaptabilities to multiple challenges coming all
together as a row of roaring cars too long been held stationary by the red light.
French philosopher Barbara Stiegler, in her excellent study with a emblematic
title Il faut s’adapter (It is Necessary to Adapt),11
has shown how, at the beginning
of the twentieth century, two prominent american philosophers Walter Lipp-
mann and John Dewey had offered different answers to the question of the
adaptability to the rapid societal change caused by the industrial revolution
that has significant parallels with the current revolutionary period. She writes
about the 1920s:
For the first time in the evolution of life and living beings, one species —our
human species— finds itself in the situation, where it is not adapted to the new
environment. For Lippmann, it was the situation where there was a huge gap
between the natural inclination of the human species to remain as they are,
inherited from the long and slow history of biological and societal evolution,
and the demands of the rapid adaptability to the new environment, brutally
imposed by the industrial revolution. Hence, the central theme of Lippmann’s
political studies: how to adapt human species to constantly and rapidly chan-
ging environment… The fundamental question for Lippmann was how to
avoid that this tension between the change and stasis, openness and closing, do
not lead the masses to choose nationalism, fascism and generally all forms of
isolationisms, in their effort to oppose to the rapid change, to restore the stasis
and isolation.12
So, it was this abyss between slow historical and biological evolution of
human species and the rapidly changing physical and social environment,
caused by the industrial revolution, that worried Walter Lippmann. If at the
10		
In my opinion, Baruch Spinoza’s “non ridere, non lugere, neque detestere, sed intelligere” (don’t ri-
dicule, don’t deplore, don’t detest, but try to understand) is the best approach in social sciences.
11		
Stiegler, B., Il faut s’adapter: sur un nouvel impératif politique, Paris, Gallimard, 2019.
12		
Ibidem, p. 14.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
10 REIN MÜLLERSON
turn of the twentieth century it was the industrial revolution, also combi-
ned with economic globalisation, at the turn of the twenty first century it is
the revolution in information technology and whipped up hyper-globalisa-
tion of economic, and particularly, financial markets that have, once again,
uprooted masses of people in different countries, where only those who are
adaptable to the change can survive. This is a bio-social experiment of the
survival of the fittest and the fittest are the rationally thinking experts and
managers and impartial judges using rational laws, who know in which di-
rection the humankind must and will evolve. The masses should be taught to
suppress their irrational impulses and follow the lead of enlightened experts,
who have been able to adapt and readapt to the constantly changing environ-
ment. One of the main aims of public education should be “the manufacture
of the consent” of the masses with the policies manufactured by the experts.
As to the role of politicians, Lippmann writes that, “though he (the states-
man) cannot himself keep the life of the nation as a whole in his mind, he
can at least make sure that he is taking counsel from those who know”.13
A
politician has to be only an expert in the choice of experts.While Lippmann,
and all the neoliberals after him, saw the solution to the gap between rapidly
changing environment and the inability of the masses to adapt to the new
environment, in the combination of expertise of specialists and the applica-
tion of rational laws, Dewey would rely more on the collective intelligence of
masses. Dewey was also the first detractor of neoliberal thinking. He wrote:
A class of experts is inevitably cut off from the common interests to such an
extent that it becomes a class with its own private interests. Every governance
by experts where masses are unable to inform the experts of their needs can-
not be anything else than an oligarchy that rules in the interest of some. And
enlightened information has to force the specialists to take account of the ne-
eds of masses. The world has suffered more from leaders and authorities than
from masses.14
We see that this almost a century old intellectual confrontation that had
influenced policies of western governments for decades, has acquired today
a new acuteness. It is a conflict between elites and masses, between self-pro-
claimed progressives and those who are denigrated as populists. We see also
that due to the spread of the Internet and social media governments, be they
democratic or autocratic, are losing their ability to “manufacture of the con-
13		
Lippmann, W., A Preface to Politics, New York-London, Mitchell Kennerley, 1914, p. 98.
14		
Dewey, J., The Public and Its Problems in The Later Works of John Dewey 1925-1953, Southern
Illinois University Press, 1984, vol. 2, pp. 364 and 365.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
11
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
sent” of the masses with policies of the elites. It should not be forgotten what
Edward Bernays wrote in 1928:
The conscious and intelligent manipulation of the organized habits and opi-
nions of the masses is an important element in democratic society. Those who
manipulate this unseen mechanism of society constitute an invisible govern-
ment which is the true ruling power of our country... We are governed, our
minds are molded, our tastes formed, our ideas suggested, largely by men we
have never heard of. This is a logical result of the way in which our democra-
tic society is organized. Vast numbers of human beings must cooperate in this
manner if they are to live together as a smoothly functioning society... In almost
every act of our daily lives, whether in the sphere of politics or business, in our
social conduct or our ethical thinking, we are dominated by the relatively small
number of persons... who understand the mental processes and social patterns
of the masses. It is they who pull the wires which control the public mind.15
Although Bernays writes about manipulation of public consciousness in
democracies, it goes without saying that autocracies do the same. The more
advanced a country, the more sophisticated the manipulation, the more diffi-
cult to feel like being manipulated.
V. Populism as an Inadequate Response to the Conflict
between the Elites and the Masses
One of the most visible aspects or results of the aforementioned bundle of
controversies is the phenomenon of so-called populism. Already in 2008, in
my lectures at the Hague Academy of International Law, I spoke about the
dialectical contradictions between nationalism, liberalism and democracy and
the rise of populism.16
However, then these contradictions hadn’t yet reached
their today’s acuteness, while populism was still a marginal phenomenon, not
worthy of lengthy discussion. Those, who were accused of being populists
where primarily leftist leaders of some third-world countries like Hugo Cha-
vez of Venezuela or Rafael Correa of Ecuador.
Today, populism has become more and more also a western phenome-
non. French writer and journalist Alexandre Devecchio writes that notwiths-
15		
Bernays, E. L., Propaganda, Routledge, 1928, pp. 9 and 10. Later this book was publis-
hed in French with the title: Propaganda: comment manipuler l’opinion en démocratie (Zones, 2007), i.e.
how to manipulate public opinion in democracy.
16		
Müllerson, R., “Democracy Promotion: Institutions, International Law and Politics”,
Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of International Law, vol. 333, 2008.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
12 REIN MÜLLERSON
tanding variances between populisms in different societies there is in them
something important in common: “a desire to defend national sovereignty
and identity against globalisation, to significantly limit immigration, certain
hostility towards multiculturalism and support of programmes of social pro-
tection that benefit only citizens of the country”.17
This is indeed what uni-
tes politicians such as Donald Trump, Boris Johnson, Matteo Salvini, Victor
Orban, Marine Le Pen and others. One more important thing in common
between populisms is that differently from so-called (self-defined) progres-
sists, who, like president Emmanuel Macron of France, are leaders of cos-
mopolitan political, economic and intellectual elites, populists leaders find
support mainly among those who are left behind or have suffered because of
the processes of globalisation.
The rise of populism, besides the negative effects of globalisation, has
been boosted also by the revolution in information technology. Alexander
Devecchio compares the effect of the spread of the Internet to that of the
invention in 1454 of the printing press by Gutenberg. The latter undermi-
ned the power and position of the Roman Church and the clergy, which had
controlled the peoples’ minds, and had led to the emergence of the Protes-
tantism, as well as religious wars. Devecchio asks:
But if the invention of the web is going to provoke a similar fracture? This time
not between catholics and protestants, but between traditional elites, who are in
the process of losing their monopoly, which they have so far had over the mass
media and the spread of information, and a new elite that can convey their po-
pulist message through the non-traditional means of communication.18
Yascha Mounk observes that “the social media networks have closed the
gap between the people and the elites, between those who have the power
and those who don’t”.19
Traditional media has been considered, already for some time and with
some justification, as the “fourth power” of the State, together with legis-
lative, executive and judicial powers, though somewhat independent, but
nevertheless in the service of the economic, political and intellectual elites,
similar to the other three powers. For decades this separation of powers has
been relative, all of them served interests and reflected the values of eco-
nomic, political and intellectual elites. We have seen the real separation of
17		
Devecchio, A., Recomposition: Le nouveau monde populiste, Les éditions du Serf, 2019,
Loc. 724.
18		
Ibidem, Loc. 1581.
19		
Mounk, Y., The People vs. Democracy: Why our Freedom is in Danger and How to Save It, Har-
vard University Press, 2018.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
13
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
powers, for example, in the conflicts between president Donald Trump and
the American Congress and between Boris Johnson and the British Parlia-
ment on the issue of Brexit.
The dialectical controversy between democracy and liberalism has been
like a ticking bomb (une bombe à retardement) waiting for its time to explode.
Though these two phenomena —liberalism and democracy— have often
been supportive of each other, there has also been, as if by necessity, a cons-
tant balancing necessary between them. Most western, especially western
european societies have until recently managed this controversy relatively
well. In some, democracy has had an upper hand (e.g., in scandinavian so-
cial democracies), while in others liberalism has prevailed (e.g., in the United
States), but there has not been an open conflict between these phenomena.
However, already for decades, due, first, to the rapid globalisation of the
world and later also to the changing balance of power in the internatio-
nal system, this controversial friend/enemy relationship between democracy
and liberalism has become less friendly and more inimical. It is reflected, inter
alia, in the fact that liberal elites in most western countries have started labe-
lling those democrats, whose policies and ideas (or/and personalities) they do
not like, as populists (let us recall that Ralf Dahrendorf has noted that, “one
man’s populism is another’s democracy, and vice versa”, though he has also qua-
lified this statement by claiming that “while populism is simple, democracy
is complicated”).20
At the same time, democrats (or populists) have started
considering liberals to be arrogant elitists who have become alienated from
the people, from their needs and ways of thinking, believing them to be losers
and ill-informed (let’s recall Hillary Clinton’s characterisation, though later
hypocritically retracted, of Donald Trump’s supporters as “racist, sexist, ho-
mophobic deplorables”).
British author David Goodhart distinguishes between those Europeans
whom he calls Anywheres and those who according to him are Somewheres.21
If
the members of the first category (no more than 20-25% of the population
in the West and much less in the Rest) belong to the cosmopolitan elite that
has profited from globalisation and feels at home in different places in the
world, the majority (more than 50% in the West) feels a need to maintain so-
lid links to their country, to its history, traditions and language. To the latter
category belong, naturally, not only those who believe that globalisation has
by-passed them.
20		
Dahrendorf, R., “Acht Anmerkungen zum Populismus”, Transit-Europäische Revue, vol.
25, 2003, pp. 156-163.
21		
Goodhart, D., The Road to Somewhere: The New Tribes Shaping British Politics, Penguin, 2017.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
14 REIN MÜLLERSON
Tensions between solidarity and diversity, between the welfare state and
mass immigration have worsened, giving way to a growing divide between
the “people from anywhere” and “people of somewhere” or as Alexander
Devecchio puts it, between “sedentaries” and “nomads”.22
It is a conflict
between those who care for their “rootedness” or entrenchment in a defini-
tive place, be it a local village, a town or a nation-state and cosmopolitans,
i.e., those who feel at home in different places. There have always been a
minority those who see the whole world, or Europe as the case may be, as
their home, and a majority of those who feel at home only there, where they
were born and among those who speak the same language and profess the
same religion. For centuries, the first category was a relatively small minority,
while most of the people were born, lived and died in the same place, except
for mass movements of population that have several times occurred in the
history of humankind.
In the globalised world these are not only authoritarian regimes that sup-
press democratic impulses in their countries and may constitute a threat to
democracy elsewhere. The spread and liberalisation of global, particularly
financial, markets are curbing democracy everywhere. Increasing the overall
GDP of many countries, unbridled liberal markets make a few extremely
rich while the majority of people are left behind. The wealth gaps are increa-
sing practically in all countries. If in autocracies people are powerless vis-à-vis
their own rulers, in the globalised world people are powerless vis-à-vis global
markets, even if they live in so-called liberal democracies, even if they belong
to the so-called middle class. This is how economic liberalism is undermining
democracy. At the same time, the rise in importance of individual rights and
rights of a multitude of minorities, who aggressively promote their —often
newly-found— identity, is undermining social cohesion and common values.
This is how social liberalism undermines democracy. Societies that become
“atomized”, to use the English title of Michel Houllebecq’s novel Les Particu-
les élémentaires, become non-societies, where there is no place for democracy.
That is why today liberalism and democracy have become less and less sup-
portive of each other and often even more antagonistic.
There seems to be a disturbing parallel between the struggle for deco-
lonialisation with its mixed results and negative effects of the current (at
least before the COVID-19 hit the world) wave of globalisation. Those who
fought against colonial imperialism in Africa or elsewhere were considered
and revered as freedom-fighters, though it would be more correct to qualify
them as independence-fighters since the end result was usually independen-
ce form colonial masters and not at all freedom for the people. Many of
22		
Devecchio, A., op. cit., p. 1798.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
15
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
such leaders of national liberation movements were populists and quite a
few (e.g., Gamal Abdel Nasser, Fidel Castro and Robert Mugabe) of them
ended up as genuine dictators. However, when they fought against imperial
forces, they were seen by many, particularly in countries which they led to
independence, as real heroes. They were fighting against colonialism as a
specific form of previous centuries globalisation. Today’s western populists
are considered by cosmopolitan elites (and not only by those in their own
countries since one of the characteristics of current western elites is that they
are generally cosmopolitan) to be narrow-minded, inward-looking protectio-
nists, at best, or xenophobic nationalists, at worst. Yet, aren’t the effects of
the forces, today’s populists are against, similar or sometimes even identical
to the forces that the anticolonial freedom-fighters were struggling against.
Globalisation, global markets, particularly financial markets, deprive peoples
of any say on their future. These impersonal forces that have become un-
controllable make democratic decision-making meaningless. These are not
only masses of people in small or underdeveloped countries, who become
voiceless. Therefore, populists can be seen as freedom fighters against exces-
ses of globalisation, against the rules established, say, by GAFAs, pharma-
ceutical companies, military-industrial and military-intellectual complexes23
or governments which they control or influence. This tendency exists almost
everywhere. Only small groups of those belonging to cosmopolitan elites be-
nefit from surfing on the waves of globalisation, though quite a few of them
also fall and drown in the process. One of the few, but significant exceptions
in that respect may be China, where the central authorities have retained
and even strengthened, with the coming to power president Xi Jinping, con-
trol over processes globalisation, but China has its own problems.
Globalisation and the current migration tide, as one of its manifesta-
tions, are exacerbating today’s crisis of the European Union, where those
who can be anywhere do not understand those who want to be somewhere. The
first category, being dominant in politics, economy and media, are beha-
ving like liberal autocrats vis-à-vis those whom they consider belonging to
the mob. Such myopic arrogance carries a heavy political price-tag. Without
resolving this contradiction between the aspiration of European peoples to
be somewhere (to feel at home in France, in Germany, in Italy, in Estonia, in
Hungary) and ambitions of transnational elites to be anywhere, Europe will
not come out unscathed from the current crisis.
Populists are accused of dividing societies with their criticism of demo-
cratically elected governments and by-passing traditional media, which has
23		
See, Conesa, Pierre, Vendre la guerre: Le complexe militaro-intellectuel, De l’Aube, 2022. Whe-
re he analyses the role of intellectuals and think-tanks in paving the road to armed conflicts.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
16 REIN MÜLLERSON
been and remain generally supportive of authorities, being critical only of
some aspects or excesses of the authorities. But this is confusing the cause
and the effect. The populist parties and leaders have become prominent
namely because Western societies have become more and more unequal
and divided. There is quite a lot of truth in the accusations from both si-
des —from the side of self-declared progressists as well as from the side of
those whom their critics call populists. In a way and simplifying a bit, both
Brexit and Trump’s victory have been triumphs of populism over elitism (or
if you like, democracy over liberalism). Personally, I don’t like Boris Johnson
because of his rude manners and being too often, even for a politician, eco-
nomical with the truth; as an estonian national living in London with his fa-
mily, who are all estonian passport holders, I don’t like Brexit either. Yet, this
doesn’t mean that I cannot see genuine concerns of Brexiteers. As canadian
essayist Mathieu Bock-Coté writes, “there are, no doubt, among populist po-
liticians extreme rights who nurture crazy and repulsive ideas, but it would
be wrong to confuse ideological obsessions of such politicians and those real
issues that form the basis of a significant part of the electorate and public
concerns that have been censured by the dominant ideology”.24
These are
the faults of so-called mainstream political parties, be they of centre-right
or centre-left, which have neglected these real issues. Populist leaders can
exploit only what is exploitable.
Populist parties of movements may face setbacks in coming elections and
their popularity ratings may suffer. However, the phenomenon is not going
away, as its sources persist. Moreover, so-called mainstream parties are more
and more using populist slogans and policies. The clearest example of this
tendency is the metamorphoses of the British Tories, who under Boris Jo-
hnson were not any more a traditional conservative party, as we had known
it. Having used some traditional Labour Party precepts and slogans as well as
Nigel Farage’s Brexit Party ideas, luring voters from both of them, the Tories
have become a populist party —partly left-wing, partly right-wing.
VI. “Illiberal Democracy”, “Undemocratic
Liberalism” and “Liberal Imperialism”
After Fareed Zakaria published, a quarter of a century ago, an article on “illi-
beral democracy”,25
the term, reflecting various degrees of reality, has become
24		
Bock-Coté, M., Le Multiculturalisme comme Religion Politique, Cerf, 2019, pp. 291-292.
25		
Zakaria, F., “The Rise of Illiberal Democracy”, Foreign Affairs, november-december
1997.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
17
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
firmly anchored in both academic as well as in political discourse. Agreeing
with Zakaria that there are democracies where liberal values are not in high
esteem, I have always wonded whether the reverse can be also true? Could
there exist political regimes that may be defined as liberal but undemocratic?
Of course, there have been authoritarian regimes that have been economi-
cally liberal, but socially conservative, like Chile under General Pinochet or
South Korea under military rulers. However, in Western democracies these
two sides of liberalism —economics and social affairs— have been, more or
less, like the two sides of the same coin.
If in illiberal democracy it is democracy that trumps liberalism, under
undemocratic liberalism it is liberalism that has the upper hand and puts
constraints on democracy. And my answer is that there can be, and in prac-
tice there are, political regimes that may be defined as “liberal”, but which
have serious deficit of democracy. Undemocratic liberalism could be defined
as a political regime, where out of the triptych —the government of the
people, by the people and for the people— only the first still fully stands,
i.e. where the participation of the people in the governance is both formal
and ineffective and where the governance is exercised not in the interest of
the majority of the people. Leaving aside societies where there is neither
democracy nor liberalism, like Saudi Arabia or North Korea, and concen-
trating attention on societies where these phenomena —democracy and libe-
ralism— have existed for some time and still exist, it seems that many, if not
most, Western societies have been infested with the germ of “undemocratic
liberalism”. While liberal ideas are prevalent among European elites, values
of democracy are today often expressed by populist parties and movements.
There is a lot of truth in Chantal Delsol’s observation that “the he populists,
contrary to what some may say, are really democrats, but they are not libe-
rals. At the same time, universalist elites, like those in Brussels, are really
liberals, who are not any more democrats since they don’t like when people
vote to limit some liberties”.26
Using sanctions against “illiberal democra-
cies”, be they members of the EU, like Hungary or Poland, or beyond, “un-
democratic liberals” (the prime example of them being the European Union
itself) are imposing their will and vision (values) on those who from their
point of view are on the wrong side of history.
Therefore, there exists not only undemocratic (or authoritarian) libera-
lism, but we are also facing the rise of liberal imperialism, euphemistically
described as “liberal international order”, giving additional impetus to the
rise of nationalistic populism. Liberal imperialism, i.e. attempts to impose
liberal values, either by persuasion or by force, as universal values to all and
26		
Delsol, C., “Populiste, c’est un adjectif pour injurier ses adversaires”, Le Figaro Vox, 2018.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
18 REIN MÜLLERSON
everybody, is a wake-up call for those for whom, say, collectivistic values,
historical traditions, stability or national independence are more, or at least
not less, important than individual liberties. Many influential liberal authors,
be they philosophers or economists, have been campaigners for liberal im-
perial order. Friedrich Hayek, one of the most important theoreticians of
liberalism of the last century, believed that the idea of interstate federation
would be “the consistent development of liberal point of view”,27
while Lud-
wig von Mises advocated the end of nation-states and creation of a “world
super-state”.28
In an interesting, though controversial (often these two adjectives are
necessarily interlinked), book Israeli author Yoram Hazony writes that when
the struggle against communism ended
…the Western minds became preoccupied with two great imperialist pro-
jects: the European Union, which has progressively relieved member nations
of many of the powers usually associated with political independence; and
the project of establishing an American “world order”, in which nations that
do not abide by international law will be coerced into doing so, principally
by means of American military might. These are imperialist projects, even
though their proponents do not like to call them like that.29
In defence of international law it should be said that it is not this rather
noble normative system, which willy-nilly worked even during the Cold War,
that Washington tries to impose by its military might and financial domi-
nation, but so-called “rules-based liberal international order”, i.e. the order
based on rules determined in Washington that has nothing to do with inter-
national law. And it is not accidental that the only aspiring global empire is
accusing those opposing its imperial ambitions, especially China and Russia,
of building, or restoring, their own empires.
It would be unfair, in my opinion, to accuse the European Union of
being an imperial project, though one may agree that promising (and acting
on this promise) to create an “ever-closer union”, a kind of federal Europe,
European political elites gradually became more and more detached from
the aspirations of their peoples. It is becoming increasingly obvious that Eu-
ropean societies, in contradistinction to political elites, are not (not yet, at
least) ready to throw the nation-state into the dustbin of history. Both the
liberal lefts and the conservative rights have become concerned about their
27		
Hayek, F., The Economic Conditions of Interstate Federalism, available at: https://fee.org/arti
cles/the-economic-conditions-of-interstate-federalism.
28		
Mises, L. von, Liberalism in the Classical Tradition, Cobden Press, 1985, p. 150.
29		
Hazony, Y., The Virtue of Nationalism, Basic Books, 2018, pp. 3 and 4.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
19
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
identity. However, if the first try to find their identity in the belongingness to
a multitude of small, often marginalized, groups (depending on sexual orien-
tation, specific interests or ways of life), the second usually try to find or
restore their affinity within bigger communities, like nations, nation-states
or traditional religions. However, even if the EU in itself is not an imperial
project, the ongoing war of the collective West against Russia —the war that
dare not speak its name— after the Kremlin’s reckless invasion of Ukraine,
shows that the European Union has become a part of the American imperial
project. Moreover, joining against their own best interest Washington’s anti-
Chinese policies, European nations have lost the remnants of independent
decision-making in world politics. Therefore, Yoram Hazony is right when
asserting that:
...[f]or all their bickering, proponents of the liberal construction are united
in endorsing a single imperialist vision: They wish to see a world in which
liberal principles are codified as universal law and imposed on the nations, if
necessary by force. This, they agree, is what will bring us universal peace and
prosperity.30
VII. Is “e pluribus unum” indeed
Replacing “ex uno plures”?
The motto E Pluribus Unum, written on the US dollar in Latin, reads in plain
English: “out of many-one”. It symbolises not only the union between the
thirteen states forming in 1776 a Federation, but also the melting pot idea of
the American political system, aimed at making the Americans out of various
migrants of European, mostly Anglo-Saxon, extraction. Now, two and a half
centuries later, Washington is in the vanguard of spreading American way of
life, including the melting pot experience, all over the world. The greenback
itself has been since the end of WWII the reserve currency of the world ser-
ving as an instrument of American domination. Attempts by Russia, China
and some other nations, who suffer or potentially may suffer from Ameri-
can “sanctions”, to dedollarise the world economy and thereby undermining
the foundations of American dominance, is one of the underlying causes of
Washington’s efforts to aggressively push back Russia and contain China.
However, tens of thousands of years before anybody used Latin, or any
other known language for that matter, another, an opposite process had be-
gun that could be called “out of one-many” (ex uno plures). It began (allegedly,
30		
Ibidem, p. 45.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
20 REIN MÜLLERSON
since new discoveries may further change the dates and locations) more than
50 000 years ago when the Homo Sapiens started his journey from an East
African village to all over the world. During that pilgrimage, our forefathers
and foremothers, who at the beginning of this migration obviously did not
differ much from each other as to the colour of their skin, slant of their eyes
or the ways in which they communicated between themselves, acquired visi-
ble physical and profound cultural differences, though remaining members
of the same species of Homo Sapiens. This process of the colonisation of
the planet Earth, during which “out of one emerged many”, was slow; it
took tens of thousands of years until foot-and fingerprints of Homo Sapiens
could be found in all hospitable, and today even inhospitable, places on Ear-
th. Being always genetically very similar, humans became visibly (superficia-
lly), depending mostly of their physical environment, rather different (some
blue-eyed, others dark-eyed, some tall while others much shorter and so on).
However, in contradistinction to these superficial (therefore easily visible) di-
fferences, groups of Homo Sapiens, gradually forming tribes, ethnic groups,
nations and civilisations, became profoundly different from each other in
terms of their cultures, religions, mores and languages spoken. As Ameri-
can philosopher Michael Walzer once aptly put it: “[e]very human society is
universal because it is human, particular because it is a society”.31
Cultural
differences between peoples, be they historical, religious or ethical, that may
or may not be immediately visible, over the millennia became huge and they
still remain profound. As physical or biological beings we are rather similar,
as social animals we may be worlds apart.
American social psychologist Jonathan Haidt has persuasively demons-
trated that even in today’s world there still coexist at least three different
categories of societies: those with the ethics of autonomy, those with the
ethics of community and those with the ethics of divinity. In the first cate-
gory, the individual with her wants, needs and preferences runs prime; in the
second, concepts such as duty, hierarchy, respect, reputation and patriotism
are predominant, while in the third prevails the idea that people are, first
and foremost, only temporary vessels within which a divine soul has been im-
planted.32
Professor Haidt concludes his essay with a warning against moral
monists: “[b]eware of anyone who insists that there is one true morality for
all people, times, and places —particularly if that morality is founded upon
31		
Walzer, M., Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad, University of Notre Dame
Press, 1994, p. 8.
32		
Haidt, J., The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion, Penguin,
2013, p. 116.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
21
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
a single moral foundation”.33
However, notwithstanding such learned voices
and warnings, there have been, and still are, those who in their provincial ig-
norance of the complexities and societal differences existing in the world try
not only to unify the world but also make it uniform, be it, say, communist,
liberal democratic or Muslim. Such worldviews have their roots in the Judeo-
Christian and Enlightenment’s belief in a universal history and in constant
progress leading inexorably towards some specific goal where history ends.
Those who don’t recognise this truth, it is argued, are “on the wrong side of
history”. If the communist experiment of the realisation of universal history
has, at least for the time being, miserably failed, then liberal democratic pro-
jects for the whole world are, notwithstanding all the red lights blinking here
and there, still actively promoted. Even Islamists have joined the ranks of
such “practical utopians” by their attempts to Islamise the globe, beginning
with the Middle East. All these movements contain a mixture of determi-
nism and voluntarism: the belief in an unavoidable unilineal course of his-
tory (i.e. determinism) and, the burning desire to accelerate the coming of
inevitable bright future in one or another form (i.e. voluntarism).
One may, of course, reasonably argue that the process of global he-
terogenisation, expressed in Ex Uno Plures, has by now if not come to an
end then at least considerably slowed down. Indeed, there are many signs
of global homogenisation, as articulated in the formula E Pluribus Unum.
Within the general process of globalisation, we can distinguish global homo-
genisation combined with the heterogenisation within individual societies, i.e.
if societies become a bit more similar to each other, there is more diversity
within most of them. To an extent, these are natural processes. It is to be ex-
pected that different societies interacting, rubbing shoulders and borrowing
from those with whom they interact, may become, at least in some respects,
more similar to each other. It may indeed be that instead of Ex Uno Plures
humankind has already begun a reverse journey towards E Pluribus Unum.
However, the processes of heterogenisation that went on for tens of thou-
sands of years, if not longer, cannot be undone within decades and probably
even within centuries, if ever. Even if some individuals from different socie-
ties can cross the boundaries of their cultural and ethical communities, to
step, so to say, outside of their “moral matrix”, or sometimes even straddle
and enjoy more than one of them, communities themselves change much
more slowly, and changes that are instigated and forced on them, either from
above or from the outside, may have lasting negative effects. Yet, there are
those who seek to artificially accelerate the processes of global homogenisa-
tion, using, inter alia, human rights discourse, exportation of democracy and
33		
Ibidem, p. 368.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
22 REIN MÜLLERSON
liberal values, carrying out operations of regime change, sometimes using
military force for that purpose. Such “one size fits all” policies foreseeably
spread chaos and destruction instead of democracy and human rights. The
much advertised and enthusiastically welcomed by the West “Arab spring”
led to the collapse of statehood in Iraq, Libya, Syria and Yemen, while in
other Middle East nations the authorities, to avoid likely implosion, returned
to authoritarian rule (e.g., Egypt, Tunisia). Even admitting that the process
of “out of one-many” has ended, and the tendency of “out of many-one” is
manifesting itself in the processes of globalisation, it would be irresponsible
to try to artificially accelerate this movement. Moreover, the end of history,
be it either à la Karl Marx or à la Francis Fukuyama, would also be the end
of social experimentation. The uniformity of social, economic or political
systems would also mark the end of societal progress. Diversity between so-
cieties is no less important than biodiversity or diversity within societies or-
ganised as States. Moreover, the world is simply too big, complex and diverse
to have its rich tapestry to be flattened into a carpet where only one pattern,
be it a Judeo-Christian, Anglo-Saxon, Confucian, Muslim or even secular
liberal-democratic, dominates.
VIII. Bibliography
Arendt, H., On Revolution, Penguin Books, 1965.
Bernays, E. L., Propaganda, Routledge, 1928.
Bock-coté, M., Le Multiculturalisme comme Religion Politique, Cerf, 2019.
Chang, H. J., Bad Samaritans, Rich Nations, Poor Policies & the Threat to the Deve-
loping World, Random House Business Books, 2007.
Conesa, P., Vendre la guerre: Le complexe militaro-intellectuel, De l’Aube, 2022.
Dahrendorf, R., “Acht Anmerkungen zum Populismus”, Transit-Europäische
Revue, vol. 25, 2003.
Delsol, C., “Populiste, c’est un adjectif pour injurier ses adversaires”, Le
Figaro, Vox, 2018.
Devecchio, A., Recomposition: Le nouveau monde populiste, Cerf, 2019.
Dewey, J., The Public and its Problems in The Later Works of John Dewey 1925-
1953, Southern Illinois University Press, vol. 2, 1984.
Dunn, J., Setting the People Free. The Story of Democracy, Atlantic Books, 2005.
Goodhart, D., The Road to Somewhere: The New Tribes Shaping British Politics,
Penguin, 2017.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
23
QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY...
Guénolé, Thomas, La Mondialisation Malheureuse: Inégalité-pillage-oligarchie,
First, 2016.
Haidt, J., The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion,
Penguin, 2013.
Hayek, F., “The Economic Conditions of Interstate Federalism”, available
at: https://fee.org/articles/the-economic-conditions-of-interstate-federalism.
Hazony, Y., The Virtue of Nationalism, Basic Books, 2018.
Lippmann, W., A Preface to Politics, New York, London, Mitchell Kennerley,
1914.
Mounk, Y., The People vs. Democracy: Why our Freedom is in Danger and How to
Save It, Harvard University Press, 2018.
Müllerson, R., “Democracy Promotion: Institutions, International Law
and Politics”, Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of International Law, vol.
333, 2008.
Müllerson, R., “The Nation-State: Not Yet Ready for the Dustbin of His-
tory?”, The Chinese Journal of International Law, vol. 20, núm. 4, Diciembre
2021.
Popper, K., The Open Society and Its Enemies, Routledge, vol. 2: Hegel & Marx,
1996.
Rodrik, D., “The inescapable trilemma of the world economy”, June 27,
2007, available at: https://rodrik.typepad.com/dani_rodriks_weblog/2007/06/
the-inescapable.html.
Rorty, R., Achieving Our Country, Harvard University Press, 1997.
Stiegler, B., Il faut s’adapter: sur un nouvel impératif politique, Paris, Gallimard,
2019.
Von Mises, L., Liberalism in the Classical Tradition, Cobden Press, 1985.
Walzer, M., Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad, University of
Notre Dame Press, 1994.
Zakaria, F., “The Rise of Illiberal Democracy”, Foreign Affairs, November-
December, 1997.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
25
THE PROVISION OF ARMS TO THE VICTIM OF ARMED
AGGRESSION: THE CASE OF UKRAINE
Stefan Talmon*
Summary: I. Introduction. II. Providing Arms and Material to Ukraine.
III. Provision of Arms and the Traditional Law of Neutrality. IV. Neutra-
lity and the United Nations Charter. V. Provision of Arms and Collective
Self-Defence. VI. Provision of Arms as a Countermeasure. VII. Inappli-
Cability of the Law of Neutrality in Case of Aggression. VIII. Conclusion.
IX. Bibliography.
I. Introduction
On 24 February 2022, the Russian Federation launched a full-scale invasion
of Ukraine which amounted to a naked act of aggression.1
For my long-time
friend and colleague Manuel Becerra Ramírez, like for any true friend of Rus-
sia, this must have been a bleak day. For many years, Manuel has had a strong
connection with Russia. He conducted his doctoral studies there in the early
1980s under the supervision of the world-renowned professor Grigory I. Tun-
kin, and in 1985 he received his degree of doctor of philosophy in Interna-
tional Law from the prestigious Lomonosov State University in Moscow after
defending his thesis on Mexico and the New International Economic Order: Legal As-
pects (in Russian). In 1989, Manuel translated professor Tunkin’s famous book
on Law and Force in the International System from russian into spanish. Both legal
questions concerning Russia and the former Soviet Union and questions on
the legal and political aspects of the use of force have been recurring themes
in Manuel’s academic work ever since. It is thus fitting to devote this short
piece in his honour to a legal question resulting from Russia’s illegal invasion
of Ukraine.
*		
Director at the Institute for Public International Law, University of Bonn; Supernume-
rary Fellow, St Anne’s College, Oxford; Barrister, Twenty Essex Chambers, London.
1		
See, e.g., Green, James et al., “Russia’s Attack on Ukraine and the jus ad bellum”, Journal
on the Use of Force and International Law, vol. 9, 2022. (Forthcoming)
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
26 STEFAN TALMON
II. Providing Arms and Material to Ukraine
On the third day of Russia’s illegal war of aggression against Ukraine, the
German Federal Government broke with a long-standing tenet of german
security policy and announced that it would deliver 1,000 anti-tank weapons
and 500 surface-to-air missiles, as well as 14 armoured vehicles and urgently
needed fuel to Ukraine in order to support the country in its defence against the
advancing russian troops.2
On the same day, it was also reported that the fede-
ral government had granted export permits to the Netherlands and Estonia to
send 400 german-made rocket-propelled grenade launchers and nine german
howitzers to Ukraine, respectively. A few days later, the federal government
decided to send another 2,700 anti-aircraft missiles to Ukraine.3
Several other
western States also provided Ukraine with significant military assistance in its
ongoing armed conflict with Russia.4
III. Provision of Arms and the Traditional
Law of Neutrality
The provision of arms to Ukraine has been considered a violation of the law
of neutrality yet did not make Germany and the other States assisting Ukraine
parties to the armed conflict.5
The law of neutrality regulates the relationship
between States that are parties to an international armed conflict (belligerents)
and States that are not (neutrals). The core of today’s customary internatio-
nal law of neutrality was laid down in two of the 1907 Hague Conventions
on the laws of war.6
The legal position of the neutral is characterized by the
2		
McGuinness, Damien, “Germany to Send Weapons Directly to Ukraine”, BBC News,
February 26, 2022, available at: https://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-60541752.
3		
“Germany to Ship Anti-Aircraft Missiles to Ukraine”, Deutsche Welle, March 3rd, 2022,
available at: https://p.dw.com/p/47vfZ.
4		
See Duthois, Thomas, “Ukraine War: Which Countries are Sending Weapons and Aid
to Forces Fighting the Russian Invasion?”, Euronews, March 4, 2022, available at: https://www.
euronews.com/next/2022/03/04/ukraine-war-these-countries-are-sending-weapons-and-aid-to-forces-
fighting-the-russian-inv.
5		
See,e.g.,VonHartwig,Matthias,“WaffenlieferungenanddieUkraine:FührtDeutschland
jetztKrieg?”,FrankfurterAllgemeineZeitungEinspruch,March1st.,2022,availableat:https://www.faz.
net/einspruch/waffenlieferungen-an-die-ukraine-fuehrt-deutschland-jetzt-krieg-17843930.html; Krajewski,
Markus, “Neither Neutral nor Party to the Conflict?: On the Legal Assessment of Arms Supp
lies to Ukraine”, Völkerrechtsblog, March 9, 2022, doi: 10.17176/20220310-000928-0.
6		
Convention (V) Regarding the Rights and Duties of Neutral Powers and Persons in
Case of War on Land, 18 October 1907; Convention (XIII) Respecting the Rights and Du-
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
27
THE PROVISION OF ARMS TO THE VICTIM OF ARMED...
duties of abstention, impartiality, and prevention; that is, the neutral State
must abstain from participating in the armed conflict, it must not discriminate
between the belligerents, and it must prevent violations of its neutrality and its
national territory by the belligerents. In particular, the law of neutrality prohi-
bits neutrals from providing weapons, ammunition and other war material to
the belligerents or supporting them in any other way, for example by providing
militarily intelligence.7
Violations of these duties can be punished by a bellige-
rent with countermeasures or armed reprisals and, ultimately, with treatment
of the assisting State as a warring party.
IV. Neutrality and the United Nations Charter
With the founding of the United Nations (UN) in 1945, the hour of neutrality
seemed to have come. Hans Kelsen pertinently observed that “the obligation
of impartiality imposed by general international law upon neutral States is su-
perseded by the Charter”.8
Under the system of collective security established
by the UN Charter, the use of force was generally prohibited, and the Security
Council was given primary responsibility for the maintenance of international
peace and security. In case force was used in violation of the prohibition, the
Security Council was to determine the aggressor and make recommendations
or decide what measures should be taken to restore international peace and
security.9
All members of the organization were to assist the United Nations in
any action the Security Council decided to take against the aggressor.10
In June 1950, for example, the Security Council determined that “the
armed attack on the Republic of Korea by forces from North Korea” cons-
tituted “a breach of the peace”,11
and recommended that “the Members of
the United Nations furnish such assistance to the Republic of Korea as may
be necessary to repel the armed attack and to restore international peace
ties of Neutral Powers in Naval Warfare, 18 October 1907, reproduced in (1908) 2 American
Journal of International Law 117 and 202, respectively.
7		
See, e.g., Bothe, Michael, “Neutrality, Concept and General Rules”, in Wolfrum, Rüdi-
ger (ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
2012, vol. VII, pp. 617-634; at 624 MN 36.
8		
Kelsen, Hans, Principles of International Law, New York, Rinehart & Company, 1952, pp.
87 and 88.
9		
See Charter of the United Nations, UN Charter, 1945, Documents of the United
Nations Conference on International Organization, vol. XV (1945) 335, Articles 2(4), 24,
39. On the UN Charter and the law of neutrality, see James Upcher, Neutrality in Contemporary
International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020) 129-135.
10		
UN Charter, Article 2(5).
11		
UN Security Council resolution 82 (1950), June 25, 1950, UN Doc. S/1501.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
28 STEFAN TALMON
and security in the area”.12
When the military forces of Iraq invaded Kuwait
in August 1990, the Security Council condemned the Iraqi invasion as “a
breach of international peace and security”.13
Subsequently, the Security
Council imposed sanctions on Iraq in order to induce it to withdraw its forces
from Kuwait.14
However, the Council expressly made it clear that its deci-
sions did not prohibit assistance to the legitimate government of Kuwait.15
In
these cases, there was thus no room for impartiality towards the conflicting
parties —the law of neutrality was not applicable.
Such clear determinations of the aggressor, however, remained the ex-
ception in the practice of the Security Council. The design of the UN Char-
ter was flawed from the outset. As early as 1948, Philip C. Jessup identified,
a “gap” in the United Nations’ collective security system.16
If one of the
five permanent members of the Security Council committed an act of ag-
gression or desired to block action, perhaps because of sympathy with the
aggressor, that Council member could, by exercising its veto power, prevent
the Council from designating the aggressor and taking any action to restore
international peace and security. He wrote:
...[i]f the veto is exercised and action by the United Nations is thus blocked,
completely or for a period of time, fighting between the parties may continue
over a period of any duration permitted by the conditions of the contest and
the contestants. During such a period, what is to be the legal position of third
states and their nationals?”.17
In such circumstances, many international lawyers assumed that the tra-
ditional law of neutrality would continue to apply.18
The flaw in the design of the UN Charter became evident again in the
case of the russian invasion of Ukraine. On February 25, 2022, Russia ve-
toed a draft resolution which had been supported by 82 States.19
In that re-
solution the Security Council would have “deplore[d] in the strongest terms
12		
UN Security Council resolution 83 (1950), June 27, 1950, UN Doc. S/1511.
13		
UN Security Council resolution 660 (1990), August 2nd, 1990, UN Doc. S/RES/660
(1990), preambular para. 2.
14		
UN Security Council resolution 661 (1990), August 6, 1990, UN Doc. S/RES/661
(1990), paras. 2-4.
15		
Ibidem, para. 9.
16		
Jessup, Philip C., A Modern Law of Nations, New York, Macmillan, 1948, p. 203.
17		
Idem.
18		
See, e.g., Bothe (n. 7) 619 MN 9.
19		
See UN Security Council, 77th
year, 8979th
meeting, 25 February 2022, UN Doc. S/
PV.8979, p. 6.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
29
THE PROVISION OF ARMS TO THE VICTIM OF ARMED...
the Russian Federation’s aggression against Ukraine in violation of Article
2, paragraph 4 of the United Nations Charter” and would have “decide[d]
that the Russian Federation shall immediately cease its use of force against
Ukraine” and “shall immediately, completely, and unconditionally withdraw
all of its military forces from the territory of Ukraine”.20
In the absence of
any action by the Security Council, some commentators assumed that the
law of neutrality was applicable and that it was being violated by the provi-
sion of arms to Ukraine.21
This, however, is not the case as will be shown in
the following sections.
V. Provision of Arms and Collective Self-Defence
Some authors have tried to justify the provision of arms to Ukraine as an
exercise of the inherent right to collective self-defence under Article 51 of
the UN Charter in response to russia’s armed attack on the country.22
It has
been argued that, if States may take part in an armed conflict using their own
armed forces to defend the victim of aggression, they must also be allowed to
provide the victim with arms and munitions in order to enable it to defend
itself. German government officials also seem to have alluded to collective
self-defence when justifying the arms deliveries to Ukraine. In an interview
broadcast on March 18, 2022, the Minister of State at the Federal Foreign
Office stated: “[t]he arms deliveries are clearly legitimate in this situation. We
have a war of aggression contrary to international law, and it is Ukraine’s right
to defend itself and our right to help it defend itself. And that is covered by the
UN Charter”.23
While this may be true in principle, the problem in the present case is
that neither Germany nor any other State which provided arms to Ukraine
formally invoked the right to collective self-defence. In particular, no State
reported these arms deliveries to the Security Council. Article 51 of the UN
20		
UN Security Council, Albania et al.: draft resolution, UN Doc. S/2022/155, 25 Fe-
bruary 2022, paras. 2-4.
21		
See, e.g., Hartwig, Matthias von, op. cit.; Krajewski, Markus, op. cit.
22		
See, e.g., Ambos, Kai, “Will a State Supplying Weapons to Ukraine Become a Party
to the Conflict and thus be Exposed to Countermeasures?”, EJIL: Talk!, March 2nd, 2022,
https://www.ejiltalk.org/will-a-state-supplying-weapons-to-ukraine-become-a-party-to-the-conflict-and-
thus-be-exposed-to-countermeasures/; Schmitt, Michael N., “Providing Arms and Material to
Ukraine: Neutrality, Co-Belligerency, and the Use of Force”, Articles of War, March 7, 2022,
available at: https://lieber.westpoint.edu/ukraine-neutrality-co-belligerency-use-of-force/.
23		
Eschenhagen, Philipp et al., “Ukrainekrieg mit Katja Keul”, Völkerrechtsblog, March 18,
2022, DOI: 10.17176/20220318-120945-0.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
30 STEFAN TALMON
Charter, however, requires Member States to report immediately to the Se-
curity Council any measures taken in the exercise of the right of self-defence.
In contrast, following the armed terrorist attack on the United States on Sep-
tember 11, 2001,24
and the armed attacks by the terrorist organization Islamic
State on Iraq, France and other States, the German Federal Government had
immediately informed the Security Council of the measures taken within
the framework of collective self-defence.25
One reason why States did not
invoke the right to collective self-defence might be that it would have made
them “co-belligerents” of Ukraine in the latter’s armed conflict with Russia.
For both legal and (internal) political reasons, the States supporting Ukraine
wanted to avoid being seen as parties to the conflict.
VI. Provision of Arms as a Countermeasure
The provision of arms to Ukraine has also been justified as a “countermeasu-
re” within the context of the law of State responsibility.26
An injured State may
counter an internationally wrongful act by not performing for the time being its
own international obligations toward the responsible State —here the obliga-
tion of impartiality under the law of neutrality— in order to induce the latter
to comply with its obligations under international law.27
Back in the 1950s,
several authors had argued, for example, that by resorting to war in viola-
tion of the General Treaty for the Renunciation of War (the “Kellogg-Briand
Pact” or “Pact of Paris”),28
a State violated the rights of all other Contracting
Parties. The latter were thereby entitled to take measures of “reprisal” against
the aggressor that could involve a departure from the duty of impartiality
otherwise imposed on non-participants of an armed conflict by the traditional
law of neutrality.29
States which provided arms to the victim of aggression
24		
See UN Security Council, Letter dated on 29 November 2001 from the Permanent
Representative of Germany to the United Nations addressed to the President of the Security
Council, UN Doc. S/2001/1127, November 29, 2001.
25		
See UN Security Council, Letter dated on December 10, 2015 from the Chargé
d’affaires a.i. of the Permanent Mission of Germany to the United Nations addressed to the
President of the Security Council, S/2015/946, 10 December 2015.
26		
See, e.g., Ambos (22).
27		
See Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts (Articles on
State Responsibility), adopted by the International Law Commission on August 3, 2001, ILC
Yearbook 2001, vol. II/2, 26, Article 49.
28		
General Treaty for the Renunciation of War as an Instrument of National Policy, done
at Paris 27 August 1928, 94 LNTS 59.
29		
See, e.g., Kelsen, Hans, Principles…, cit., p. 87; Kelsen, Hans, “Collective Security under
International Law”, International Law Studies, vol. 49, 1954.
Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM
www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj
DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf
El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf

Más contenido relacionado

Similar a El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf

Los recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUEL
Los recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUELLos recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUEL
Los recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUELKatherine Quijón
 
ANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdf
ANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdfANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdf
ANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdfkarenzun14
 
Anonimo 11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacion
Anonimo   11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacionAnonimo   11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacion
Anonimo 11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacionvyktor Anabalon
 
La abogacia en mexico
La abogacia en mexicoLa abogacia en mexico
La abogacia en mexicoLuz De Vida
 
1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docx
1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docx1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docx
1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docxEduardoToscano8
 
Antología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdf
Antología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdfAntología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdf
Antología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdfMiguel Toralla
 
2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en Venezuela
2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en Venezuela2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en Venezuela
2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en VenezuelaEspacio Público
 
Descolonizar el saber_final.pdf
Descolonizar el saber_final.pdfDescolonizar el saber_final.pdf
Descolonizar el saber_final.pdfPaolaTopolanski
 
Descolonizar el saber final boaventura cópia
Descolonizar el saber final   boaventura cópiaDescolonizar el saber final   boaventura cópia
Descolonizar el saber final boaventura cópiaMiguel Gaitan
 
Apuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSR
Apuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSRApuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSR
Apuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSRMauri Rojas
 
Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...
Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...
Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...frank0071
 
La-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdf
La-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdfLa-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdf
La-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdfjavierluciohuancahua
 
Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...
Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...
Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...Maite Pelacho
 

Similar a El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf (20)

Los recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUEL
Los recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUELLos recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUEL
Los recursos procesales - MARIO MOSQUERA RUIZ - CRISTIAN MATURANA MIQUEL
 
0586
05860586
0586
 
ANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdf
ANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdfANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdf
ANTOLOGÍAS PARA EL ESTUDIO Y ENSEÑANZA DE LA CP.pdf
 
Anonimo 11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacion
Anonimo   11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacionAnonimo   11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacion
Anonimo 11 de septiembre. las caras de la globalizacion
 
La abogacia en mexico
La abogacia en mexicoLa abogacia en mexico
La abogacia en mexico
 
329154 135596-1-pb
329154 135596-1-pb329154 135596-1-pb
329154 135596-1-pb
 
1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docx
1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docx1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docx
1 guia ddactica cs 10° 1p 23.docx
 
Antología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdf
Antología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdfAntología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdf
Antología para el estudio y la enseñanza de la ciencia política.pdf
 
Tc
TcTc
Tc
 
2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en Venezuela
2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en Venezuela2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en Venezuela
2004 Situación del Derecho a la Libertad de Expresión e Información en Venezuela
 
Descolonizar el saber_final.pdf
Descolonizar el saber_final.pdfDescolonizar el saber_final.pdf
Descolonizar el saber_final.pdf
 
Descolonizar el saber final boaventura cópia
Descolonizar el saber final   boaventura cópiaDescolonizar el saber final   boaventura cópia
Descolonizar el saber final boaventura cópia
 
Almenara 11 - 2019
Almenara   11 - 2019Almenara   11 - 2019
Almenara 11 - 2019
 
Almenara 11 - 2019
Almenara   11 - 2019Almenara   11 - 2019
Almenara 11 - 2019
 
Apuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSR
Apuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSRApuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSR
Apuntes sobre la historia de la corrupcion_IAFJSR
 
Boletin del Area de Derecho Publico. No. 02
Boletin del Area de Derecho Publico. No. 02Boletin del Area de Derecho Publico. No. 02
Boletin del Area de Derecho Publico. No. 02
 
Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...
Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...
Jellinek, Georg. - La Declaración de los Derechos del Hombre y del-Ciudadano ...
 
La-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdf
La-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdfLa-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdf
La-historia-militar-hoy-Investigaciones-y-tendencias.pdf
 
Humanidades
HumanidadesHumanidades
Humanidades
 
Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...
Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...
Otra autonomia de la Ciencia. Reflexiones a la luz del pensamiento de Serguei...
 

Más de Marizay2

Filiación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptx
Filiación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptxFiliación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptx
Filiación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptxMarizay2
 
Los_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdf
Los_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdfLos_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdf
Los_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdfMarizay2
 
ORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdf
ORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdfORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdf
ORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdfMarizay2
 
MANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdf
MANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdfMANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdf
MANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdfMarizay2
 
MANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdf
MANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdfMANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdf
MANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdfMarizay2
 
El_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdf
El_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdfEl_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdf
El_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdfMarizay2
 

Más de Marizay2 (6)

Filiación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptx
Filiación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptxFiliación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptx
Filiación ,concepto ,clases , normativa al respecto, legislación vigente 1.pptx
 
Los_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdf
Los_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdfLos_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdf
Los_contratos_civiles_y_sus_generalidades____Trevino-.pdf
 
ORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdf
ORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdfORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdf
ORATORIA_FORENSE_Y_REDACCION_JURIDICA.pdf
 
MANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdf
MANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdfMANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdf
MANUAL_DE_CRIMINALISTICA_Y_CIENCIAS_FORENSES.pdf
 
MANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdf
MANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdfMANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdf
MANUAL-DEL-SISTEMA-DE-CADENA-DE-CUSTODIA.pdf
 
El_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdf
El_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdfEl_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdf
El_abogado_del_manana libro de ciencias políticas y JURÍDICOS.pdf
 

Último

Conflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacio
Conflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacioConflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacio
Conflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacioEdwinRubio14
 
M15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICO
M15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICOM15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICO
M15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICOMarianaCuevas22
 
Libro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdf
Libro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdfLibro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdf
Libro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdfEdgar Jaimes Cruz
 
Esquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptx
Esquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptxEsquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptx
Esquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptxcarmen579579
 
Dictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordia
Dictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordiaDictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordia
Dictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordia20minutos
 
Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...
Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...
Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...OmarFernndez26
 
articulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptx
articulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptxarticulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptx
articulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptxCanelitaI
 
RÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RG
RÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RGRÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RG
RÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RGAndreeAngelSalcedoLu
 
EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...
EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...
EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...Corporación Hiram Servicios Legales
 
LGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantiles
LGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantilesLGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantiles
LGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantilesmoraledulxe
 
Impedimentos y Recusación Procesal Civil
Impedimentos y Recusación Procesal CivilImpedimentos y Recusación Procesal Civil
Impedimentos y Recusación Procesal CivilAidaTejada5
 
sistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actual
sistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actualsistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actual
sistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actualJose Navarro
 
Ensayo Critico sobre Garantismo Funcional
Ensayo Critico sobre Garantismo FuncionalEnsayo Critico sobre Garantismo Funcional
Ensayo Critico sobre Garantismo FuncionalPoder Judicial
 
linea de tiempo .evolución histórica de los derechos humanos
linea de tiempo  .evolución histórica de los derechos humanoslinea de tiempo  .evolución histórica de los derechos humanos
linea de tiempo .evolución histórica de los derechos humanosmarcovalor2005
 
ESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptx
ESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptxESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptx
ESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptxVictoriaCanales6
 
EL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptx
EL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptxEL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptx
EL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptxanamlazaro25
 
Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...
Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...
Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...OscarArgueta22
 
Derecho Laboral General y Otras Disposiciones
Derecho Laboral General y Otras DisposicionesDerecho Laboral General y Otras Disposiciones
Derecho Laboral General y Otras DisposicionesDiegoMorales287268
 

Último (18)

Conflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacio
Conflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacioConflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacio
Conflicto de leyes en el tiempo y en el espacio
 
M15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICO
M15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICOM15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICO
M15_U1_S1_UNADM_DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PUBLICO
 
Libro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdf
Libro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdfLibro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdf
Libro el miedo a la libertad_ El Miedo A La Libertad.pdf
 
Esquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptx
Esquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptxEsquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptx
Esquema proceso contencioso administrativo - copia - copia.pptx
 
Dictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordia
Dictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordiaDictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordia
Dictamen de la ONU sobre las leyes de concordia
 
Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...
Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...
Act_3.2_FernandezIzquerrdo_MartinezMillet_RodriguezCarmona_InvestigacionenRec...
 
articulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptx
articulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptxarticulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptx
articulo 87 Ley General de Sociedades Ley N° 26887.pptx
 
RÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RG
RÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RGRÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RG
RÉGIMENES TRIBUTARIOS EN EL PERU -RUS, RER, RG
 
EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...
EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...
EL INTERÉS LEGÍTIMO DE LA REVISIÓN DE LOS ACTOS ADMINISTRATIVOS CONTRARIOS A ...
 
LGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantiles
LGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantilesLGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantiles
LGSM.pdf ley general sociedades mercantiles
 
Impedimentos y Recusación Procesal Civil
Impedimentos y Recusación Procesal CivilImpedimentos y Recusación Procesal Civil
Impedimentos y Recusación Procesal Civil
 
sistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actual
sistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actualsistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actual
sistema tributario boliviano en el contexto actual
 
Ensayo Critico sobre Garantismo Funcional
Ensayo Critico sobre Garantismo FuncionalEnsayo Critico sobre Garantismo Funcional
Ensayo Critico sobre Garantismo Funcional
 
linea de tiempo .evolución histórica de los derechos humanos
linea de tiempo  .evolución histórica de los derechos humanoslinea de tiempo  .evolución histórica de los derechos humanos
linea de tiempo .evolución histórica de los derechos humanos
 
ESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptx
ESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptxESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptx
ESQUEMAS IAD introduccion al analisi del derecho.pptx
 
EL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptx
EL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptxEL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptx
EL PROCEDIMIENTO REGISTRAL EN EL PERU.pptx
 
Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...
Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...
Ejercicio abusivo del derecho a la libertad de expresion de los medios de com...
 
Derecho Laboral General y Otras Disposiciones
Derecho Laboral General y Otras DisposicionesDerecho Laboral General y Otras Disposiciones
Derecho Laboral General y Otras Disposiciones
 

El_derecho_internacional_publico_en_la_obra_de_Manuel_Becerra_Ramirez.pdf

  • 1.
  • 2. EL DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PÚBLICO EN LA OBRA DE MANUEL BECERRA RAMÍREZ
  • 3. INSTITUTO DE INVESTIGACIONES JURÍDICAS Serie Doctrina Jurídica, núm. 1012 DIRECTORIO Dra. Mónica González Contró Directora Dr. Mauricio Padrón Innamorato Secretario Académico Mtra. Wendy Vanesa Rocha Cacho Jefa del Departamento de Publicaciones Créditos editoriales Wendy Vanesa Rocha Cacho Coordinación editorial Roberto Zavaleta Cornejo Cuidado de la edición Oscar Martínez González Formación en computadora Edith Aguilar Gálvez Diseño y elaboración de portada
  • 4. EL DERECHO INTERNACIONAL PÚBLICO EN LA OBRA DE MANUEL BECERRA RAMÍREZ UNIVERSIDAD NACIONAL AUTÓNOMA DE MÉXICO INSTITUTO DE INVESTIGACIONES JURÍDICAS México, 2024 Nuria González Martín Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández Ingrid Berlanga Vasile Mónica Elizabeth Nuño Nuño Coordinadores
  • 5. Primera edición: 2 de febrero de 2024 DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas Circuito Mario de la Cueva s/n Ciudad Universitaria, Coyoacán, 04510 Ciudad de México ISBN (libro electrónico): 978-607-30-8689-9 Hecho en México Esta edición y sus características son propiedad de la Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México. Prohibida la reproducción total o parcial por cualquier medio sin la autorización escrita del titular de los derechos patrimoniales. Catalogación en la publicación UNAM. Dirección General de Bibliotecas y Servicios Digitales de Información Nombres: González Martín, Nuria, editor. | Benavides Hernández, Luis Ángel, editor. | Berlanga Vasile, Ingrid, editor. | Nuño Nuño, Mónica Elizabeth, editor. Título: El derecho internacional público en la obra de Manuel Becerra Ramírez / Nuria González Martín, Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández, Ingrid Berlanga Vasile, Mónica Eli- zabeth Nuño Nuño, coordinadores. Descripción: Primera edición. | México : Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas, 2024. | Serie: Serie Doctrina jurídica ; núm. 1012. Identificadores: LIBRUNAM 2226943 (libro electrónico) | ISBN 9786073086899 (li- bro electrónico). Temas: Derecho internacional. | Derechos humanos -- Siglo XXI. | Propiedad intelec- tual -- Aspectos económicos. | Guerra de Ucrania, 2022- . | Rusia -- Aspectos políticos. | Becerra Ramírez, Manuel. Clasificación: LCC KZ3410 (libro electrónico) | DDC 341.01—dc23
  • 6. V CONTENIDO Presentación . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . IX Nuria González Martín Mónica Elizabeth Nuño Nuño Ingrid Berlanga Vasile Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández Primera parte DERECHO Y RELACIONES INTERNACIONALES Quo Vadis, Humanity? Reflections on Contemporary Geopolitical and Societal Transformations. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 Rein Müllerson The Provision of Arms to the Victim of Armed Aggression: The Case of Ukraine. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Stefan Talmon Common Heritage or Private Property? Power, Strategy, and Law-Ma- king for the Deep Seabed and Outer Space. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49 Michael Byers Las transformaciones económicas, políticas y jurídicas en la URSS. Su incidencia en la guerra de Ucrania. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79 Virdzhiniya Petrova Georgieva Las guerras híbridas: nuevas formas de agresión, injerencismo e inter- vencionismo. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99 Luis Lorenzo Córdova Arellano
  • 7. VI CONTENIDO Segunda parte DERECHO DE LOS TRATADOS Obligación de no frustrar el objeto y el fin de un tratado antes de su entrada en vigor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119 Ricardo Abello-Galvis Reflexiones sobre los tratados internacionales de derechos humanos. . 131 Sergio García Ramírez The Holy See and the Treaties of Westphalia. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 175 Maurizio Ragazzi Tercera parte PROPIEDAD INTELECTUAL Secretos industriales, un cambio de paradigma. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195 Mauricio Jaliffe Daher Los sistemas de inteligencia artificial como inventores: consideraciones para un debate a partir de fallos judiciales. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207 Jorge Luis Ordelin Font Blue Economy: The Future of Intellectual Property?. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223 Pablo Ferrera Cuarta parte ENSEÑANZA DEL DERECHO INTERNACIONAL JURÍDICO Las grandes transformaciones del derecho internacional en un enfo- que de las ciencias políticas y sociales. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 249 Juan Carlos Velázquez Elizarrarás
  • 8. VII CONTENIDO Las creaciones intelectuales como bienes comunes. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 Rafael Pérez Miranda El derecho internacional en el panorama de la producción jurídica. . . 289 Ramiro Contreras Acevedo María Amelia Solórzano Peña Notas amistosas. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 317 Acerca de Manuel Becerra Ramírez y su obra. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 387
  • 9. IX PRESENTACIÓN La presente obra tiene por objeto hacer una revisión en torno al pensamien- to jurídico del doctor Manuel Becerra Ramírez, destacado internacionalista mexicano. Es indudable que México ha contado con destacados internacionalistas cuyos nombres, por ser conocidos, no es necesario repetir. Sin embargo, el doctor Becerra pertenece a un grupo muy particular de internacionalistas, a aquel alejado de la fama y los grandes círculos políticos y diplomáticos, pero forjado en la academia y en el rigor jurídico, aquél en el que los aplausos no provienen de los puestos que haya ocupado, sino del reconocimiento y admi- ración de sus pares, alumnas, alumnos y amigos, un quehacer caracterizado por el apoyo incondicional que siempre profesa. Desde el inicio de su carrera Manuel Becerra ha sido una especie de outsider. Su formación internacionalista no la hizo en alguno de los grandes centros educativos occidentales. En una época en donde el mundo aún era bipolar, Manuel Becerra decidió estudiar en la Unión Soviética, en la Uni- versidad Lomonosov, con el gran profesor internacionalista Grigory Tun- kin, esto es, decidió estudiar desde otro lente, lejos de la retórica predomi- nante, este hecho marcaría profundamente su pensamiento jurídico, siempre tratando de ver las dos caras de la moneda, siendo equilibrado y mesurado. Sin lugar a duda, su incorporación al Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídi- cas de la UNAM fue otro paso trascendente en su desarrollo profesional, ello le permitió combinar dos de sus grandes pasiones, a saber, la investigación y la docencia. Lo anterior hizo que innumerables estudiantes pudieran cono- cerle. Destaca allí su labor durante los llamados “veranos de la investigación científica” que permiten a jóvenes universitarios colaborar con un investiga- dor y fomentar el amor por la ciencia. En este sentido, es importante señalar que uno de los reconocimientos a su enorme calidad académica es el hecho de haber sido nombrado inves- tigador nacional emérito por el Sistema Nacional de Investigadores como prueba de la escuela forjada. Asimismo, no se podría dejar de mencionar la labor realizada por el doc- tor Becerra a través del Anuario Mexicano de Derecho Internacional, el cual fundó y dirige desde hace más de veinte años. Desde su concepción, el Anuario fue Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 10. X PRESENTACIÓN pensado como un espacio para dar voz no sólo a los internacionalistas en México, sino también de América Latina y de otras regiones del mundo. El Anuario Mexicano ha servido de inspiración a otras publicaciones en la región y hoy en día es un referente en todo el continente. En muchas ocasiones las personas contamos con alguien que marca nuestras vidas, casi siempre son los padres, pero también, de manera fre- cuente, lo son los profesores; para aquellos que hemos tenido la dicha de co- nocer a Manuel Becerra Ramírez podemos decir, sin temor a equivocarnos, que él ha marcado las nuestras. El rigor académico junto con la simpatía y sencillez de su persona hace de él un ser humano extraordinario. La presente obra, que se ha concretado con el invaluable apoyo de Emi- liano Márquez en la fase final de su compilación, se encuentra dividida en dos partes. La primera es una compilación en torno a las grandes áreas de estudio de Manuel Becerra tales como derecho de los tratados, propiedad in- telectual, derecho internacional en periodos de transformaciones históricas como la caída del muro de Berlín y de la Unión Soviética, derecho y relacio- nes internacionales desde América Latina, fuentes del derecho internacional, entre otros. La diversidad de autores y temas que participan son muestra de la pluralidad del pensamiento tan característico en Manuel Becerra. La segunda parte está constituida por las contribuciones de muchas de las personas a quienes Manuel Becerra ha impactado en su vida, se trata de notas muy personales, que entrañan recuerdos y agradecimientos, algo de lo mucho que nos ha brindado. Dada la diversidad temática de los artículos que constituyen la primera parte del libro es importante proporcionar al lector una visión general de los mismos con la finalidad de invitarlo a su lectura. Así, Rein Müllerson hace una serie de análisis sobre la geopolítica contem- poránea y su impacto en las transformaciones de las sociedades. Es, a la vez, una revisión personal a partir de los últimos años de la URSS a la época actual. Por su parte, Luis Córdova aborda, desde una perspectiva holística, los nuevos tipos de conflictos internacionales, los llamados conflictos híbridos, en donde no necesariamente se utilizan armas convencionales, sino que los teatros de operaciones pueden ser el ciberespacio o el derecho. En otro tema, Michael Byers compara los esfuerzos de elaboración de reglas internacionales sobre la minería de los fondos marinos y la minería espacial. Particularmente se centra en las diferentes estrategias desplegadas por Estados Unidos, y cómo el G-77 a veces es capaz de resistirlas, o al me- nos modificar los resultados. En el artículo de Sergio García Ramírez se hace una reflexión profun- da sobre la naturaleza de los tratados en materia de derechos humanos, así Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 11. XI PRESENTACIÓN como el diálogo jurisdiccional y control de convencionalidad desarrollados en tiempos recientes. Sin esos factores no se podría entender el derecho in- ternacional contemporáneo de los derechos humanos. En la misma temática de tratados se encuentra el artículo de Ricardo Abello quien, desde una óptica colombiana, aborda con ejemplos regionales muy interesantes la obligación de no frustrar el objeto y el fin de un tratado antes de su entrada en vigor. En materia de propiedad intelectual, Pablo Ferrara hace un análisis de la llamada “economía azul” la cual se refiere a aquellas actividades orientadas a lograr el crecimiento y el desarrollo económicos basados en las actividades oceánicas, al mismo tiempo que considera los resultados sociales y ambien- tales de estas actividades. Siguiendo la misma temática, Rafael Pérez Miranda realiza un análisis conceptual comparativo sobre los conocimientos intelectuales o intangibles y las obras artísticas como bienes comunes sobre los cuales aún no hay un con- cepto universalmente aceptado. Señala que en la doctrina y el derecho se ha excluido de la protección a productores de conocimientos científicos básicos y hace énfasis en la importancia de retribuir y reconocer adecuadamente los derechos de científicos y artistas. De igual forma, el artículo de Jorge Luis Ordelín Font tiene como obje- tivo analizar algunos retos de los derechos de propiedad intelectual ante la capacidad creativa de los sistemas de inteligencia artificial (IA) a partir de los argumentos expuestos por los jueces de Australia y Reino Unido en tres resoluciones judiciales. El autor expone las cuestiones fundamentales rela- cionadas con el caso Device for the Autonomous Bootstrapping of Unified Sentience (DABUS) y analiza los principales argumentos a favor y en contra del reco- nocimiento de DABUS como inventor. Continuando en esa área, Mauricio Jaliffe Daher aborda la represión de la competencia desleal mediante los llamados “secretos industriales”, sien- do la figura que a nivel internacional ofrece mayor protección a los activos de las empresas, en particular a las que manejan tecnologías muy avanzadas. Destaca la necesidad de revertir la incongruencia de origen en la formación y valoración empresarial en la aportación de información constitutiva de secre- tos industriales así como la importancia de contar con un marco legal efectivo en México para proteger a startups de competidores. En un análisis histórico de las relaciones internacionales Maurizio Ra- gazzi hace un recuento del impacto de los tratados de Westphalia en las re- laciones internacionales, especialmente del papel que jugó la santa sede en el contexto diplomático del siglo XVII y de los tres papas, siendo particular- mente el de Urbano VIII. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 12. XII PRESENTACIÓN A su vez, Ramiro Contreras Acevedo y María Amelia Solórzano Peña hacen un análisis del desarrollo de la producción científica en materia de de- recho internacional desde finales del siglo XX hasta la actualidad, llevando a cabo un ejercicio de mapeo, eligiendo bases de datos bibliográficas sobre derecho internacional de acceso abierto en español, destacando el Anuario Mexicano de Derecho Internacional por el número de artículos publicados. Por su parte, Juan Carlos Velázquez Elizarrarás realiza un análisis so- bre la enseñanza-aprendizaje del derecho internacional en el contexto de las ciencias políticas y sociales, concibiendo al derecho internacional como un contribuyente ordenador y eje de conocimiento insustituible de las relaciones internacionales, que a la vez está condicionado a una constante adecuación y transformación del derecho internacional e incluso a una ampliación y di- versificación tanto temática como de investigación. El artículo de Stephan Talmon analiza, en el contexto de la guerra entre Rusia y Ucrania, si la norma de neutralidad de no proveer de armamento a una de las partes en un conflicto puede admitir una excepción, esta excep- ción se argumenta bajo distintos supuestos, por ejemplo, invocando el artícu- lo 51 de la Carta de la ONU debido a que una de las partes del conflicto es miembro del Consejo de Seguridad y utiliza el veto para obstruir la decisión de dicho Consejo o cuando el conflicto inicia por una agresión. La autora Virdzhiniya Petrova Georgieva retoma una serie de entrevistas realizadas por el doctor Manuel Becerra a selectos académicos y estudiosos de la URSS en noviembre de 1991. Las preguntas, que versaban sobre las transformaciones ocurridas en la URSS después del final de la Guerra Fría y desde las disciplinas de la economía internacional, la política internacio- nal y el derecho internacional, son retomados por la autora como punto de partida para tomar sus principales hallazgos y paralelismo en su origen para hacer un análisis que incide en la guerra de Ucrania. La presente obra nace de la gran admiración de parte de alumnos, cole- gas y amigos, así como del reconocimiento por la enorme labor formadora, en todos los sentidos de la palabra, que en muchos de nosotros ha tenido Manuel Becerra. Don Manuel ha sido más que un profesor, ha fungido como un verdadero mentor y en más de una ocasión ha actuado con un verdadero sentido paternal. Nuria González Martín Mónica Elizabeth Nuño Nuño Ingrid Berlanga Vasile Luis Ángel Benavides Hernández Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 13. Primera parte DERECHO Y RELACIONES INTERNACIONALES Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 14. 3 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY GEOPOLITICAL AND SOCIETAL TRANSFORMATIONS Rein Müllerson* Summary: I. Introduction. II. On Current Geopolitical Configurations. III. Liberalism versus Democracy. IV. On the Adaptability to Rapid Change. V. Populism as an Inadequate Response to the Conflict Between the Elites and the Masses. VI. “Illiberal Democracy”, “Undemocratic Liberalism” and “Liberal Imperialism”. VII. Is “e pluribus unum” indeed Replacing “ex uno plures”? VIII. Bibliography. I. Introduction It was almost forty years ago when, as a young academic at Moscow Universi- ty, I met an even younger scholar from Mexico —Manuel Becerra Ramirez—. He had just become a Ph.D. student of the most famous soviet specialist on international law —professor Grigory Ivanovitch Tunkin—. I know from my personal experience how difficult is the russian language for those for whom it is not a native tongue. However, I had mastered the language of Pushkin well before I started my legal studies. Therefore, for Manuel, it was all even more difficult. However, due to his intelligence and hard work, he not only became fluent in russian but also excelled as an international lawyer, successfully de- fending his Ph.D. thesis. Since then, I have followed his progress by reading his works and even contributing to the excellent Mexican Yearbook of International Law, so ably edited already for years by professor Becerra. Several years ago, it was my great pleasure to meet him personally in UNAM and see with my own eyes the high respect bestowed to Manuel Becerra Ramirez by his colleagues as well as students. I am extremely happy to contribute my following reflec- tions, that are not only and even not so much on international law as on the * Ph. D., l’Institut de Droit International (IDI), Geneva, Switzerland, Member and for- mer President; Tallinn University Professor Emeritus. Estonia. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 15. 4 REIN MÜLLERSON causes that prevent the law prevail over politics, as we expected when we were young, to the book that celebrates high achievements of my mexican friend. II. On Current Geopolitical Configurations Since the end of the 1980s the world is passing through two interrelated re- volutionary processes, one of which is global, affecting all the nations in the world, the other being specific, though not limited, to western nations. Or ma- ybe it would be better to say that if decades ago it plagued mainly non-western countries, today it has become mostly a western phenomenon. Revolutionary processes, by definition, put pressure on all kinds of normative systems, inclu- ding law and morality, since, as being normative phenomena, they function well in circumstances that could be called normal. In revolutionary periods in any society —be it, say, in France at the end of the Eighteenth century, or in Rus- sia at the beginning of the Twentieth, when normalcy was an exception and expediency ruled, law broke down, and even morality often lost its guiding force—. In that respect, the international society is not an exception. The first revolutionary change is geopolitical. Starting from about the end of the 1980s, the world entered into a period of radical geopolitical re- configuration, whose results cannot be predicted with any certainty even to- day. This process started with the collapse of the rather stable bipolar system, going then through a unipolar moment of the long 1990s, and has today a tendency of moving with jolts and jerks towards some kind of multipolarity. While the West, led by Washington, tries to perpetuate its absolute domi- nance acquired after the collapse of its erstwhile rival (the USSR), those be- longing to the rest, led by China, Russia, India, Mexico, and other nations, use different means to put an end to western hegemony. The war in Ukraine epitomises the relentlessness of this geopolitical transformation of the world, unfortunate victims of which are mostly people in Ukraine. In this country, the collective west, notwithstanding Russia’s illegal use of military force aga- inst its neighbour that was provoked by the movement of NATO to the fron- tiers of Russia, is using Ukrainian territory and ukrainian people to bring down Russia as one of the nations that has openly disobeyed the american hegemony. Until the “revolutionary dust” settles down, one way or other, and new “normalcy” emerges (or the old returns, though less plausible scena- rio), it is difficult to expect that international law could function “normally”. The second revolutionary transformation, not unrelated to the first, is the crisis of liberal democracy that was meant, and for a while even seemed, to triumph when the failure of its main ideological rival at the end of the Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 16. 5 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... 1980s had become obvious. After the collapse of the Soviet Union and the bipolar world, it seemed to many that it was exactly liberal democracy that had prevailed, and it would continue to flourish until the whole world would become the same. However, the disappearance of the main enemy, combined with a wave of globalisation, started revealing, though not imme- diately, internal contradictions of liberal democracy. Modern democracy, originating in western european societies, has had dialectical relationships (i.e. situations, where different phenomena, depen- ding on concrete circumstances, have a kind of friend/enemy relations- hips) with three other phenomena that have, on the one hand, supported democracy’s emergence and growth while also putting limits on its expansion and deepening. These three phenomena are nationalism, capitalism, and li- beralism. As in the post-WWII, the last two have been considered almost in- separable (i.e. individual liberties and market freedoms have been often seen as two sides of the same coin), the controversial (i.e. dialectical) relationship of democracy with capitalism and liberalism can be dealt with as one dialec- tical controversy, notwithstanding that there have been societies and periods where and when free market has coexisted (or still coexists) with conservative, even authoritarian and anti-liberal, social policies. In this article, I will not dwell at length on an important and controversial issue of the relationship between democracy and nationalism since I have dealt with it elsewhere, in detail particularly in one of my recent articles.1 The process of globalisation has revealed and made acute the contradiction between democracy and nationalism, whose ideal had become enshrined in the concept of the nation-state and where modern democracy emerged and evolved (the nation-state and democracy as a kind of twin brothers though not always in best terms). Without nationalism there wouldn’t have been na- tion-states, without nation-states there would not have been democracy, at least in its current form. Therefore, I conclude in the aforementioned article that without and beyond nation-states (even if they are multi-ethnic) the- re could hardly exist democracy, though nationalism may also undermine democracy, especially in multi-ethnic or multi-confessional societies. Besides the revolutionary situation in international relations, where the existing ba- lance of powers was broken and competing visions of future —a unipolarity with one centre of power and refashioned multipolarity with different centres of power— are competing, there is also a revolutionary situation in countries that have been most stable and have served as examples for others. This is the crisis of liberal democracy that is also related to, and even conditioned by, 1 Müllerson, R., “The Nation-State: Not Yet Ready for the Dustbin of History?”, The Chinese Journal of International Law, vol. 20, núm. 4, 2021, pp. 699-725. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 17. 6 REIN MÜLLERSON processes of globalisation. Below, therefore, I will concentrate on this contro- versial, i.e. dialectical, relationship between democracy and liberalism. III. Liberalism versus Democracy At the beginning of the twenty-first century, the positive aspects of the rela- tionship between democracy and liberalism, which for decades had prevailed in the post-Second World War west, have become overwhelmed by negative features. Democracy and liberalism, which had rather peacefully and with mu- tual benefits coexisted for many decades, are now undermining each other’s potentials. The main reason for such a turnaround lies in the negative aspects or consequences of the processes of globalisation, which the french call la mondialisation malheureuse in contradistinction to that of heureuse.2 As Harvard economist Dani Rodrik has argued, there is a fundamental incompatibility between hyper-globalization, on the one hand, and democracy and national sovereignty, on the other.3 You cannot have all of them at the same time. The spread of market economy and democracy —the concepts that are considered by many to be as obvious goods as God, motherhood and apple- pie— have in practice turned out to be a mixed blessing. If the planned economy of the soviet type left everybody, and society as a whole, poor and market freedoms may indeed be one of the preconditions for political free- doms and personal liberties —the shock introduction of markets, especia- lly unbridled markets, make a few extremely rich while many become even poorer than they were under the previous system—. As one of the central tenets of democracy (with some important qualifications of course) is that the voice, interests or values of the many count more than those of the few, it should be clear that economic “shock therapy” and political democracy are incompatible and one either has a shock or democracy, not both. Cambridge economist Ha-Joon Chang goes even further writing that “free market and democracy are not natural partners”,4 though it must be emphasised that professor Chang is speaking rather of “unbridled markets”, as advocated by Milton Friedman or Alissa Zinovievna Rosenbaum (alias Ayn Rand) and their followers. 2 See, e.g., Guénolé, Thomas, La Mondialisation Malheureuse: Inégalité-pillage-oligarchie, First, 2016. 3 Rodrik, D., “The Inescapable Trilemma of the World Economy”, June, 27 2007, avai- lable at: https://rodrik.typepad.com/dani_rodriks_weblog/2007/06/the-inescapable.html. 4 Chang, H. J., Bad Samaritans. Rich Nations, Poor Policies & the Threat to the Developing World, Random House Business Books, 2007, p. 18. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 18. 7 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... However, already more than half a century ago one of the most persistent market-friendly advocates of political freedoms, Karl Popper, incisively wrote: Even if the state protects its citizens from being bullied by physical violence (as it does in principle, under the system of unrestrained capitalism), it may defeat our ends by its failure to protect them from the misuse of economic power. In such a state, the economically strong is still free to bully one who is economi- cally weak, and to rob of his freedom. Under these circumstances, unlimited economic freedom can be just as self-defeating as unlimited physical freedom, and economic power may be nearly as dangerous as physical violence.5 Free market (capitalism) and liberal democracy, phenomena that, on the one hand, presume each other, are at the same time also in constant rivalry. The freer is a market, the greater is the economic inequality; the greater in- equality, the less would there be democracy, and vice versa. Strong democracy attained by curbing inequality almost inevitably also bridles market freedoms. Economic inequality de facto and inevitably also increases political inequality, while political equality puts breaks on the widening economic inequality. De- mocracy tries to make a society more equal, while unbridled market increa- ses inequality. The result of such constant balancing has been that in Wes- tern European liberal democratic societies these two spheres —political and economic— while supporting each other have also constantly tempered each other, softened each other’s excesses. However, this balance has not withstood the impact of the latest wave of globalisation. John Dunn has observed that within the liberal democratic movement “the partisans of the order of egoism”, i.e. capitalists, have defea- ted “the partisans of equality”,6 i.e. democrats. One of the important causes of equality’s defeat in the hands of economic egoism has been that, in the long run, the uncompromising instruments for attempting to realize equality and the rigidities inherent in its pursuit have blunted equality’s appeal as a goal.7 Both the french and especially the russian revolutions, where contrary to the american revolution, the aim was not, as Hannah Arendt wrote, the “freedom from oppression” but “freedom from want”, and one of the main requirements, therefore was egalité (equality), have contributed to such a mis- balance within today’s liberal-democracy. Hannah Arendt observes that the inescapable fact was that liberation from tyranny spelled freedom only for 5 Popper, K., The Open Society and Its Enemies, Routledge, 1996, vol. 2 “Hegel & Marx”, p. 124. 6 Dunn, J., Setting the People Free. The Story of Democracy, Atlantic Books, 2005, p. 134. 7 Ibidem, p. 129. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 19. 8 REIN MÜLLERSON a few and was hardly felt by the many who remained loaded down by their misery. These had to be liberated once more and compared to this liberation from the yoke of necessity, the original liberation from tyranny must have looked like child’s play.8 Excesses of radical attempts to get rid of the “yoke of necessity”, be it as a result of the french or the russian or the cuban revo- lutions, have always led to radical suppression of individual liberties. These facts, in turn, have been used by proponents of liberalism or neoliberalism to suppress calls for more equality and also more democracy, while equality has often been defined only as an equality of opportunity —you have the right but cannot. The process of globalisation has revealed and made acute not only the contradiction between democracy and nationalism, whose ideal had become enshrined in the concept of the nation-state and where modern democracy emerged and evolved, but also between democracy and liberalism —both economic and social—. Moreover, there is a bundle of interlinks that can- not be unravelled without irreparably damaging at least some, if not all, of them. Contemporary democracy, i.e. the government by the people and for the people, emerged and evolved within nation-states and seems inseparable from it. Yet, economic liberalism with global uncontrolled world financial markets, together with social liberalism, putting the primacy of the indivi- dual with her interests and desires above the interests of society, are destro- ying social bonds that have helped hold societies together, and are, as a result, also undermining nation-states —the cradles of democracy. As it often happens, rare early warnings usually remain unheard. It was more than twenty years ago when Richard Rorty published a small book, Achieving our Country, where he wrote that the american liberal left, concentra- ting on the rights of ethnic, racial, religious, cultural, and sexual minorities, had neglected the widening gap between the rich and the poor. At some point, Rorty warned ...something will crack. The nonsuburban electorate will decide that the sys- tem has failed and start looking around for a strongman to vote for someone willing to assure them that, once he is elected, the smug bureaucrats, tricky lawyers, overpaid bond salesmen, and postmodern professors will no longer be calling the shots.9 Sounds eerily familiar and up to date, doesn’t it? Rorty considered him- self to belong to the category of liberal left, though as one of the brightest 8 Arendt, H., On Revolution, Penguin Books, 1965, p. 74. 9 Rorty, R., Achieving Our Country, Harvard, Harvard University Press, 1997, p. 90. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 20. 9 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... representatives of american pragmatism, he hardly be branded as a post- modern professor. And differently from many, if not from most, he did not ridicule, deplore or detest those who were different, but tried to understand them, which doesn’t necessarily mean to justify.10 IV. On the Adaptability to Rapid Change The recent wave of globalisation has also exponentially increased the rapidity of alterations in technology, economy, politics and in ways of life generally. This speed of changes is exacerbating the rift between the elites and the mas- ses since they have different adaptabilities to multiple challenges coming all together as a row of roaring cars too long been held stationary by the red light. French philosopher Barbara Stiegler, in her excellent study with a emblematic title Il faut s’adapter (It is Necessary to Adapt),11 has shown how, at the beginning of the twentieth century, two prominent american philosophers Walter Lipp- mann and John Dewey had offered different answers to the question of the adaptability to the rapid societal change caused by the industrial revolution that has significant parallels with the current revolutionary period. She writes about the 1920s: For the first time in the evolution of life and living beings, one species —our human species— finds itself in the situation, where it is not adapted to the new environment. For Lippmann, it was the situation where there was a huge gap between the natural inclination of the human species to remain as they are, inherited from the long and slow history of biological and societal evolution, and the demands of the rapid adaptability to the new environment, brutally imposed by the industrial revolution. Hence, the central theme of Lippmann’s political studies: how to adapt human species to constantly and rapidly chan- ging environment… The fundamental question for Lippmann was how to avoid that this tension between the change and stasis, openness and closing, do not lead the masses to choose nationalism, fascism and generally all forms of isolationisms, in their effort to oppose to the rapid change, to restore the stasis and isolation.12 So, it was this abyss between slow historical and biological evolution of human species and the rapidly changing physical and social environment, caused by the industrial revolution, that worried Walter Lippmann. If at the 10 In my opinion, Baruch Spinoza’s “non ridere, non lugere, neque detestere, sed intelligere” (don’t ri- dicule, don’t deplore, don’t detest, but try to understand) is the best approach in social sciences. 11 Stiegler, B., Il faut s’adapter: sur un nouvel impératif politique, Paris, Gallimard, 2019. 12 Ibidem, p. 14. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 21. 10 REIN MÜLLERSON turn of the twentieth century it was the industrial revolution, also combi- ned with economic globalisation, at the turn of the twenty first century it is the revolution in information technology and whipped up hyper-globalisa- tion of economic, and particularly, financial markets that have, once again, uprooted masses of people in different countries, where only those who are adaptable to the change can survive. This is a bio-social experiment of the survival of the fittest and the fittest are the rationally thinking experts and managers and impartial judges using rational laws, who know in which di- rection the humankind must and will evolve. The masses should be taught to suppress their irrational impulses and follow the lead of enlightened experts, who have been able to adapt and readapt to the constantly changing environ- ment. One of the main aims of public education should be “the manufacture of the consent” of the masses with the policies manufactured by the experts. As to the role of politicians, Lippmann writes that, “though he (the states- man) cannot himself keep the life of the nation as a whole in his mind, he can at least make sure that he is taking counsel from those who know”.13 A politician has to be only an expert in the choice of experts.While Lippmann, and all the neoliberals after him, saw the solution to the gap between rapidly changing environment and the inability of the masses to adapt to the new environment, in the combination of expertise of specialists and the applica- tion of rational laws, Dewey would rely more on the collective intelligence of masses. Dewey was also the first detractor of neoliberal thinking. He wrote: A class of experts is inevitably cut off from the common interests to such an extent that it becomes a class with its own private interests. Every governance by experts where masses are unable to inform the experts of their needs can- not be anything else than an oligarchy that rules in the interest of some. And enlightened information has to force the specialists to take account of the ne- eds of masses. The world has suffered more from leaders and authorities than from masses.14 We see that this almost a century old intellectual confrontation that had influenced policies of western governments for decades, has acquired today a new acuteness. It is a conflict between elites and masses, between self-pro- claimed progressives and those who are denigrated as populists. We see also that due to the spread of the Internet and social media governments, be they democratic or autocratic, are losing their ability to “manufacture of the con- 13 Lippmann, W., A Preface to Politics, New York-London, Mitchell Kennerley, 1914, p. 98. 14 Dewey, J., The Public and Its Problems in The Later Works of John Dewey 1925-1953, Southern Illinois University Press, 1984, vol. 2, pp. 364 and 365. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 22. 11 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... sent” of the masses with policies of the elites. It should not be forgotten what Edward Bernays wrote in 1928: The conscious and intelligent manipulation of the organized habits and opi- nions of the masses is an important element in democratic society. Those who manipulate this unseen mechanism of society constitute an invisible govern- ment which is the true ruling power of our country... We are governed, our minds are molded, our tastes formed, our ideas suggested, largely by men we have never heard of. This is a logical result of the way in which our democra- tic society is organized. Vast numbers of human beings must cooperate in this manner if they are to live together as a smoothly functioning society... In almost every act of our daily lives, whether in the sphere of politics or business, in our social conduct or our ethical thinking, we are dominated by the relatively small number of persons... who understand the mental processes and social patterns of the masses. It is they who pull the wires which control the public mind.15 Although Bernays writes about manipulation of public consciousness in democracies, it goes without saying that autocracies do the same. The more advanced a country, the more sophisticated the manipulation, the more diffi- cult to feel like being manipulated. V. Populism as an Inadequate Response to the Conflict between the Elites and the Masses One of the most visible aspects or results of the aforementioned bundle of controversies is the phenomenon of so-called populism. Already in 2008, in my lectures at the Hague Academy of International Law, I spoke about the dialectical contradictions between nationalism, liberalism and democracy and the rise of populism.16 However, then these contradictions hadn’t yet reached their today’s acuteness, while populism was still a marginal phenomenon, not worthy of lengthy discussion. Those, who were accused of being populists where primarily leftist leaders of some third-world countries like Hugo Cha- vez of Venezuela or Rafael Correa of Ecuador. Today, populism has become more and more also a western phenome- non. French writer and journalist Alexandre Devecchio writes that notwiths- 15 Bernays, E. L., Propaganda, Routledge, 1928, pp. 9 and 10. Later this book was publis- hed in French with the title: Propaganda: comment manipuler l’opinion en démocratie (Zones, 2007), i.e. how to manipulate public opinion in democracy. 16 Müllerson, R., “Democracy Promotion: Institutions, International Law and Politics”, Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of International Law, vol. 333, 2008. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 23. 12 REIN MÜLLERSON tanding variances between populisms in different societies there is in them something important in common: “a desire to defend national sovereignty and identity against globalisation, to significantly limit immigration, certain hostility towards multiculturalism and support of programmes of social pro- tection that benefit only citizens of the country”.17 This is indeed what uni- tes politicians such as Donald Trump, Boris Johnson, Matteo Salvini, Victor Orban, Marine Le Pen and others. One more important thing in common between populisms is that differently from so-called (self-defined) progres- sists, who, like president Emmanuel Macron of France, are leaders of cos- mopolitan political, economic and intellectual elites, populists leaders find support mainly among those who are left behind or have suffered because of the processes of globalisation. The rise of populism, besides the negative effects of globalisation, has been boosted also by the revolution in information technology. Alexander Devecchio compares the effect of the spread of the Internet to that of the invention in 1454 of the printing press by Gutenberg. The latter undermi- ned the power and position of the Roman Church and the clergy, which had controlled the peoples’ minds, and had led to the emergence of the Protes- tantism, as well as religious wars. Devecchio asks: But if the invention of the web is going to provoke a similar fracture? This time not between catholics and protestants, but between traditional elites, who are in the process of losing their monopoly, which they have so far had over the mass media and the spread of information, and a new elite that can convey their po- pulist message through the non-traditional means of communication.18 Yascha Mounk observes that “the social media networks have closed the gap between the people and the elites, between those who have the power and those who don’t”.19 Traditional media has been considered, already for some time and with some justification, as the “fourth power” of the State, together with legis- lative, executive and judicial powers, though somewhat independent, but nevertheless in the service of the economic, political and intellectual elites, similar to the other three powers. For decades this separation of powers has been relative, all of them served interests and reflected the values of eco- nomic, political and intellectual elites. We have seen the real separation of 17 Devecchio, A., Recomposition: Le nouveau monde populiste, Les éditions du Serf, 2019, Loc. 724. 18 Ibidem, Loc. 1581. 19 Mounk, Y., The People vs. Democracy: Why our Freedom is in Danger and How to Save It, Har- vard University Press, 2018. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 24. 13 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... powers, for example, in the conflicts between president Donald Trump and the American Congress and between Boris Johnson and the British Parlia- ment on the issue of Brexit. The dialectical controversy between democracy and liberalism has been like a ticking bomb (une bombe à retardement) waiting for its time to explode. Though these two phenomena —liberalism and democracy— have often been supportive of each other, there has also been, as if by necessity, a cons- tant balancing necessary between them. Most western, especially western european societies have until recently managed this controversy relatively well. In some, democracy has had an upper hand (e.g., in scandinavian so- cial democracies), while in others liberalism has prevailed (e.g., in the United States), but there has not been an open conflict between these phenomena. However, already for decades, due, first, to the rapid globalisation of the world and later also to the changing balance of power in the internatio- nal system, this controversial friend/enemy relationship between democracy and liberalism has become less friendly and more inimical. It is reflected, inter alia, in the fact that liberal elites in most western countries have started labe- lling those democrats, whose policies and ideas (or/and personalities) they do not like, as populists (let us recall that Ralf Dahrendorf has noted that, “one man’s populism is another’s democracy, and vice versa”, though he has also qua- lified this statement by claiming that “while populism is simple, democracy is complicated”).20 At the same time, democrats (or populists) have started considering liberals to be arrogant elitists who have become alienated from the people, from their needs and ways of thinking, believing them to be losers and ill-informed (let’s recall Hillary Clinton’s characterisation, though later hypocritically retracted, of Donald Trump’s supporters as “racist, sexist, ho- mophobic deplorables”). British author David Goodhart distinguishes between those Europeans whom he calls Anywheres and those who according to him are Somewheres.21 If the members of the first category (no more than 20-25% of the population in the West and much less in the Rest) belong to the cosmopolitan elite that has profited from globalisation and feels at home in different places in the world, the majority (more than 50% in the West) feels a need to maintain so- lid links to their country, to its history, traditions and language. To the latter category belong, naturally, not only those who believe that globalisation has by-passed them. 20 Dahrendorf, R., “Acht Anmerkungen zum Populismus”, Transit-Europäische Revue, vol. 25, 2003, pp. 156-163. 21 Goodhart, D., The Road to Somewhere: The New Tribes Shaping British Politics, Penguin, 2017. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 25. 14 REIN MÜLLERSON Tensions between solidarity and diversity, between the welfare state and mass immigration have worsened, giving way to a growing divide between the “people from anywhere” and “people of somewhere” or as Alexander Devecchio puts it, between “sedentaries” and “nomads”.22 It is a conflict between those who care for their “rootedness” or entrenchment in a defini- tive place, be it a local village, a town or a nation-state and cosmopolitans, i.e., those who feel at home in different places. There have always been a minority those who see the whole world, or Europe as the case may be, as their home, and a majority of those who feel at home only there, where they were born and among those who speak the same language and profess the same religion. For centuries, the first category was a relatively small minority, while most of the people were born, lived and died in the same place, except for mass movements of population that have several times occurred in the history of humankind. In the globalised world these are not only authoritarian regimes that sup- press democratic impulses in their countries and may constitute a threat to democracy elsewhere. The spread and liberalisation of global, particularly financial, markets are curbing democracy everywhere. Increasing the overall GDP of many countries, unbridled liberal markets make a few extremely rich while the majority of people are left behind. The wealth gaps are increa- sing practically in all countries. If in autocracies people are powerless vis-à-vis their own rulers, in the globalised world people are powerless vis-à-vis global markets, even if they live in so-called liberal democracies, even if they belong to the so-called middle class. This is how economic liberalism is undermining democracy. At the same time, the rise in importance of individual rights and rights of a multitude of minorities, who aggressively promote their —often newly-found— identity, is undermining social cohesion and common values. This is how social liberalism undermines democracy. Societies that become “atomized”, to use the English title of Michel Houllebecq’s novel Les Particu- les élémentaires, become non-societies, where there is no place for democracy. That is why today liberalism and democracy have become less and less sup- portive of each other and often even more antagonistic. There seems to be a disturbing parallel between the struggle for deco- lonialisation with its mixed results and negative effects of the current (at least before the COVID-19 hit the world) wave of globalisation. Those who fought against colonial imperialism in Africa or elsewhere were considered and revered as freedom-fighters, though it would be more correct to qualify them as independence-fighters since the end result was usually independen- ce form colonial masters and not at all freedom for the people. Many of 22 Devecchio, A., op. cit., p. 1798. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 26. 15 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... such leaders of national liberation movements were populists and quite a few (e.g., Gamal Abdel Nasser, Fidel Castro and Robert Mugabe) of them ended up as genuine dictators. However, when they fought against imperial forces, they were seen by many, particularly in countries which they led to independence, as real heroes. They were fighting against colonialism as a specific form of previous centuries globalisation. Today’s western populists are considered by cosmopolitan elites (and not only by those in their own countries since one of the characteristics of current western elites is that they are generally cosmopolitan) to be narrow-minded, inward-looking protectio- nists, at best, or xenophobic nationalists, at worst. Yet, aren’t the effects of the forces, today’s populists are against, similar or sometimes even identical to the forces that the anticolonial freedom-fighters were struggling against. Globalisation, global markets, particularly financial markets, deprive peoples of any say on their future. These impersonal forces that have become un- controllable make democratic decision-making meaningless. These are not only masses of people in small or underdeveloped countries, who become voiceless. Therefore, populists can be seen as freedom fighters against exces- ses of globalisation, against the rules established, say, by GAFAs, pharma- ceutical companies, military-industrial and military-intellectual complexes23 or governments which they control or influence. This tendency exists almost everywhere. Only small groups of those belonging to cosmopolitan elites be- nefit from surfing on the waves of globalisation, though quite a few of them also fall and drown in the process. One of the few, but significant exceptions in that respect may be China, where the central authorities have retained and even strengthened, with the coming to power president Xi Jinping, con- trol over processes globalisation, but China has its own problems. Globalisation and the current migration tide, as one of its manifesta- tions, are exacerbating today’s crisis of the European Union, where those who can be anywhere do not understand those who want to be somewhere. The first category, being dominant in politics, economy and media, are beha- ving like liberal autocrats vis-à-vis those whom they consider belonging to the mob. Such myopic arrogance carries a heavy political price-tag. Without resolving this contradiction between the aspiration of European peoples to be somewhere (to feel at home in France, in Germany, in Italy, in Estonia, in Hungary) and ambitions of transnational elites to be anywhere, Europe will not come out unscathed from the current crisis. Populists are accused of dividing societies with their criticism of demo- cratically elected governments and by-passing traditional media, which has 23 See, Conesa, Pierre, Vendre la guerre: Le complexe militaro-intellectuel, De l’Aube, 2022. Whe- re he analyses the role of intellectuals and think-tanks in paving the road to armed conflicts. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 27. 16 REIN MÜLLERSON been and remain generally supportive of authorities, being critical only of some aspects or excesses of the authorities. But this is confusing the cause and the effect. The populist parties and leaders have become prominent namely because Western societies have become more and more unequal and divided. There is quite a lot of truth in the accusations from both si- des —from the side of self-declared progressists as well as from the side of those whom their critics call populists. In a way and simplifying a bit, both Brexit and Trump’s victory have been triumphs of populism over elitism (or if you like, democracy over liberalism). Personally, I don’t like Boris Johnson because of his rude manners and being too often, even for a politician, eco- nomical with the truth; as an estonian national living in London with his fa- mily, who are all estonian passport holders, I don’t like Brexit either. Yet, this doesn’t mean that I cannot see genuine concerns of Brexiteers. As canadian essayist Mathieu Bock-Coté writes, “there are, no doubt, among populist po- liticians extreme rights who nurture crazy and repulsive ideas, but it would be wrong to confuse ideological obsessions of such politicians and those real issues that form the basis of a significant part of the electorate and public concerns that have been censured by the dominant ideology”.24 These are the faults of so-called mainstream political parties, be they of centre-right or centre-left, which have neglected these real issues. Populist leaders can exploit only what is exploitable. Populist parties of movements may face setbacks in coming elections and their popularity ratings may suffer. However, the phenomenon is not going away, as its sources persist. Moreover, so-called mainstream parties are more and more using populist slogans and policies. The clearest example of this tendency is the metamorphoses of the British Tories, who under Boris Jo- hnson were not any more a traditional conservative party, as we had known it. Having used some traditional Labour Party precepts and slogans as well as Nigel Farage’s Brexit Party ideas, luring voters from both of them, the Tories have become a populist party —partly left-wing, partly right-wing. VI. “Illiberal Democracy”, “Undemocratic Liberalism” and “Liberal Imperialism” After Fareed Zakaria published, a quarter of a century ago, an article on “illi- beral democracy”,25 the term, reflecting various degrees of reality, has become 24 Bock-Coté, M., Le Multiculturalisme comme Religion Politique, Cerf, 2019, pp. 291-292. 25 Zakaria, F., “The Rise of Illiberal Democracy”, Foreign Affairs, november-december 1997. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 28. 17 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... firmly anchored in both academic as well as in political discourse. Agreeing with Zakaria that there are democracies where liberal values are not in high esteem, I have always wonded whether the reverse can be also true? Could there exist political regimes that may be defined as liberal but undemocratic? Of course, there have been authoritarian regimes that have been economi- cally liberal, but socially conservative, like Chile under General Pinochet or South Korea under military rulers. However, in Western democracies these two sides of liberalism —economics and social affairs— have been, more or less, like the two sides of the same coin. If in illiberal democracy it is democracy that trumps liberalism, under undemocratic liberalism it is liberalism that has the upper hand and puts constraints on democracy. And my answer is that there can be, and in prac- tice there are, political regimes that may be defined as “liberal”, but which have serious deficit of democracy. Undemocratic liberalism could be defined as a political regime, where out of the triptych —the government of the people, by the people and for the people— only the first still fully stands, i.e. where the participation of the people in the governance is both formal and ineffective and where the governance is exercised not in the interest of the majority of the people. Leaving aside societies where there is neither democracy nor liberalism, like Saudi Arabia or North Korea, and concen- trating attention on societies where these phenomena —democracy and libe- ralism— have existed for some time and still exist, it seems that many, if not most, Western societies have been infested with the germ of “undemocratic liberalism”. While liberal ideas are prevalent among European elites, values of democracy are today often expressed by populist parties and movements. There is a lot of truth in Chantal Delsol’s observation that “the he populists, contrary to what some may say, are really democrats, but they are not libe- rals. At the same time, universalist elites, like those in Brussels, are really liberals, who are not any more democrats since they don’t like when people vote to limit some liberties”.26 Using sanctions against “illiberal democra- cies”, be they members of the EU, like Hungary or Poland, or beyond, “un- democratic liberals” (the prime example of them being the European Union itself) are imposing their will and vision (values) on those who from their point of view are on the wrong side of history. Therefore, there exists not only undemocratic (or authoritarian) libera- lism, but we are also facing the rise of liberal imperialism, euphemistically described as “liberal international order”, giving additional impetus to the rise of nationalistic populism. Liberal imperialism, i.e. attempts to impose liberal values, either by persuasion or by force, as universal values to all and 26 Delsol, C., “Populiste, c’est un adjectif pour injurier ses adversaires”, Le Figaro Vox, 2018. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 29. 18 REIN MÜLLERSON everybody, is a wake-up call for those for whom, say, collectivistic values, historical traditions, stability or national independence are more, or at least not less, important than individual liberties. Many influential liberal authors, be they philosophers or economists, have been campaigners for liberal im- perial order. Friedrich Hayek, one of the most important theoreticians of liberalism of the last century, believed that the idea of interstate federation would be “the consistent development of liberal point of view”,27 while Lud- wig von Mises advocated the end of nation-states and creation of a “world super-state”.28 In an interesting, though controversial (often these two adjectives are necessarily interlinked), book Israeli author Yoram Hazony writes that when the struggle against communism ended …the Western minds became preoccupied with two great imperialist pro- jects: the European Union, which has progressively relieved member nations of many of the powers usually associated with political independence; and the project of establishing an American “world order”, in which nations that do not abide by international law will be coerced into doing so, principally by means of American military might. These are imperialist projects, even though their proponents do not like to call them like that.29 In defence of international law it should be said that it is not this rather noble normative system, which willy-nilly worked even during the Cold War, that Washington tries to impose by its military might and financial domi- nation, but so-called “rules-based liberal international order”, i.e. the order based on rules determined in Washington that has nothing to do with inter- national law. And it is not accidental that the only aspiring global empire is accusing those opposing its imperial ambitions, especially China and Russia, of building, or restoring, their own empires. It would be unfair, in my opinion, to accuse the European Union of being an imperial project, though one may agree that promising (and acting on this promise) to create an “ever-closer union”, a kind of federal Europe, European political elites gradually became more and more detached from the aspirations of their peoples. It is becoming increasingly obvious that Eu- ropean societies, in contradistinction to political elites, are not (not yet, at least) ready to throw the nation-state into the dustbin of history. Both the liberal lefts and the conservative rights have become concerned about their 27 Hayek, F., The Economic Conditions of Interstate Federalism, available at: https://fee.org/arti cles/the-economic-conditions-of-interstate-federalism. 28 Mises, L. von, Liberalism in the Classical Tradition, Cobden Press, 1985, p. 150. 29 Hazony, Y., The Virtue of Nationalism, Basic Books, 2018, pp. 3 and 4. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 30. 19 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... identity. However, if the first try to find their identity in the belongingness to a multitude of small, often marginalized, groups (depending on sexual orien- tation, specific interests or ways of life), the second usually try to find or restore their affinity within bigger communities, like nations, nation-states or traditional religions. However, even if the EU in itself is not an imperial project, the ongoing war of the collective West against Russia —the war that dare not speak its name— after the Kremlin’s reckless invasion of Ukraine, shows that the European Union has become a part of the American imperial project. Moreover, joining against their own best interest Washington’s anti- Chinese policies, European nations have lost the remnants of independent decision-making in world politics. Therefore, Yoram Hazony is right when asserting that: ...[f]or all their bickering, proponents of the liberal construction are united in endorsing a single imperialist vision: They wish to see a world in which liberal principles are codified as universal law and imposed on the nations, if necessary by force. This, they agree, is what will bring us universal peace and prosperity.30 VII. Is “e pluribus unum” indeed Replacing “ex uno plures”? The motto E Pluribus Unum, written on the US dollar in Latin, reads in plain English: “out of many-one”. It symbolises not only the union between the thirteen states forming in 1776 a Federation, but also the melting pot idea of the American political system, aimed at making the Americans out of various migrants of European, mostly Anglo-Saxon, extraction. Now, two and a half centuries later, Washington is in the vanguard of spreading American way of life, including the melting pot experience, all over the world. The greenback itself has been since the end of WWII the reserve currency of the world ser- ving as an instrument of American domination. Attempts by Russia, China and some other nations, who suffer or potentially may suffer from Ameri- can “sanctions”, to dedollarise the world economy and thereby undermining the foundations of American dominance, is one of the underlying causes of Washington’s efforts to aggressively push back Russia and contain China. However, tens of thousands of years before anybody used Latin, or any other known language for that matter, another, an opposite process had be- gun that could be called “out of one-many” (ex uno plures). It began (allegedly, 30 Ibidem, p. 45. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 31. 20 REIN MÜLLERSON since new discoveries may further change the dates and locations) more than 50 000 years ago when the Homo Sapiens started his journey from an East African village to all over the world. During that pilgrimage, our forefathers and foremothers, who at the beginning of this migration obviously did not differ much from each other as to the colour of their skin, slant of their eyes or the ways in which they communicated between themselves, acquired visi- ble physical and profound cultural differences, though remaining members of the same species of Homo Sapiens. This process of the colonisation of the planet Earth, during which “out of one emerged many”, was slow; it took tens of thousands of years until foot-and fingerprints of Homo Sapiens could be found in all hospitable, and today even inhospitable, places on Ear- th. Being always genetically very similar, humans became visibly (superficia- lly), depending mostly of their physical environment, rather different (some blue-eyed, others dark-eyed, some tall while others much shorter and so on). However, in contradistinction to these superficial (therefore easily visible) di- fferences, groups of Homo Sapiens, gradually forming tribes, ethnic groups, nations and civilisations, became profoundly different from each other in terms of their cultures, religions, mores and languages spoken. As Ameri- can philosopher Michael Walzer once aptly put it: “[e]very human society is universal because it is human, particular because it is a society”.31 Cultural differences between peoples, be they historical, religious or ethical, that may or may not be immediately visible, over the millennia became huge and they still remain profound. As physical or biological beings we are rather similar, as social animals we may be worlds apart. American social psychologist Jonathan Haidt has persuasively demons- trated that even in today’s world there still coexist at least three different categories of societies: those with the ethics of autonomy, those with the ethics of community and those with the ethics of divinity. In the first cate- gory, the individual with her wants, needs and preferences runs prime; in the second, concepts such as duty, hierarchy, respect, reputation and patriotism are predominant, while in the third prevails the idea that people are, first and foremost, only temporary vessels within which a divine soul has been im- planted.32 Professor Haidt concludes his essay with a warning against moral monists: “[b]eware of anyone who insists that there is one true morality for all people, times, and places —particularly if that morality is founded upon 31 Walzer, M., Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad, University of Notre Dame Press, 1994, p. 8. 32 Haidt, J., The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion, Penguin, 2013, p. 116. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 32. 21 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... a single moral foundation”.33 However, notwithstanding such learned voices and warnings, there have been, and still are, those who in their provincial ig- norance of the complexities and societal differences existing in the world try not only to unify the world but also make it uniform, be it, say, communist, liberal democratic or Muslim. Such worldviews have their roots in the Judeo- Christian and Enlightenment’s belief in a universal history and in constant progress leading inexorably towards some specific goal where history ends. Those who don’t recognise this truth, it is argued, are “on the wrong side of history”. If the communist experiment of the realisation of universal history has, at least for the time being, miserably failed, then liberal democratic pro- jects for the whole world are, notwithstanding all the red lights blinking here and there, still actively promoted. Even Islamists have joined the ranks of such “practical utopians” by their attempts to Islamise the globe, beginning with the Middle East. All these movements contain a mixture of determi- nism and voluntarism: the belief in an unavoidable unilineal course of his- tory (i.e. determinism) and, the burning desire to accelerate the coming of inevitable bright future in one or another form (i.e. voluntarism). One may, of course, reasonably argue that the process of global he- terogenisation, expressed in Ex Uno Plures, has by now if not come to an end then at least considerably slowed down. Indeed, there are many signs of global homogenisation, as articulated in the formula E Pluribus Unum. Within the general process of globalisation, we can distinguish global homo- genisation combined with the heterogenisation within individual societies, i.e. if societies become a bit more similar to each other, there is more diversity within most of them. To an extent, these are natural processes. It is to be ex- pected that different societies interacting, rubbing shoulders and borrowing from those with whom they interact, may become, at least in some respects, more similar to each other. It may indeed be that instead of Ex Uno Plures humankind has already begun a reverse journey towards E Pluribus Unum. However, the processes of heterogenisation that went on for tens of thou- sands of years, if not longer, cannot be undone within decades and probably even within centuries, if ever. Even if some individuals from different socie- ties can cross the boundaries of their cultural and ethical communities, to step, so to say, outside of their “moral matrix”, or sometimes even straddle and enjoy more than one of them, communities themselves change much more slowly, and changes that are instigated and forced on them, either from above or from the outside, may have lasting negative effects. Yet, there are those who seek to artificially accelerate the processes of global homogenisa- tion, using, inter alia, human rights discourse, exportation of democracy and 33 Ibidem, p. 368. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 33. 22 REIN MÜLLERSON liberal values, carrying out operations of regime change, sometimes using military force for that purpose. Such “one size fits all” policies foreseeably spread chaos and destruction instead of democracy and human rights. The much advertised and enthusiastically welcomed by the West “Arab spring” led to the collapse of statehood in Iraq, Libya, Syria and Yemen, while in other Middle East nations the authorities, to avoid likely implosion, returned to authoritarian rule (e.g., Egypt, Tunisia). Even admitting that the process of “out of one-many” has ended, and the tendency of “out of many-one” is manifesting itself in the processes of globalisation, it would be irresponsible to try to artificially accelerate this movement. Moreover, the end of history, be it either à la Karl Marx or à la Francis Fukuyama, would also be the end of social experimentation. The uniformity of social, economic or political systems would also mark the end of societal progress. Diversity between so- cieties is no less important than biodiversity or diversity within societies or- ganised as States. Moreover, the world is simply too big, complex and diverse to have its rich tapestry to be flattened into a carpet where only one pattern, be it a Judeo-Christian, Anglo-Saxon, Confucian, Muslim or even secular liberal-democratic, dominates. VIII. Bibliography Arendt, H., On Revolution, Penguin Books, 1965. Bernays, E. L., Propaganda, Routledge, 1928. Bock-coté, M., Le Multiculturalisme comme Religion Politique, Cerf, 2019. Chang, H. J., Bad Samaritans, Rich Nations, Poor Policies & the Threat to the Deve- loping World, Random House Business Books, 2007. Conesa, P., Vendre la guerre: Le complexe militaro-intellectuel, De l’Aube, 2022. Dahrendorf, R., “Acht Anmerkungen zum Populismus”, Transit-Europäische Revue, vol. 25, 2003. Delsol, C., “Populiste, c’est un adjectif pour injurier ses adversaires”, Le Figaro, Vox, 2018. Devecchio, A., Recomposition: Le nouveau monde populiste, Cerf, 2019. Dewey, J., The Public and its Problems in The Later Works of John Dewey 1925- 1953, Southern Illinois University Press, vol. 2, 1984. Dunn, J., Setting the People Free. The Story of Democracy, Atlantic Books, 2005. Goodhart, D., The Road to Somewhere: The New Tribes Shaping British Politics, Penguin, 2017. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 34. 23 QUO VADIS, HUMANITY? REFLECTIONS ON CONTEMPORARY... Guénolé, Thomas, La Mondialisation Malheureuse: Inégalité-pillage-oligarchie, First, 2016. Haidt, J., The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion, Penguin, 2013. Hayek, F., “The Economic Conditions of Interstate Federalism”, available at: https://fee.org/articles/the-economic-conditions-of-interstate-federalism. Hazony, Y., The Virtue of Nationalism, Basic Books, 2018. Lippmann, W., A Preface to Politics, New York, London, Mitchell Kennerley, 1914. Mounk, Y., The People vs. Democracy: Why our Freedom is in Danger and How to Save It, Harvard University Press, 2018. Müllerson, R., “Democracy Promotion: Institutions, International Law and Politics”, Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of International Law, vol. 333, 2008. Müllerson, R., “The Nation-State: Not Yet Ready for the Dustbin of His- tory?”, The Chinese Journal of International Law, vol. 20, núm. 4, Diciembre 2021. Popper, K., The Open Society and Its Enemies, Routledge, vol. 2: Hegel & Marx, 1996. Rodrik, D., “The inescapable trilemma of the world economy”, June 27, 2007, available at: https://rodrik.typepad.com/dani_rodriks_weblog/2007/06/ the-inescapable.html. Rorty, R., Achieving Our Country, Harvard University Press, 1997. Stiegler, B., Il faut s’adapter: sur un nouvel impératif politique, Paris, Gallimard, 2019. Von Mises, L., Liberalism in the Classical Tradition, Cobden Press, 1985. Walzer, M., Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad, University of Notre Dame Press, 1994. Zakaria, F., “The Rise of Illiberal Democracy”, Foreign Affairs, November- December, 1997. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 35. 25 THE PROVISION OF ARMS TO THE VICTIM OF ARMED AGGRESSION: THE CASE OF UKRAINE Stefan Talmon* Summary: I. Introduction. II. Providing Arms and Material to Ukraine. III. Provision of Arms and the Traditional Law of Neutrality. IV. Neutra- lity and the United Nations Charter. V. Provision of Arms and Collective Self-Defence. VI. Provision of Arms as a Countermeasure. VII. Inappli- Cability of the Law of Neutrality in Case of Aggression. VIII. Conclusion. IX. Bibliography. I. Introduction On 24 February 2022, the Russian Federation launched a full-scale invasion of Ukraine which amounted to a naked act of aggression.1 For my long-time friend and colleague Manuel Becerra Ramírez, like for any true friend of Rus- sia, this must have been a bleak day. For many years, Manuel has had a strong connection with Russia. He conducted his doctoral studies there in the early 1980s under the supervision of the world-renowned professor Grigory I. Tun- kin, and in 1985 he received his degree of doctor of philosophy in Interna- tional Law from the prestigious Lomonosov State University in Moscow after defending his thesis on Mexico and the New International Economic Order: Legal As- pects (in Russian). In 1989, Manuel translated professor Tunkin’s famous book on Law and Force in the International System from russian into spanish. Both legal questions concerning Russia and the former Soviet Union and questions on the legal and political aspects of the use of force have been recurring themes in Manuel’s academic work ever since. It is thus fitting to devote this short piece in his honour to a legal question resulting from Russia’s illegal invasion of Ukraine. * Director at the Institute for Public International Law, University of Bonn; Supernume- rary Fellow, St Anne’s College, Oxford; Barrister, Twenty Essex Chambers, London. 1 See, e.g., Green, James et al., “Russia’s Attack on Ukraine and the jus ad bellum”, Journal on the Use of Force and International Law, vol. 9, 2022. (Forthcoming) Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 36. 26 STEFAN TALMON II. Providing Arms and Material to Ukraine On the third day of Russia’s illegal war of aggression against Ukraine, the German Federal Government broke with a long-standing tenet of german security policy and announced that it would deliver 1,000 anti-tank weapons and 500 surface-to-air missiles, as well as 14 armoured vehicles and urgently needed fuel to Ukraine in order to support the country in its defence against the advancing russian troops.2 On the same day, it was also reported that the fede- ral government had granted export permits to the Netherlands and Estonia to send 400 german-made rocket-propelled grenade launchers and nine german howitzers to Ukraine, respectively. A few days later, the federal government decided to send another 2,700 anti-aircraft missiles to Ukraine.3 Several other western States also provided Ukraine with significant military assistance in its ongoing armed conflict with Russia.4 III. Provision of Arms and the Traditional Law of Neutrality The provision of arms to Ukraine has been considered a violation of the law of neutrality yet did not make Germany and the other States assisting Ukraine parties to the armed conflict.5 The law of neutrality regulates the relationship between States that are parties to an international armed conflict (belligerents) and States that are not (neutrals). The core of today’s customary internatio- nal law of neutrality was laid down in two of the 1907 Hague Conventions on the laws of war.6 The legal position of the neutral is characterized by the 2 McGuinness, Damien, “Germany to Send Weapons Directly to Ukraine”, BBC News, February 26, 2022, available at: https://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-60541752. 3 “Germany to Ship Anti-Aircraft Missiles to Ukraine”, Deutsche Welle, March 3rd, 2022, available at: https://p.dw.com/p/47vfZ. 4 See Duthois, Thomas, “Ukraine War: Which Countries are Sending Weapons and Aid to Forces Fighting the Russian Invasion?”, Euronews, March 4, 2022, available at: https://www. euronews.com/next/2022/03/04/ukraine-war-these-countries-are-sending-weapons-and-aid-to-forces- fighting-the-russian-inv. 5 See,e.g.,VonHartwig,Matthias,“WaffenlieferungenanddieUkraine:FührtDeutschland jetztKrieg?”,FrankfurterAllgemeineZeitungEinspruch,March1st.,2022,availableat:https://www.faz. net/einspruch/waffenlieferungen-an-die-ukraine-fuehrt-deutschland-jetzt-krieg-17843930.html; Krajewski, Markus, “Neither Neutral nor Party to the Conflict?: On the Legal Assessment of Arms Supp lies to Ukraine”, Völkerrechtsblog, March 9, 2022, doi: 10.17176/20220310-000928-0. 6 Convention (V) Regarding the Rights and Duties of Neutral Powers and Persons in Case of War on Land, 18 October 1907; Convention (XIII) Respecting the Rights and Du- Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 37. 27 THE PROVISION OF ARMS TO THE VICTIM OF ARMED... duties of abstention, impartiality, and prevention; that is, the neutral State must abstain from participating in the armed conflict, it must not discriminate between the belligerents, and it must prevent violations of its neutrality and its national territory by the belligerents. In particular, the law of neutrality prohi- bits neutrals from providing weapons, ammunition and other war material to the belligerents or supporting them in any other way, for example by providing militarily intelligence.7 Violations of these duties can be punished by a bellige- rent with countermeasures or armed reprisals and, ultimately, with treatment of the assisting State as a warring party. IV. Neutrality and the United Nations Charter With the founding of the United Nations (UN) in 1945, the hour of neutrality seemed to have come. Hans Kelsen pertinently observed that “the obligation of impartiality imposed by general international law upon neutral States is su- perseded by the Charter”.8 Under the system of collective security established by the UN Charter, the use of force was generally prohibited, and the Security Council was given primary responsibility for the maintenance of international peace and security. In case force was used in violation of the prohibition, the Security Council was to determine the aggressor and make recommendations or decide what measures should be taken to restore international peace and security.9 All members of the organization were to assist the United Nations in any action the Security Council decided to take against the aggressor.10 In June 1950, for example, the Security Council determined that “the armed attack on the Republic of Korea by forces from North Korea” cons- tituted “a breach of the peace”,11 and recommended that “the Members of the United Nations furnish such assistance to the Republic of Korea as may be necessary to repel the armed attack and to restore international peace ties of Neutral Powers in Naval Warfare, 18 October 1907, reproduced in (1908) 2 American Journal of International Law 117 and 202, respectively. 7 See, e.g., Bothe, Michael, “Neutrality, Concept and General Rules”, in Wolfrum, Rüdi- ger (ed.), Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012, vol. VII, pp. 617-634; at 624 MN 36. 8 Kelsen, Hans, Principles of International Law, New York, Rinehart & Company, 1952, pp. 87 and 88. 9 See Charter of the United Nations, UN Charter, 1945, Documents of the United Nations Conference on International Organization, vol. XV (1945) 335, Articles 2(4), 24, 39. On the UN Charter and the law of neutrality, see James Upcher, Neutrality in Contemporary International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020) 129-135. 10 UN Charter, Article 2(5). 11 UN Security Council resolution 82 (1950), June 25, 1950, UN Doc. S/1501. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 38. 28 STEFAN TALMON and security in the area”.12 When the military forces of Iraq invaded Kuwait in August 1990, the Security Council condemned the Iraqi invasion as “a breach of international peace and security”.13 Subsequently, the Security Council imposed sanctions on Iraq in order to induce it to withdraw its forces from Kuwait.14 However, the Council expressly made it clear that its deci- sions did not prohibit assistance to the legitimate government of Kuwait.15 In these cases, there was thus no room for impartiality towards the conflicting parties —the law of neutrality was not applicable. Such clear determinations of the aggressor, however, remained the ex- ception in the practice of the Security Council. The design of the UN Char- ter was flawed from the outset. As early as 1948, Philip C. Jessup identified, a “gap” in the United Nations’ collective security system.16 If one of the five permanent members of the Security Council committed an act of ag- gression or desired to block action, perhaps because of sympathy with the aggressor, that Council member could, by exercising its veto power, prevent the Council from designating the aggressor and taking any action to restore international peace and security. He wrote: ...[i]f the veto is exercised and action by the United Nations is thus blocked, completely or for a period of time, fighting between the parties may continue over a period of any duration permitted by the conditions of the contest and the contestants. During such a period, what is to be the legal position of third states and their nationals?”.17 In such circumstances, many international lawyers assumed that the tra- ditional law of neutrality would continue to apply.18 The flaw in the design of the UN Charter became evident again in the case of the russian invasion of Ukraine. On February 25, 2022, Russia ve- toed a draft resolution which had been supported by 82 States.19 In that re- solution the Security Council would have “deplore[d] in the strongest terms 12 UN Security Council resolution 83 (1950), June 27, 1950, UN Doc. S/1511. 13 UN Security Council resolution 660 (1990), August 2nd, 1990, UN Doc. S/RES/660 (1990), preambular para. 2. 14 UN Security Council resolution 661 (1990), August 6, 1990, UN Doc. S/RES/661 (1990), paras. 2-4. 15 Ibidem, para. 9. 16 Jessup, Philip C., A Modern Law of Nations, New York, Macmillan, 1948, p. 203. 17 Idem. 18 See, e.g., Bothe (n. 7) 619 MN 9. 19 See UN Security Council, 77th year, 8979th meeting, 25 February 2022, UN Doc. S/ PV.8979, p. 6. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 39. 29 THE PROVISION OF ARMS TO THE VICTIM OF ARMED... the Russian Federation’s aggression against Ukraine in violation of Article 2, paragraph 4 of the United Nations Charter” and would have “decide[d] that the Russian Federation shall immediately cease its use of force against Ukraine” and “shall immediately, completely, and unconditionally withdraw all of its military forces from the territory of Ukraine”.20 In the absence of any action by the Security Council, some commentators assumed that the law of neutrality was applicable and that it was being violated by the provi- sion of arms to Ukraine.21 This, however, is not the case as will be shown in the following sections. V. Provision of Arms and Collective Self-Defence Some authors have tried to justify the provision of arms to Ukraine as an exercise of the inherent right to collective self-defence under Article 51 of the UN Charter in response to russia’s armed attack on the country.22 It has been argued that, if States may take part in an armed conflict using their own armed forces to defend the victim of aggression, they must also be allowed to provide the victim with arms and munitions in order to enable it to defend itself. German government officials also seem to have alluded to collective self-defence when justifying the arms deliveries to Ukraine. In an interview broadcast on March 18, 2022, the Minister of State at the Federal Foreign Office stated: “[t]he arms deliveries are clearly legitimate in this situation. We have a war of aggression contrary to international law, and it is Ukraine’s right to defend itself and our right to help it defend itself. And that is covered by the UN Charter”.23 While this may be true in principle, the problem in the present case is that neither Germany nor any other State which provided arms to Ukraine formally invoked the right to collective self-defence. In particular, no State reported these arms deliveries to the Security Council. Article 51 of the UN 20 UN Security Council, Albania et al.: draft resolution, UN Doc. S/2022/155, 25 Fe- bruary 2022, paras. 2-4. 21 See, e.g., Hartwig, Matthias von, op. cit.; Krajewski, Markus, op. cit. 22 See, e.g., Ambos, Kai, “Will a State Supplying Weapons to Ukraine Become a Party to the Conflict and thus be Exposed to Countermeasures?”, EJIL: Talk!, March 2nd, 2022, https://www.ejiltalk.org/will-a-state-supplying-weapons-to-ukraine-become-a-party-to-the-conflict-and- thus-be-exposed-to-countermeasures/; Schmitt, Michael N., “Providing Arms and Material to Ukraine: Neutrality, Co-Belligerency, and the Use of Force”, Articles of War, March 7, 2022, available at: https://lieber.westpoint.edu/ukraine-neutrality-co-belligerency-use-of-force/. 23 Eschenhagen, Philipp et al., “Ukrainekrieg mit Katja Keul”, Völkerrechtsblog, March 18, 2022, DOI: 10.17176/20220318-120945-0. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas
  • 40. 30 STEFAN TALMON Charter, however, requires Member States to report immediately to the Se- curity Council any measures taken in the exercise of the right of self-defence. In contrast, following the armed terrorist attack on the United States on Sep- tember 11, 2001,24 and the armed attacks by the terrorist organization Islamic State on Iraq, France and other States, the German Federal Government had immediately informed the Security Council of the measures taken within the framework of collective self-defence.25 One reason why States did not invoke the right to collective self-defence might be that it would have made them “co-belligerents” of Ukraine in the latter’s armed conflict with Russia. For both legal and (internal) political reasons, the States supporting Ukraine wanted to avoid being seen as parties to the conflict. VI. Provision of Arms as a Countermeasure The provision of arms to Ukraine has also been justified as a “countermeasu- re” within the context of the law of State responsibility.26 An injured State may counter an internationally wrongful act by not performing for the time being its own international obligations toward the responsible State —here the obliga- tion of impartiality under the law of neutrality— in order to induce the latter to comply with its obligations under international law.27 Back in the 1950s, several authors had argued, for example, that by resorting to war in viola- tion of the General Treaty for the Renunciation of War (the “Kellogg-Briand Pact” or “Pact of Paris”),28 a State violated the rights of all other Contracting Parties. The latter were thereby entitled to take measures of “reprisal” against the aggressor that could involve a departure from the duty of impartiality otherwise imposed on non-participants of an armed conflict by the traditional law of neutrality.29 States which provided arms to the victim of aggression 24 See UN Security Council, Letter dated on 29 November 2001 from the Permanent Representative of Germany to the United Nations addressed to the President of the Security Council, UN Doc. S/2001/1127, November 29, 2001. 25 See UN Security Council, Letter dated on December 10, 2015 from the Chargé d’affaires a.i. of the Permanent Mission of Germany to the United Nations addressed to the President of the Security Council, S/2015/946, 10 December 2015. 26 See, e.g., Ambos (22). 27 See Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts (Articles on State Responsibility), adopted by the International Law Commission on August 3, 2001, ILC Yearbook 2001, vol. II/2, 26, Article 49. 28 General Treaty for the Renunciation of War as an Instrument of National Policy, done at Paris 27 August 1928, 94 LNTS 59. 29 See, e.g., Kelsen, Hans, Principles…, cit., p. 87; Kelsen, Hans, “Collective Security under International Law”, International Law Studies, vol. 49, 1954. Esta obra forma parte del acervo de la Biblioteca Jurídica Virtual del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM www.juridicas.unam.mx https://biblio.juridicas.unam.mx/bjv Libro completo en: http://tinyurl.com/yt3rbzwj DR © 2024. Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México-Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas